Maariage SEP
Maariage SEP
Marriage, a prominent institution regulating sex, reproduction, and family life, is a route into classical
philosophical issues such as the good and the scope of individual choice, as well as itself raising distinctive
philosophical questions. Political philosophers have taken the organization of sex and reproduction to be
essential to the health of the state, and moral philosophers have debated whether marriage has a special moral
status and relation to the human good. Philosophers have also disputed the underlying moral and legal rationales
for the structure of marriage, with implications for questions such as the content of its moral obligations and the
legal recognition of same-sex marriage. Feminist philosophers have seen marriage as playing a crucial role in
women’s oppression and thus a central topic of justice. In this area philosophy courts public debate: in 1940,
Bertrand Russell’s appointment to an academic post was withdrawn on the grounds that the liberal views
expressed in Marriage and Morals made him morally unfit for such a post. Likewise, debate over same-sex
marriage has been highly charged. Unlike some contemporary issues sparking such wide interest, there is a long
tradition of philosophical thought on marriage.
Philosophical debate concerning marriage extends to what marriage, fundamentally, is; therefore, Section 1
examines its definition. Section 2 sets out the historical development of the philosophy of marriage, which
shapes today’s debates. Many of the ethical positions on marriage can be understood as divided on the question
of whether marriage should be defined contractually by the spouses or by its institutional purpose, and they
further divide on whether that purpose necessarily includes procreation or may be limited to the marital love
relationship. Section 3 taxonomizes ethical views of marriage accordingly. Section 4 will examine rival political
understandings of marriage law and its rationale. Discussion of marriage has played a central role in feminist
philosophy; Section 5 will outline the foremost critiques of the institution.
1. Defining Marriage
2. Understanding Marriage: Historical Orientation
3. Marriage and Morals
3.1 Contractual Views
3.2 Institutional Views
4. The Politics of Marriage
4.1 Marriage and Legal Contract
4.2 The Rationale of Marriage Law
4.3 Same-Sex Marriage
4.4 Arguments for Marriage Reform
5. Marriage and Oppression: Gender, Race, and Class
5.1 Feminist Approaches
5.2 The Queer Critique
Bibliography
Contemporary Works
Historical Works
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries
1. Defining Marriage
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 1/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
‘Marriage’ can refer to a legal contract and civil status, a religious rite, and a social practice, all of which vary by
legal jurisdiction, religious doctrine, and culture. History shows considerable variation in marital practices:
polygyny has been widely practiced, some societies have approved of extra-marital sex and, arguably,
recognized same-sex marriages, and religious or civil officiation has not always been the norm (Boswell 1994;
Mohr 2005, 62; Coontz 2006). More fundamentally, while the contemporary Western ideal of marriage involves
a relationship of love, friendship, or companionship, marriage historically functioned primarily as an economic
and political unit used to create kinship bonds, control inheritance, and share resources and labor. Indeed, some
ancients and medievals discouraged ‘excessive’ love in marriage. The Western ‘love revolution’ in marriage
dates popularly to the 18th century (Coontz 2006, Part 3). The understanding of marriage as grounded in
individual choice and romantic love reflects historically and culturally situated beliefs and practices. Most
notably, the aspect of consent or voluntary entry - often taken to be crucial to marriage (Cott 2000) - is
challenged where practices of forced or child marriage are prevalent (Narayan 1997; Bhandary 2018). Arranged
marriage, which is compatible with the consent of the spouses, prioritizes caregiving and economic aspects of
the institution over romantic love (Bhandary 2018).
The global variety of marriage practices and law is difficult to encapsulate: notable variations in law include
recognition of same-sex marriage, polygamy, and ‘common-law’ marriage, restrictions on marriages between
members of the same family or of different social castes, the existence of civil marriage, practices of arranged,
forced, or child marriage, and women’s rights within marriage (see Moses 2018 for an entry into the literature on
these differences), as well as cultural and religious practices of temporary marriage (Shrage 2013, Nolan 2016)
or polyamorous marriage (Brake 2018). Religious, cultural, and philosophical traditions also shape ideals of
marriage. For instance, Xiaorong Li writes that “Confucian ideals of family, society, and women’s role”
influence expectations of marriage in China (Li 1995, 413). However, scholarship on such differences must be
careful to avoid misrepresentation (see for example discussion of misleading Western accounts of ‘sati’ and
dowry-murder in India in Narayan 1997).
Ethical and political questions regarding marriage are sometimes answered by appeal to the definition of
marriage. But the historical and cultural variation in marital practices has prompted some philosophers to argue
that marriage is a ‘family resemblance’ concept, with no essential purpose or structure (Wasserstrom 1974; see
also the interesting discussion of whether the many different practices identified by anthropologists as marriage
should be counted as marriages in Nolan, forthcoming). If marriage has no essential features, then one cannot
appeal to definition to justify particular legal or moral obligations. For instance, if monogamy is not an essential
feature of marriage, then one cannot appeal to the definition of marriage to justify a requirement that legal
marriage be monogamous. To a certain extent, the point that actual legal or social definitions cannot settle the
question of what features marriage should have is just. First, past applications of a term need not yield necessary
and sufficient criteria for applying it: ‘marriage’ (like ‘citizen’) may be extended to new cases without thereby
changing its meaning (Mercier 2001). Second, appeal to definition may be uninformative: for example, legal
definitions are sometimes circular, defining marriage in terms of spouses and spouses in terms of marriage
(Mohr 2005, 57). Third, appeal to an existing definition in the context of debate over what the law of marriage,
or its moral obligations, should be risks begging the question: in debate over same-sex marriage, for example,
appeal to the current legal definition begs the normative question of what the law should be. However, this point
also tells against the argument for the family resemblance view of marriage, as the variation of marital forms in
practice does not preclude the existence of a normatively ideal form. Thus, philosophers who defend an
essentialist definition of marriage offer normative definitions, which appeal to fundamental ethical or political
principles. Defining marriage must depend on, rather than precede, ethical and political inquiry.
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 2/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
In his depiction of the ideal state, Plato (427–347 BCE) described a form of marriage contrasting greatly with
actual marriage practices of his time. He argued that, just as male and female watchdogs perform the same
duties, men and women should work together, and, among Guardians, ‘wives and children [should be held] in
common’ (The Republic, ca. 375–370 BCE, 423e–424a). To orchestrate eugenic breeding, temporary marriages
would be made at festivals, where matches, apparently chosen by lot, would be secretly arranged by the Rulers.
Resulting offspring would be taken from biological parents and reared anonymously in nurseries. Plato’s reason
for this radical restructuring of marriage was to extend family sympathies from the nuclear family to the state
itself: the abolition of the private family was intended to discourage private interests at odds with the common
good and the strength of the state (ibid., 449a-466d; in Plato’s Laws, ca. 355–47 BCE, private marriage is
retained but still designed for public benefit).
Aristotle (384–322 BCE) sharply criticized this proposal as unworkable. On his view, Plato errs in assuming that
the natural love for one’s own family can be transferred to all fellow-citizens. The state arises from component
parts, beginning with the natural procreative union of male and female. It is thus a state of families rather than a
family state, and its dependence on the functioning of individual households makes marriage essential to
political theory (Politics, 1264b). The Aristotelian idea that the stability of society depends on the marital family
influenced Hegel, Rawls, and Sandel, among others. Aristotle also disagreed with Plato on gender roles in
marriage, and these views too would prove influential. Marriage, he argued, is properly structured by gender: the
husband, “fitter for command,” rules. The sexes express their excellences differently: “the courage of a man is
shown in commanding, of a woman in obeying,” a complementarity which promotes the marital good (Politics,
ca. 330 BCE, 1253b, 1259b, 1260a; Nicomachean Ethics, ca. 325 BCE, 1160–62).
In contrast to the ancients, whose philosophical discussion of sex and sexual love was not confined to marriage,
Christian philosophers introduced a new focus on marriage as the sole permissible context for sex, marking a
shift from viewing marriage as primarily a political and economic unit. St. Augustine (354–430), following St.
Paul, condemns sex outside marriage and lust within it. “[A]bstinence from all sexual union is better even than
marital intercourse performed for the sake of procreating,” and the unmarried state is best of all (The Excellence
of Marriage, ca. 401, §6, 13/15). But marriage is justified by its goods: “children, fidelity [between spouses],
and sacrament.” Although procreation is the purpose of marriage, marriage does not morally rehabilitate lust.
Instead, the reason for the individual marital sexual act determines its permissibility. Sex for the sake of
procreation is not sinful, and sex within marriage solely to satisfy lust is a pardonable (venial) sin. As marital sex
is preferable to “fornication” (extra-marital sex), spouses owe the “marriage debt” (sex) to protect against
temptation, thereby sustaining mutual fidelity (Marriage and Desire, Book I, ca. 418–19, §7, 8, 17/19, 14/16).
St. Thomas Aquinas (ca. 1225–1274) grounded concurring judgments about sexual morality in natural law,
explicating marriage in terms of basic human goods, including procreation and fidelity between spouses (Finnis
1997). Monogamous marriage, as the arrangement fit for the rearing of children, “belong[s] to the natural law.”
Monogamous marriage secures paternal guidance, which a child needs; fornication is thus a mortal sin because it
“tends to injure the life of the offspring.” (Aquinas rejects polygamy on similar grounds while, like Augustine,
arguing that it was once permitted to populate the earth.) Marital sex employs the body for its purpose of
preserving the species, and pleasure may be a divinely ordained part of this. Even within marriage, sex is
morally troubling because it involves “a loss of reason,” but this is compensated by the goods of marriage
(Summa Theologiae, unfinished at Aquinas’ death, II-II, 153, 2; 154, 2). Among these goods, Aquinas
emphasizes the mutual fidelity of the spouses, including payment of the “marriage debt” and “partnership of a
common life”—a step towards ideas of companionate marriage (Summa Theologiae, Supp. 49, 1).
Indeed, we see indications of discontent with the economic model of marriage a century earlier in the letters of
Héloïse (ca. 1100–1163) to Abelard (1079–1142). Héloïse attacks marriage, understood as an economic
transaction, arguing that a woman marrying for money or position deserves “wages, not gratitude” and would
“prostitute herself to a richer man, if she could.” In place of this economic relation she praises love, understood
on a Ciceronian model of friendship: the “name of wife may seem more sacred or more binding, but sweeter for
me will always be the word friend (amica), or, if you will permit me, that of concubine or whore” (Abelard and
Héloïse, Letters, ca. 1133–1138, 51–2). The relation between love and marriage will continue to preoccupy later
philosophers. Do marital obligations and economic incentives threaten love, as Héloïse suggested? (Cave 2003,
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 3/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Card 1996) As Søren Kierkegaard (1813–1855) dramatically suggests in The Seducer’s Diary, are the obligations
of marriage incompatible with romantic and erotic love? Or, instead, does marital commitment uniquely enable
spousal love, as Aquinas suggested? (Finnis 1997; cf. Kierkegaard’s Judge William’s defense of marriage
[Either/Or, 1843, vol. 2].)
Questions of the relation between love and marriage emerge from changing understandings of the role of
marriage; in the early modern era, further fault lines appear as new understandings of human society conflict
with the traditional structure of marriage. For Aristotle, Augustine, and Aquinas, marriage was unproblematically
structured by sexual difference, and its distinctive features explained by nature or sacrament. But in the early
modern era, as doctrines of equal rights and contract appeared, a new ideal of relationships between adults as
free choices between equals appeared. In this light, the unequal and unchosen content of the marriage
relationship raised philosophical problems. Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) acknowledged that his arguments for
rough equality among humans apply to women: “whereas some have attributed the dominion [over children] to
the man only, as being of the more excellent sex; they misreckon in it. For there is not always that difference of
strength, or prudence between the man and the woman, as that the right can be determined without war.”
Nonetheless, Hobbes admits that men dominate in marriage, which he explains (inadequately) thus: “for the
most part commonwealths have been erected by the fathers, not by the mothers of families” (Leviathan, 1651,
Ch. 20; Okin 1979, 198–199, Pateman 1988, 44–50).
Likewise, defending marital hierarchy posed a problem for John Locke (1632–1704). Locke ties his rejection of
political patriarchy to a rejection of the patriarchal family, arguing that marriage, like the state, rests on consent,
not natural hierarchy; marriage is a “voluntary compact.” But Locke fails to follow this reasoning consistently,
for Lockean marriage remains hierarchical: in cases of conflict, “the rule … naturally falls to the man’s as the
abler and stronger.” Ceding decision-making power to one party on the basis of a presumed natural hierarchy
creates an internal tension in Locke’s views (The Second Treatise of Government, 1690, §77, 81, 82; Okin 1979,
199–200). This inconsistency prompted Mary Astell’s (1666–1731) response: “If all Men are born free, how is it
that all women are born slaves? as they must be if the being subjected to the inconstant, uncertain, unknown,
arbitrary Will of Men, be the perfect Condition of Slavery?” (“Reflections upon Marriage,” 1700, 18) Similar
tensions arise for Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778), whose treatise on education, Émile, describes the
unequal status of Émile’s wife, Sophie. Her education, a template for all women’s, prepares her only to please
and serve her husband and rear children. Mary Wollstonecraft (1759–1798) attacked Rousseau’s views on
women’s nature, education, and marital inequality in A Vindication of the Rights of Woman (see also Okin 1979,
Chapter 6).
The contractual understanding of marriage prompts the question as to why marital obligations should be fixed
other than by spousal agreement. Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) combined a contractual account of marriage with
an Augustinian preoccupation with sexual morality to argue that the distinctive content of the marriage contract
was required to make sex permissible. In Kant’s view, sex involves morally problematic objectification, or
treatment of oneself and other as a mere means. The marriage right, a “right to a person akin to a right to a
thing,” gives spouses “lifelong possession of each other’s sexual attributes,” a transaction supposed to render sex
compatible with respect for humanity: “while one person is acquired by the other as if it were a thing, the one
who is acquired acquires the other in turn; for in this way each reclaims itself and restores its personality.” But
while these rights, according to Kant, make sex compatible with justice, married sex is not clearly virtuous
unless procreation is a possibility (Metaphysics of Morals, 1797–98, Ak 6:277–79, 6:424–427). Kant’s account
of sexual objectification has had wide influence—from feminists to new natural lawyers. More surprisingly,
given his views on gender inequality and the wrongness of same-sex sexual activity, Kant’s account of marriage
has been sympathetically reconstructed by feminists and defenders of same-sex marriage drawn by Kant’s focus
on equality, reciprocity, and the moral rehabilitation of sex within marriage (Herman 1993, Altman 2010,
Papadaki 2010). Kant interestingly suggests that morally problematic relationships can be reconstructed through
equal juridical rights, but how such reconstruction occurs is puzzling (Herman 1993, Brake 2005). Among other
things, it is difficult to see how Kant’s insistence on equal marriage rights can be reconciled with his views on
gender inequality (Sticker 2020).
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 4/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Characteristically, G. W. F. Hegel’s (1770–1831) account of marriage synthesizes the preceding themes. Hegel
returns to Aristotle’s understanding of (nuclear) marriage as the foundation of a healthy state, while explicating
its contribution in terms of spousal love. Hegel criticized Kant’s reduction of marriage to contract as
“disgraceful” because spouses begin “from the point of view of contract—i.e. that of individual personality as a
self-sufficient unit—in order to supersede it.” They “consent to constitute a single person and to give up their
natural and individual personalities within this union.” The essence of marriage is ethical love, “the
consciousness of this union as a substantial end, and hence in love, trust, and the sharing of the whole of
individual existence.” Ethical love is not, like sexual love, contingent: “Marriage should not be disrupted by
passion, for the latter is subordinate to it” (Elements of the Philosophy of Right, 1821, §162–63, 163A).
Like his predecessors, Hegel must justify the distinctive features of marriage, and in particular, why, if it is the
ethical love relationship which is ethically significant, formal marriage is necessary. Hegel’s contemporary
Friedrich von Schlegel had argued that love can exist outside marriage—a point which Hegel denounced as the
argument of a seducer! For Hegel, ethical love depends on publicly assuming spousal roles which define
individuals as members in a larger unit. Such unselfish membership links marriage and the state. Marriage plays
an important role in Hegel’s system of right, which culminates in ethical life, the customs and institutions of
society: family, civil society, and the state. The role of marriage is to prepare men to relate to other citizens as
sharers in a common enterprise. In taking family relationships as conditions for good citizenship, Hegel follows
Aristotle and influences Rawls and Sandel; it is also notable that he takes marriage as a microcosm of the state.
Kant and Hegel attempted to show that the distinctive features of marriage could be explained and justified by
foundational normative principles. In contrast, early feminists argued that marital hierarchy was simply an unjust
remnant of a pre-modern era. John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) argued that women’s subordination within marriage
originated in physical force—an anomalous holdover of the ‘law of the strongest’. Like Wollstonecraft in her
1792 A Vindication of the Rights of Woman, Mill compared marriage and slavery: under coverture wives had no
legal rights, little remedy for abuse, and, worse, were required to live in intimacy with their ‘masters’. This
example of an inequality based on force had persisted so long, Mill argued, because all men had an interest in
retaining it. Mill challenged the contractual view that entry into marriage was fully voluntary for women,
pointing out that their options were so limited that marriage was “only Hobson’s choice, ‘that or none’” (The
Subjection of Women, 1869, 29). He also challenged the view that women’s nature justified marital inequality: in
light of different socialization of girls and boys, there was no way to tell what woman’s nature really was. Like
Wollstonecraft, Mill described the ideal marital relationship as one of equal friendship (Abbey and Den Uyl,
2001). Such marriages would be “schools of justice” for children, teaching them to treat others as equals. But
marital inequality was a school of injustice, teaching boys unearned privilege and corrupting future citizens. The
comparison of marriage with slavery has been taken up by more recent feminists (Cronan 1973), as has the
argument that marital injustice creates unjust citizens (Okin 1994).
Marxists also saw marriage as originating in ancient exercises of force and as continuing to contribute to the
exploitation of women. Friedrich Engels (1820–1895) argued that monogamous marriage issued from a “world
historical defeat of the female sex” (Engels 1884, 120). Exclusive monogamy “was not in any way the fruit of
individual sex love, with which it had nothing whatever to do … [but was based on] economic conditions—on
the victory of private property over primitive, natural communal property” (ibid., 128). Monogamy allowed men
to control women and reproduction, thereby facilitating the intergenerational transfer of private property by
producing undisputed heirs. Karl Marx (1818–83) argued that abolishing the private family would liberate
women from male ownership, ending their status “as mere instruments of production” (The Communist
Manifesto, Marx 1848, 173). The Marxist linking of patriarchy and capitalism, in particular its understanding of
marriage as an ownership relation ideologically underpinning the capitalist order, has been especially influential
in feminist thought (Pateman 1988, cf. McMurtry 1972).
choice. The contractual view of marriage implies that spouses can choose marital obligations to suit their
interests. However, to some, the value of marriage consists precisely in the limitations it sets on individual
choice in the service of a greater good: thus, Hegel commented that arranged marriage is the most ethical form
of marriage because it subordinates personal choice to the institution. The institutional view holds that the
purpose of the institution defines its obligations, taking precedence over spouses’ desires, either in the service of
a procreative union or to protect spousal love, in the two most prominent forms of this view. These theories have
implications for the moral status of extra-marital sex and divorce, as well as the purpose of marriage.
One rationale for treating marital obligations as such promises might be thought to be the voluntaristic account
of obligation. On this view, all special obligations (as opposed to general duties) are the result of voluntary
undertakings; promises are then the paradigm of special obligations (see entry on Special Obligations). Thus,
whatever special obligations spouses have to one another must originate in voluntary agreement, best understood
as promise. We will return to this below. A second rationale is the assumption that existing marriage practices are
morally arbitrary, in the sense that there is no special moral reason for their structure. Further, there are diverse
social understandings of marriage. If the choice between them is morally arbitrary, there is no moral reason for
spouses to adopt one specific set of marital obligations; it is up to spouses to choose their terms. Thus, the
contractual account depends upon the assumption that there is no decisive moral reason for a particular marital
structure.
On the contractual account, not just any contracts count as marriages. The default content of marital promises is
supplied by social and legal practice: sexual exclusivity, staying married, and so on. But it entails that spouses
may release one another from these moral obligations. For example, extra-marital sex has often been construed
as morally wrong by virtue of promise-breaking: if spouses promise sexual exclusivity, extra-marital sex breaks
a promise and is thereby prima facie wrong. However, if marital obligations are simply promises between the
spouses, then the parties can release one another, making consensual extra-marital sex permissible (Wasserstrom
1974). Marriage is also sometimes taken to involve a promise to stay married. This seems to make unilateral
divorce morally problematic, as promisors cannot release themselves from promissory obligations (Morse 2006).
But standard conditions for overriding promissory obligations, such as conflict with more stringent moral duties,
inability to perform, or default by the other party to a reciprocal promise would permit at least some unilateral
divorces (Houlgate 2005, Chapter 12). Some theorists of marriage have suggested that marital promises are
conditional on enduring love or fulfilling sex (Marquis 2005, Moller 2003). But this assumption is at odds with
the normal assumption that promissory conditions are to be stated explicitly.
Release from the marriage promise is not the only condition for permissible divorce on the contractual view.
Spouses may not be obligated to one another to stay married—but they may have parental duties to do so: if
divorce causes avoidable harm to children, it is prima facie wrong (Houlgate 2005, Chapter 12, Russell 1929,
Chapter 16). However, in some cases divorce will benefit the child—as when it is the means to escape abuse. A
vast empirical literature disputes the likely effects of divorce on children (Galston 1991, 283–288, Young 1995).
What is notable here, philosophically, is that this moral reason against divorce is not conceived as a spousal, but
a parental, duty.
Marriage is widely taken to have an amatory core, suggesting that a further marital promise is a promise to love,
as expressed in wedding vows ‘to love and cherish’. But the possibility of such promises has met with
skepticism. If one cannot control whether one loves, the maxim that ‘ought implies can’ entails that one cannot
promise to love. One line of response has been to suggest that marriage involves a promise not to feel but to
behave a certain way—to act in ways likely to sustain the relationship. But such reinterpretations of the marital
promise face a problem: promises depend on what promisors intend to promise—and presumably most spouses
do not intend to promise mere behavior (Martin 1993, Landau 2004, Wilson 1989, Mendus 1984, Brake 2012,
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 6/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Chapter 1; see also Kronqvist 2011). However, developing neuroenhancement technology promises to bring love
under control through “love drugs” which would produce bonding hormones such as oxytocin. While the use of
neuroenhancement to keep one’s vows raises questions about authenticity and the nature of love (as well as
concerns regarding its use in abusive relationships), it is difficult to see how such technology morally differs
from other love-sustaining devices such as romantic dinners—except that it is more likely to be effective
(Savulescu and Sandberg 2008).
One objection to the contractual account is that, without appeal to the purpose of the institution, there is no
reason why not just any set of promises count as marriage (Finnis 2008). The objection continues that the
contractual account cannot explain the point of marriage. Some marriage contractualists accept this implication.
According to the “bachelor’s argument,” marriage is irrational: chances of a strongly dis-preferred outcome (a
loveless marriage) are too high (Moller 2003). Defenders of the rationality of marriage have replied that marital
obligations are rational because they help agents to secure their long-term interests in the face of passing desires
(Landau 2004). From the institutional perspective, evaluating the rationality of marriage thus, in terms of
fulfilling subjective preferences, clashes with the tradition of viewing it as uniquely enabling certain objective
human goods; however, a positive case must be made for the latter view.
Another objection to the contractual view concerns voluntarism. Critics of the voluntarist approach to the family
deny that family morality is exhausted by voluntary obligations (Sommers 1989). Voluntarist conceptions of the
family conflict with common-sense intuitions that there are unchosen special duties between family members,
such as filial duties. However, even if voluntarism is false, this does not suffice to establish special spousal
duties. On the other hand, voluntarism alone does not entail the contractual view, for it does not entail that
spouses can negotiate the obligations of marriage or that the obligations be subject to release, only that spouses
must agree to them. Voluntarism, in other words, need not extend to the choice of marital obligations and hence
need not entail the contractual account. The contractual account depends on denying that there is decisive moral
reason for marriage to incorporate certain fixed obligations. Let us turn to the case that there is such reason.
Like Kant, the new natural law account of marriage focuses on the permissible exercise of sexual attributes;
following Aquinas, it emphasizes the goods of marriage, which new natural lawyers, notably John Finnis (cf.
George 2000, Grisez 1993, Lee 2008), identify as reproduction and fides—roughly, marital friendship (see entry
on The Natural Law Tradition in Ethics). Marriage is here taken to be the institution uniquely apt for conceiving
and rearing children by securing the participation of both parents in an ongoing union. The thought is that there
is a distinctive marital good related to sexual capacities, consisting in procreation and fides, and realizable only
in marriage. Within marriage, sex may be engaged in for the sake of the marital good. Marital sex need not result
in conception to be permissible; it is enough that it is open towards procreation and expresses fides. The view
does not entail that it is wrong to take pleasure in sex, for this can be part of the marital good.
However, sex outside marriage (as defined here) cannot be orientated toward the marital good. Furthermore,
sexual activity not orientated toward this good—including same-sex activity, masturbation, contracepted sex, sex
without marital commitment (even within legal marriage)—is valueless; it does not instantiate any basic good.
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 7/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Furthermore, such activity is impermissible because it violates the basic good of marriage. Marital sex is thought
to instantiate the good of marriage. By contrast, non-marital sex is thought to treat sexual capacities
instrumentally—using them merely for pleasure. (It is here that the account is influenced by Kant.) Non-marital
sex violates the good of marriage by treating sexual capacities in a way contrary to that good. Furthermore, for
an agent merely to condone non-marital sex damages his or her relation to the marital good, for even a
hypothetical willingness to treat sex instrumentally precludes proper marital commitment (Finnis 1997, 120).
As Finnis emphasizes, one feature of the new natural law account of marriage is that the structure of marriage
can be fully explained by its purpose. Marriage is between one man and one woman because this is the unit able
to procreate without third-party assistance; permanence is required to give children a lifelong family. Finnis
charges, as noted above, that accounts which do not ground marriage in this purpose have no theoretical reason
to resist the extension of marriage to polygamy, incest, and bestiality (Finnis 1995). As all non-marital sex fails
to instantiate basic goods, there is no way morally to distinguish these different relations.
A further point concerns law: to guide citizens’ judgments and choices towards the relationship in which they
can uniquely achieve the marital good, the state should endorse marriage, as understood on this view, and not
recognize same-sex relationships as marriages. However, it might be asked whether this is an effective way to
guide choice, and whether state resources might be better spent promoting other basic human goods. Moreover,
as the argument equally implies a state interest in discouraging contraception, divorce, and extra-marital sex, the
focus on same-sex marriage appears arbitrary (Garrett 2008, Macedo 1995). This objection is a specific instance
of a more general objection: this account treats sex and the marital good differently than it does the other basic
human goods. Not only is less attention paid to promoting those goods legally (and discouraging behavior
contrary to them), but the moral principle forbidding action contrary to basic human goods is not consistently
applied elsewhere—for example, to eating unhealthily (Garrett 2008).
A second objection attacks the claim that non-marital sex cannot instantiate any basic human goods. This
implausibly consigns all non-marital sex (including all contracepted sex) to the same value as anonymous sex,
prostitution, or masturbation (Macedo 1995, 282). Plausibly, non-marital sex can instantiate goods such as
“pleasure, communication, emotional growth, personal stability, long-term fulfillment” (Corvino 2005, 512), or
other basic human goods identified by the new natural law account, such as knowledge, play, and friendship
(Garrett 2008; see also Blankschaen 2020).
A third objection is related. The view seems to involve a double standard in permitting infertile opposite-sex
couples to marry (Corvino 2005; Macedo 1995). The new natural lawyers have responded that penile-vaginal sex
is reproductive in type, even if not in effect, while same-sex activity can never be reproductive in type (Finnis
1997, cf. George 2000, Lee 2008). Reproductive-type sex can be oriented towards procreation even if not
procreative in effect. But it is unclear how individuals who know themselves to be infertile can have sex for the
reason of procreation (Macedo 1995, Buccola 2005). Ultimately, to differentiate infertile heterosexual couples
from same-sex couples, new natural lawyers invoke complementarity between men and women as partners and
parents. Thus, the defense of this account of marriage turns on a controversial view of the nature and importance
of sexual difference (Finnis 1997, Lee 2008).
A related, influential argument focuses on the definition of marriage. This argues that marriage is necessarily
between one man and one woman because it involves a comprehensive union between spouses, a unity of lives,
minds, and bodies. Organic bodily union requires being united for a biological purpose, in a procreative-type act
(Girgis, et al., 2010). Like the new natural law arguments, this has raised questions as to why only, and all,
different-sex couples, even infertile ones, can partake in procreative-type acts, and why bodily union has special
significance (Arroyo 2018, Johnson 2013).
While much discussion of new natural law accounts of marriage oscillates between attacking and defending the
basis in biological sex difference, some theorists sympathetic to new natural law attempt to avoid the Scylla of
rigid biological restrictions and the Charybdis of liberal “plasticity” regarding marriage (Goldstein 2011).
Goldstein, for one, offers an account of marriage as a project generated by the basic good of friendship; while
this project includes procreation as a core feature, the institution of marriage has, on this account, a
compensatory power, meaning that the institution itself can compensate for failures such as inability to procreate.
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 8/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Such an account grounds marriage in the new natural law account of flourishing, but it also allows the extension
to same-sex marriage without, according to Goldstein, permitting other forms such as polygamy.
A second widespread (though less unified) institutional approach to marriage appeals to the ideal marital love
relationship to define the structure of marriage. This approach, in the work of different philosophers, yields a
variety of specific prescriptions, on, for example, whether marital love (or committed romantic love in general)
requires sexual difference or sexual exclusivity (Scruton 1986, 305–311, Chapter 11, Halwani 2003, 226–242,
Chartier 2016). Some, but not all, proponents explicitly argue that the marital love relationship is an objective
good (Scruton 1986, Chapter 11, 356–361, Martin 1993). These views, however, all take the essential feature,
and purpose, of marriage to be protecting a sexual love relationship. The thought is that marriage helps to
maintain and support a relationship either in itself valuable, or at least valued by the parties to it.
On this approach, the structure of marriage derives from the behavior needed to maintain such a relationship.
Thus marriage involves a commitment to act for the relationship as well as to exclude incompatible options—
although there is controversy over what specific policies these general commitments entail. To take an
uncontroversial example, marriage creates obligations to perform acts which sustain love, such as focusing on
the beloved’s good qualities (Landau 2004). More controversially, some philosophers argue that sustaining a
love relationship requires sexual exclusivity. The thought is that sexual activity generates intimacy and affection,
and that objects of affection and intimacy will likely come into competition, threatening the marital relationship.
Another version focuses on the emotional harm, and consequent damage to the relationship, caused by sexual
jealousy. Thus, due to the psychological conditions required to maintain romantic love, marriage, as a love-
protecting institution, generates obligations to sexual exclusivity (Martin 1993, Martin 1994, Scruton 1986,
Chapter 11, 356–361, Steinbock 1986). However, philosophers dispute the psychological conditions needed to
maintain romantic love. Some argue that casual extra-marital sex need not create competing relationships or
trigger jealousy (Halwani 2003, 235; Wasserstrom 1974). Indeed, some have even argued that extra-marital sex,
or greater social tolerance thereof, could strengthen otherwise difficult marriages (Russell 1929, Chapter 16),
and some polyamorists (those who engage in multiple sex or love relationships) claim that polyamory allows
greater honesty and openness than exclusivity (Emens 2004). Other philosophers have treated sexual fidelity as
something of a red herring, shifting focus to other qualities of an ideal relationship such as attentiveness,
warmth, and honesty, or a commitment to justice in the relationship (Martin 1993, Kleingeld 1998).
Views understanding marriage as protecting love generate diverse conclusions regarding its obligations. But
such views share two crucial assumptions: that marriage has a role to play in creating a commitment to a love
relationship, and that such commitments may be efficacious in protecting love (Cave 2003, Landau 2004, Martin
1993, Martin 1994, Mendus 1984, Scruton 1986, 356–361). However, both of these assumptions may be
questioned. First, even if commitment can protect a love relationship, why must such a commitment be made
through a formal marriage? If it is possible to maintain a long-term romantic relationship outside marriage, the
question as to the point of marriage re-emerges: do we really need marriage for love? May not the legal and
social supports of marriage, indeed, trap individuals in a loveless marriage or themselves corrode love by
associating it with obligation? (Card 1996, Cave 2003; see also Gheaus 2016) Second, can commitment, within
or without marriage, really protect romantic love? High divorce rates would seem to suggest not. Of course, even
if, as discussed in 3.1, agents cannot control whether they love, they can make a commitment to act in ways
protective of love (Landau 2004, Mendus 1984). But this returns us the difficulty, suggested by the preceding
paragraph, of knowing how to protect love!
Reflecting the difficulty of generating specific rules to protect love, many such views have understood the
ethical content of marriage in terms of virtues (Steinbock 1991, Scruton 1986, Chapter 11, 356–361). The virtue
approach analyzes marriage in terms of the dispositions it cultivates, an approach which, by its reference to
emotional states, promises to explain the relevance of marriage to love. However, such approaches must explain
how marriage fosters virtues (Brake 2012). Some virtue accounts cite the effects of its social status: marriage
triggers social reactions which secure spousal privacy and ward off the disruptive attention of outsiders (Scruton
1986, 356–361). Its legal obligations, too, can be understood as Ulysses contracts[1]: they protect relationships
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 9/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
when spontaneous affection wavers, securing agents’ long-term commitments against passing desires. Whether
or not such explanations ultimately show that marital status and obligations can play a role in protecting love, the
general focus on ideal marital love relationships may be characterized as overly idealistic when contrasted with
problems in actual marriages, such as spousal abuse (Card 1996). This last point suggests that moral analysis of
marriage cannot be entirely separated from political and social inquiry.
Proponents of the contractualization, or privatization, of marriage have argued that marriage should be brought
further into line with the contractual paradigm. A default assumption for some liberals, as for libertarians, is that
competent adults should be legally permitted to choose the terms of their interaction. In a society characterized
by freedom of contract, restrictions on entry to or exit from marriage, or the content of its legal obligations,
appear to be an illiberal anomaly. Full contractualization would imply that there should be no law of marriage at
all—marriage officiation would be left to religions or private organizations, with the state enforcing whatever
private contracts individuals make and otherwise not interfering (Vanderheiden 1999, Sunstein and Thaler 2008,
Chartier 2016; for a critique of contractualization, see Chambers 2016). The many legal implications of marriage
for benefit entitlements, inheritance, taxation, and so on, can also be seen as a form of state interference in
private choice. By conferring these benefits, as well as merely recognizing marriage as a legal status, the state
encourages the relationships thereby formalized (Waldron 1988–89, 1149–1152).[2]
Marriage is the basis for legal discrimination in a number of contexts; such discrimination requires justification,
as does the resource allocation involved in providing marital benefits (Cave 2004, Vanderheiden 1999). In the
absence of such justification, providing benefits through marriage may treat the unmarried unjustly, as their
exclusion from such benefits would then be arbitrary (Card 1996). Thus, there is an onus to provide a rationale
justifying such resource allocations and legal discrimination on the basis of marriage, as well as for restricting
marriage in ways that other contracts are not restricted.
Before exploring some common rationales, it is worth noting that critics of the social contract model of the state
and of freedom of contract have used the example of marriage against contractual principles. First, Marxists
have argued that freedom of contract is compatible with exploitation and oppression—and Marxist feminists
have taken marriage as a special example, arguing against contractualizing it on these grounds (Pateman 1988,
162–188). Such points, as we will see, suggest the need for rules governing property division on divorce.
Second, communitarians have argued that contractual relations are inferior to those characterized by trust and
affection—again, using marriage as a special example (Sandel 1982, 31–35, cf. Hegel 1821, §75, §161A). This
objection applies not only to contractualizing marriage, but more generally, to treating it as a case for application
of principles of justice: the concern is that a rights-based perspective will undermine the morally superior
affection between family members, importing considerations of individual desert which alienate family members
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 10/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
from their previous unselfish identification with the whole (Sandel 1982, 31–35). However, although marriages
are not merely an exchange of rights, spousal rights protect spouses’ interests when affection fails; given the
existence of abuse and economic inequality within marriage, these rights are especially important for protecting
individuals within, and after, marriage (Kleingeld 1998, Shanley 2004, 3–30, Waldron 1988).
A first reason for recognizing marriage should be set aside. This is that the monogamous heterosexual family
unit is a natural, pre-political structure which the state must respect in the form in which it finds it (Morse 2006;
cf. new natural lawyers, Girgis et al. 2010). But, whatever the natural reproductive unit may be, marriage law, as
legislation, is constrained by principles of justice constraining legislation. Within most contemporary political
philosophy, the naturalness of a given practice is irrelevant; indeed, in no area other than the family is it
proposed that law should follow nature (with the possible exception of laws regarding suicide). Finally, such
objections must answer to feminist concerns that excluding the family unit from principles of justice, allowing
natural affection to regulate it, has facilitated inequality and abuse within it (see section 5).
Let us then begin with the question of why marriage should be recognized in law at all. One answer is that legal
recognition conveys the state’s endorsement, guiding individuals into a valuable form of life (George 2000). A
second is that legal recognition is necessary to maintain and protect social support for the institution, a valuable
form of life which would otherwise erode (Raz 1986, 162, 392–3; Scruton 1986, 356–361; see discussion in
Waldron 1988–89). But this prompts the question as to why this form of life is valuable.
It is sometimes argued that traditions, having stood the test of time, have proved their value. Not only is marriage
itself such a tradition, but through its child-rearing role it can pass on other traditions (Sommers 1989, Scruton
1986, 356–361, cf. Devlin 1965, Chapter 4). But many marital traditions—coverture, gender-structured legal
duties, marital rape exemptions, inter-racial marriage bans—have been unjust. Tradition provides at best a prima
facie reason for legislation which may be overridden by considerations of justice. Further, in a diverse society,
there are many competing traditions, amongst which this rationale fails to choose (Garrett 2008).
An account of the value of a particular form of marriage itself (and not just qua tradition) is needed. One thought
is that monogamous marriage encourages the sexual self-control needed for health and happiness; another is that
it encourages the goods of love and intimacy found in committed relationships. State support for monogamous
marriage, by providing incentives to enter marital commitments, thus helps people lead better lives (e.g. Macedo
1995, 286). However, this approach faces objections. First, the explanation in terms of emotional goods
underdetermines the institution to be supported: other relationships, such as friendships, embody emotional
goods. Second, claims about the value of sexual self-control are controversial; objectors might argue that
polygamy, polyamory, or promiscuity are equally good options (see 5.2). There is a further problem with this
justification, which speaks to a division within liberal thought. Some liberals embrace neutrality, the view that
the state should not base law on controversial judgments about what constitutes valuable living. To such neutral
liberals, this class of rationales, which appeal to controversial value judgments about sex and love, must be
excluded (Rawls 1997, 779). Some theorists have sought to develop rationales consistent with political
liberalism, arguing, for instance, that the intimate dyadic marital relationship protects autonomy (Bennett 2003),
or that some form of marriage could be justified by its efficiency in providing benefits (Toop 2019) or its role in
protecting diverse caring relationships (Brake 2012), fragile romantic love relationships (Cave 2017), or
caregivers and children (Hartley and Watson 2012, Toop 2019; see also May 2016, Wedgwood 2016).
It is widely accepted that the state should protect children. If two-parent families benefit children, incentives to
marry may be justified as promoting two-parent families and hence children’s welfare. One benefit of two-parent
families is economic: there is a correlation between single motherhood and poverty. Another benefit is
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 11/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
emotional: children appear to benefit from having two parents (Galston 1991, 283–288). (Moreover, some argue
that gender complementarity in parenting benefits children; but empirical evidence does not seem to support this
[Lee 2008, Nussbaum 1999, 205, Manning et al., 2014].)
One objection to this line of argument is that marriage is an ineffective child anti-poverty plan. For one thing,
this account assumes that incentives to marry will lead a significant number of parents who would not otherwise
have married to marry. But marriage and child-rearing have increasingly diverged despite incentives to marry.
Second, this approach does not address the many children outside marriages and in poor two-parent families.
Child poverty could be addressed more efficiently through direct anti-child-poverty programs rather than the
indirect strategy of marriage (Cave 2004; Vanderheiden 1999; Young 1995). Moreover, there is controversy over
the psychological effects of single parenthood, particularly over the causality underlying certain correlations: for
instance, are children of divorce unhappier due to divorce itself, or to the high-conflict marriage preceding it?
(Young 1995) Indeed, some authors have recently argued that children might be better protected by legally
separating marriage from parenting: freestanding parenting frameworks would be more durable than marriage
(which can end in divorce), would protect children outside of marriages, and would accommodate new family
forms such as three-parent families (Brennan and Cameron 2016, Shrage 2018; see also Chan and Cutas 2012).
A related, but distinct, line of thought invokes the alleged psychological effects of two-parent families to argue
that marriage benefits society by promoting good citizenship and state stability (Galston 1991, 283–288). This
depends on the empirical case (as we have seen, a contested one) that children of single parents face
psychological and economic hurdles which threaten their capacity to acquire the virtues of citizenship.
Moreover, if economic dependence produces power inequality within marriage, then Mill’s ‘school of injustice’
objection applies—an institution teaching injustice is likely to undermine the virtues of citizenship (Okin 1994,
Young 1995).
Finally, a rationale for restricting the terms of exit from marriage (but not for supporting it as a form of life) is
the protection of women and children following divorce. Women in gender-structured marriages, particularly if
they have children, tend to become economically vulnerable. Statistically, married women are more likely than
their husbands to work in less well-paid part-time work, or to give up paid work entirely, especially to meet the
demands of child-rearing. Thus, following divorce, women are likely to have a reduced standard of living, even
to enter poverty. Because these patterns of choice within marriages lead to inequalities between men and women,
property division on divorce is a matter of equality or equal opportunity, and so a just law of divorce is essential
to gender justice (Okin 1989, Chapters 7 and 8; Rawls 1997, 787–794; Shanley 2004, 3–30; Waldron 1988, and
see 5.1). However, it can still be asked why a law recognizing marriage as such should be necessary, as opposed
to default rules governing property distribution when such gender-structured relationships end (Sunstein and
Thaler 2008, Chambers 2017). Indeed, placing these restrictions only on marriage, as opposed to enacting
general default rules, may make marriage less attractive, especially to men, and hence be counter-productive,
leaving women more vulnerable.
The preceding two rationales are both weakened by the diminished social role of marriage; changing legal and
social norms undermine its effectiveness as a policy tool. In the 20th century, marriage was beset by a “perfect
storm”: the expectation that it should be emotionally fulfilling, women’s liberation, and effective contraception
(Coontz 2006, Chapter 16). Legally, exit from marriage has become relatively easy since the ‘no-fault divorce
revolution’ of the 1970’s. Moreover, cohabitation and child-rearing increasingly take place outside marriage.
This reflects the end of laws against unmarried cohabitation and legal discrimination against children on grounds
of ‘illegitimacy’, as well as diminishing social stigmas against such behavior. Given such significant changes,
marriage is at best an indirect strategy for achieving goals such as protecting women or children (Cave 2004,
Sunstein and Thaler 2008, Vanderheiden 1999).
Some theorists have argued, in the absence of a compelling rationale for marriage law, for abolishing marriage
altogether, replacing it with civil unions or domestic partnerships. This line of thought will be taken up in 4.4,
after an examination of the debate over same-sex marriage.
Many arguments for same-sex marriage invoke liberal principles of justice such as equal treatment, equal
opportunity, and neutrality. Where same-sex marriage is not recognized in law, marriage provides benefits which
are denied to same-sex couples on the basis of their orientation; if the function of marriage is the legal
recognition of loving, or “voluntary intimate,” relationships, the exclusion of same-sex relationships appears
arbitrary and unjustly discriminatory (Wellington 1995, 13). Same-sex relationships are relevantly similar to
different-sex relationships recognized as marriages, yet the state denies gays and lesbians access to the benefits
of marriage, hence treating them unequally (Mohr 2005, Rajczi 2008, Williams 2011). Further, arguments in
support of such discrimination seem to depend on controversial moral claims regarding homosexuality of the
sort excluded by neutrality (Wellington 1995, Schaff 2004, Wedgwood 1999, Arroyo 2018).
A political compromise (sometimes proposed in same-sex marriage debates) of restricting marriage to different-
sex couples and offering civil unions or domestic partnerships to same-sex couples does not fully answer the
arguments for same-sex marriage. To see why such a two-tier solution fails to address the arguments grounded in
equal treatment, we must consider what benefits marriage provides. There are tangible benefits such as eligibility
for health insurance and pensions, privacy rights, immigration eligibility, and hospital visiting rights (see Mohr
2005, Chapter 3), which could be provided through an alternate status. Crucially, however, there is also the
important benefit of legal, and indirectly social, recognition of a relationship as marriage. The status of marriage
itself confers legitimacy and invokes social support. A two-tier system would not provide equal treatment
because it does not confer on same-sex relationships the status associated with marriage.
In addition, some philosophers have argued that excluding gays and lesbians from marriage is central to gay and
lesbian oppression, making them ‘second-class citizens’ and underlying social discrimination against them.
Marriage is central to concepts of good citizenship, and so exclusion from it displaces gays and lesbians from
full and equal citizenship: “being fit for marriage is intimately bound up with our cultural conception of what it
means to be a citizen … because marriage is culturally conceived as playing a uniquely foundational role in
sustaining civil society” (Calhoun 2000, 108). From this perspective, the ‘separate-but-equal’ category of civil
unions retains the harmful legal symbol of inferiority (Card 2007, Mohr 2005, 89, Calhoun 2000, Chapter 5; cf.
Stivers and Valls 2007; for a comprehensive survey of these issues, see Macedo 2015).
However, if marriage is essentially different-sex, excluding same-sex couples is not unequal treatment; same-sex
relationships simply do not qualify as marriages. One case that marriage is essentially different-sex invokes
linguistic definition: marriage is by definition different-sex, just as a bachelor is by definition an unmarried man
(Stainton, cited in Mercier 2001). But this confuses meaning and reference. Past applications of a term need not
yield necessary and sufficient criteria for applying it: ‘marriage’, like ‘citizen’, may be extended to new cases
without thereby changing its meaning (Mercier 2001). As noted above, appeal to past definition begs the
question of what the legal definition should be (Stivers and Valls 2007).
A normative argument for that marriage is essentially different-sex appeals to its purpose: reproduction in a
naturally procreative unit (see 3.2.a). But marriage does not require that spouses be able to procreate naturally, or
that they intend to do so at all. Further, married couples adopt and reproduce using donated gametes, rather than
procreating ‘naturally’. Nor do proponents of this objection to same-sex marriage generally suggest that entry to
marriage should be restricted by excluding those unable to procreate without third-party assistance, or not
intending to do so.
Indeed, as the existence of intentionally childless married couples suggests, marriage has purposes other than
child-rearing—notably, fostering a committed relationship (Mohr 2005, Wellington 1995, Wedgwood 1999).
This point suggests a second defense of same-sex marriage: exclusive marital commitments are goods which the
state should promote amongst same-sex as well as opposite-sex couples (Macedo 1995). As noted above, such
rationales come into tension with liberal neutrality; further controversy regarding them will be discussed below
(5.2).
Some arguments against same-sex marriage invoke a precautionary principle urging that changes which might
affect child welfare be made with extreme caution. But in light of the data available, Murphy argues that the
precautionary principle has been met with regard to harm to children. On his view, parenting is a basic civil
right, the restriction of which requires the threat of a certain amount of harm. But social science literature shows
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 13/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
that children are neither typically nor seriously harmed by same-sex parenting (see Manning et al., 2014). Even
if two biological parents statistically provide the optimal parenting situation, optimality is too high a standard for
permitting parenting. This can be seen if an optimality condition is imagined for other factors, such as education
or wealth (Murphy 2011).
A third objection made to same-sex marriage is that its proponents have no principled reason to oppose legally
recognizing polygamy (e.g. Finnis 1997; see Corvino 2005). One response differentiates the two by citing
harmful effects and unequal status for women found in male-headed polygyny, but not in same-sex marriage
(e.g. Wedgwood 1999, Crookston 2014, de Marneffe 2016, Macedo 2015). Another response is to bite the bullet:
a liberal state should not choose amongst the various ways (compatible with justice) individuals wish to organize
sex and intimacy. Thus, the state should recognize a diversity of marital relationships—including polygamy
(Calhoun 2005, Mahoney 2008) or else privatize marriage, relegating it to private contract without special legal
recognition or definition (Baltzly 2012).
Finally, some arguments against same-sex marriage rely on judgments that same-sex sexual activity is
impermissible. As noted above, the soundness of these arguments aside, neutrality and political liberalism
exclude appeal to such contested moral views in justifying law in important matters (Rawls 1997, 779, Schaff
2004, Wedgwood 1999, Arroyo 2018). However, some arguments against same-sex marriage have invoked
neutrality, on the grounds that legalizing same-sex marriage would force some citizens to tolerate what they find
morally abhorrent (Jordan 1995, and see Beckwith 2013). But this reasoning seems to imply, absurdly, that
mixed-race marriage, where that is the subject of controversy, should not be legalized. A rights claim to equal
treatment (if such a claim can support same-sex marriage) trumps offense caused to those who disagree; the state
is not required to be neutral in matters of justice (Beyer 2002; Boonin 1999; Schaff 2004; see also Barry 2011,
Walker 2015).
There are several reform proposals compatible with the ‘disestablishment’ of marriage. One proposal is full
contractualization or privatization, leaving marriage to churches and private organizations. “Marital
contractualism” (MC) would relegate spousal agreements to existing contract law, eradicating any special legal
marital status or rights. Garrett has defended MC as the default position, arguing that state regulation of contracts
between spouses and state expenditures on marriage administration and promotion need justification. On his
view, efficiency, equality, diversity, and informed consent favor MC; there is no adequate justification for the
costly redistribution of taxpayer funds to the married, or for sustaining social stigma against the unmarried
through legal marriage (Garrett 2009, see also Chartier 2016).
But marriage confers rights not available through private contract and which arguably should not be eliminated
due to their importance in protecting intimate relationships—such as evidentiary privilege or special eligibility
for immigration. A second proposal would retain such rights while abolishing marriage; on this proposal, the
state ought to replace civil marriage entirely with a secular status such as civil union or domestic partnership,
which could serve the purpose of identifying significant others for benefit entitlements, visiting rights, and so on
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 14/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
(March 2010, 2011). This would allow equal treatment of same-sex relationships while reducing controversy,
avoiding non-neutrality, and respecting the autonomy of religious organizations by not compelling them to
recognize same-sex marriage (Sunstein and Thaler 2008). However, neither solution resolves the conflict
between religious autonomy and equality for same-sex relationships. Privatization does not solve this conflict so
long as religious organizations are involved in civil society—for example, as employers or benefit providers. The
question is whether religious autonomy would allow them, in such roles, to exclude same-sex civil unions from
benefits. Such exclusion could be defended as a matter of religious autonomy; but it could also be objected to as
unjust discrimination—as it would be if, for example, equal treatment were denied to inter-racial marriages.
Another issue raised by such a reform proposal is how to delimit the relationships entitled to such recognition.
Recall the new natural law charge that liberalism entails an objectionable “plasticicty” regarding marriage
(3.2.1). One question is whether recognition should be extended to polygamous or polyamorous relationships.
Some defenders of same-sex marriage hold that their arguments do not entail recognizing polygamy, due to its
oppressive effects on women (Wedgwood 1999). However, some monogamous marriages are also oppressive
(March 2011), and egalitarian polygamous or polyamorous relationships, such as a group of three women or
three men, exist (Emens 2004). Thus, oppressiveness does not cleanly distinguish monogamous from
polygamous relationships. Brooks has sought to show that polygamy is distinctively structurally inegalitarian as
one party (usually the husband) can determine who will join the marriage, whereas wives cannot (Brooks 2009).
However, this overlooks various possible configurations—if a polygamous “sister wife,” for instance, has the
legal right to marry outside the existing marriage, there is no structural inequality (Strauss 2012). Most
fundamentally, some authors have urged that a politically liberal state should not prescribe the arrangements in
which its competent adult members seek love, sex, and intimacy, so long as they are compatible with justice
(Calhoun 2005, March 2011). Some philosophers have argued that polygamists and polyamorous people are
unjustly excluded from the benefits of marriage, and that legal recognition of plural marriage - or small groups
of friends – can preserve equality (Brake 2012, 2014, Den Otter 2015, Shrage 2016). Finally, the history of
racialized stigmatization of polygamy gives reason to consider whether anti-polygamous intuitions rest on just
foundations (Denike 2010).
Conservatives also charge that the liberal approach cannot rule out incestuous marriage. While this topic has
sparked less debate than polygamy, one defender of the civil-unions-for-all proposal has pointed out that civil
union status, as justified on politically liberal grounds, would not connote sexual or romantic involvement. Thus,
eligibility of adult family members for this status would not convey state endorsement of incest; whether the
state should prohibit or discourage incest is an independent question (March 2010).
A further problem arises with the proposal to replace marriage with civil unions on neutrality grounds. Civil
unions, if they carry legal benefits similar to marriage, would still involve legal discrimination (between
members of civil unions and those who were not members) requiring justification (for a specific example of this
problem in the area of immigration law, see Ferracioli 2016). Depending on how restrictive the entry criteria for
civil unions were (for example, whether more than two parties, blood relations, and those not romantically
involved could enter) and how extensive the entitlements conferred by such unions were, the state would need to
provide reason for this discrimination. In the absence of compelling neutral reasons for such differential
treatment, liberty considerations suggest the state should cease providing any special benefits to members of
civil unions (or intimate relationships) (Vanderheiden 1999, cf. Sunstein and Thaler 2008). As noted in 4.2, some
political liberals have sought to provide rationales showing why a liberal state should support certain
relationships; these rationales generate corresponding reform proposals. One approach focuses on protecting
economically dependent caregivers; Metz proposes replacing civil marriage with “intimate care-giving unions”
which would protect the rights of dependent caregivers (Metz 2010; cf. Hartley and Watson 2012). Another
approach holds that caring relationships themselves - whether friendships or romantic relationships - should be
recognized as valuable by the politically liberal state, and it should, accordingly, distribute rights supporting
them equally; the corresponding reform proposal, “minimal marriage,” would provide rights directly supporting
relationships, but not economic benefits, without restriction as to sex or number of parties or the nature of their
caring relationship (Brake 2012). This would extend marriage not only to polyamorists, but to asexuals and
aromantics, as well as those who choose to build their lives around friendships. A third approach proposes that
marital rights and status be replaced by “piecemeal directives” which would regulate the various functional
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 15/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
contexts to which marriage law now applies (such as cohabitation and co-parenting) (Chambers 2017); this
proposal would avoid designating any relationship type as entitled to special treatment.
Many of the views discussed to this point imply that current marriage law is unjust because it arbitrarily
excludes some groups from benefits; it follows, on such views, that marrying is to avail oneself of privileges
unjustly extended. This seems to give reason for boycotting the institution, so long as some class of persons is
unjustly excluded (Parsons 2008).
Before Obergefell, U.S. law was in patchwork regarding marriages involving at least one transgender person —
“trans—marriage,” in Loren Cannon’s term. As a transgender person traveled from state to state, both their legal
sex and marital status could change (Cannon 2009, 85). While some raised concerns that the political rationales
given for recognizing such marriages (such as the possibility of penile-vaginal intercourse) reaffirmed
heteronormative assumptions (Robson 2007), to other theorists, the possibility of trans-marriage itself suggests
the instability or incoherence of legal gender categories and gendered restrictions on marriage (Cannon 2009,
Almeida 2012).
While Mill and Engels saw the establishment of monogamous marriage as an ancient defeat of the female sex,
Aquinas, Kant, and many others have seen monogamy as a victory for women, securing for them faithful
partners, protection, and material support. So Kant writes that “skepticism on this topic [marriage] is bound to
have bad consequences for the whole feminine sex, because this sex would be degraded to a mere means for
satisfying the desire of the other sex, which, however, can easily result in boredom and unfaithfulness.—Woman
becomes free by marriage; man loses his freedom by it” (Kant 1798, 210–211, [309]). However, as a historical
thesis about the origin of marriage, the idea that monogamy provided women with needed material support has
been debunked. In early hunting-gathering societies, female foraging likely provided more than male hunting,
child-care was arranged communally, and, rather than a single male providing for his female partner, survival
required a much larger group (Coontz 2006, 37–38). As a thesis about the protection of women by their male
partners, the incidence of rape and violence by male partners themselves must be taken into account (e.g., in the
contemporary U.S., Tjaden and Thoennes 2000). And as a thesis about sex difference, evolutionary ‘just-so’
stories purporting to show that women are naturally more monogamous have been challenged by feminist
philosophers of biology (Tuana 2004).
Marriage law has also been a tool of racial oppression. The majority of American states at one time prohibited
inter-racial marriage; the Supreme Court struck down such laws in 1967 (Wallenstein 2002, 253–254). Anti-
miscegenation law did not prevent actual sex and procreation between races, but it excluded women of color and
their children from the benefits of marriage. It was also a potent symbol of alleged racial difference.
Furthermore, African-American marriage patterns were shaped by slavery. Enslaved persons could not legally
marry, and slave couples and their children were frequently separated (Cott 2000). Contemporary philosophers
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 16/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
of race argue that marriage is still implicated in systemic racism (Collins 1998). For example, historical
conditions and structural racism have led to practices of shared child-rearing in some African-American
communities. Some theories of marriage imply that such child-rearing practices are inferior to the marital family.
Theorists of racial oppression argue that such practices should be recognized as a valuable alternative, and,
moreover, that law which excludes such practices from benefits accorded to marriage may be racially unjust
(Vanderheiden 1999; cf. Collins 1998, Card 1996). Immigration law has also made women who are dependent
on marriage for their immigration status vulnerable to abuse, particularly those women who are also subject to
racism or cultural marginalization (Narayan 1995).
Recent work has also highlighted the contemporary class-based marriage gap in the U.S.: wealthier people are
more likely to marry (McClain 2013). This suggests a different link between marriage and oppression: one effect
of socioeconomic inequality may be to deprive the worse-off of access to marriage (perhaps because poverty
impedes the formation of stable relationships) and the further legal benefits marriage can bring. There is
arguably a tension, among egalitarian approaches, between feminist criticisms of marriage as inherently
oppressive and egalitarian criticisms of barriers to accessing it (Chambers 2013).
As noted above, one persistent rationale for excluding the family from norms of justice is that its natural
relations of affection and trust are superior to merely just relations and likely to be threatened by construing the
family in terms of justice (Hegel 1821, §75, §161A; Sandel 1982, 31–35). But abuse within marriage and
inequality on dissolution are significant problems, the gravity of which should, according to critics, outweigh
these finer virtues; rights within marriage protect spouses when affection fails (Waldron 1988, Okin 1989).
Moreover, it is not clear that affection and justice must conflict; a commitment to treating one’s spouse justly
could be part of marital love (Kleingeld 1998). Finally, marriage is part of the basic structure of society, and
thus, at least within Rawlsian liberalism, is subject to principles of justice. This does not determine, however,
how principles of justice should constrain marriage; the default liberal presumption is that marriage, as a
voluntary association, should be ordered as spouses choose—so long as these choices do not lead to injustice
(Rawls 1997, 792). We will return to this below.
Marriage is a focus of feminist concern due to its effects on women’s life chances. Continuing disadvantage
accruing to women in marriage has been widely documented, and in some feminist analyses, undergirds gender
inequality (rival accounts place greater emphasis on sexual objectification or workplace discrimination). Wives,
even those who work full-time outside the home, perform more housework than husbands—this ‘second shift’
affecting their workplace competitiveness. The social assignment of primary responsibility for childcare to
women, combined with the difficulty of combining childcare with paid work, also undermine the workplace
competitiveness of women with children (Okin 1989, Chapter 7). The gendered division of labor and the fact
that ‘women’s work’ is less well-paid than men’s together make it more likely that married women, rather than
their husbands, will downgrade their careers, choose part-time work, or stay home to facilitate child-rearing or
when the spouses’ careers conflict. These choices make women “vulnerable by marriage”: economic
dependence, and dependence on marriage for benefits such as health insurance, fosters power inequality and
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 17/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
makes exit difficult, in turn facilitating abuse (Okin 1989, Chapter 7, Narayan 1995, Card 1996, Brake 2016,
Ferguson 2016).
As discussed in 4.2, rationales of equality or equal opportunity are given for addressing economic inequalities
arising within marriage through divorce law (Okin 1989, Chapters 7 and 8; Shanley 2004, 3–30, Rawls 1997,
787–794). However, divorce law does not address non-economic sources of power imbalances (such as gender
role socialization) within on-going marriages, nor does it address the systemic way in which such inequalities
arise. Equal opportunity seems to require changing social norms related to marriage in ways which divorce law
does not. First, the gendered division of labor within ongoing marriages is costly for women (Kleingeld 1998).
Second, power imbalances within marriage limit girls’ expectations and teach children to accept gendered
inequality (Okin 1989, Chapter 7, Okin 1994). Third, anticipation of marriage affects women’s investment in
their earning ability before marriage (Okin 1989, Chapter 7). (But for an argument that some hierarchy and
inequality in marriage is just, see Landau 2012.)
Such social norms could be addressed through education or through media campaigns promoting the equitable
division of housework. Legal measures such as requiring all marital income to be held equally could encourage
power equality within marriage (Okin 1989, Chapter 8). However, state interference in on-going marriages
arguably conflicts with spouses’ liberties (Rawls 1997, 787–794). This seems to raise a theoretical problem for
liberal feminism. Recent liberal feminist approaches to marriage focus on how a just law of marriage can protect
women’s interests as well as supporting a fairer distribution of care work, which often falls on women (Metz
2010, Brake 2012, Hartley and Watson 2012, Ferguson 2016, Bhandary 2018; see also reform proposals in 4.4
above).
While many feminists have focused on the reform of marriage, others have argued for its abolition as a legal
status (Metz 2010, Chambers 2013, 2017). It is sometimes claimed that marriage is inherently structured by
sexist social norms, precluding the possibility of feminist reform — and that marriage also reinforces stigma
against the unmarried (Chambers 2017). On such views, abolishing marriage is necessary to reshape social
expectations and change patterns of choice accompanying it. For example, legal marriage may encourage
women’s economic dependence by enabling and providing incentives for it. Thus, the legal structure of marriage,
in combination with social norms, is taken to encourage choices which disempower women relative to men.
Moreover, legal recognition of marriage itself endorses an ideal of a central, exclusive love relationship which,
on the views of some feminists, encourages women to make disadvantageous choices by inculcating an
exaggerated valuation of such relationships—at the expense of women’s other aspirations. Thus, in The Second
Sex, feminist philosopher Simone de Beauvoir (1908–86) identified the expectations surrounding marriage as
one of the primary means by which women are socialized into a femininity which, in her view, was limiting:
marriage “is the destiny traditionally offered to women by society” (de Beauvoir 1949 [1989], 425; see also Okin
1989), leading women to focus on their attractiveness as mates—and not on study, career, or other ambitions. For
this reason, some feminists have rejected ideals of romantic, exclusive love relationships, arguing that women
should choose non-monogamy or lesbian separatism (Firestone 1970; see also Card 1996). The idea that
marriage is essentially tied to such an ideal of romantic love will require further examination in the next section.
undermine, rather than achieve, gay and lesbian liberation - and, indeed, further marginalize asexuals,
aromantics, polyamorists, and those who choose to build their lives around friendships.
Recall that some arguments for same-sex marriage claim that central, exclusive relationships are valuable, and
that same-sex marriage would benefit gays and lesbians by encouraging them to enter such relationships (e.g.
Macedo 2005; see 3.3). But critics of heteronormativity, drawing on gay and lesbian experience, have argued
that the central, exclusive relationship ideal is a heterosexual paradigm. Such critics note that gays and lesbians
often choose relationships which are less possessive and more flexible than monogamous marriage. Instead of
recognizing the diverse relationships found in the gay and lesbian community, same-sex marriage would
assimilate lesbian and gay relationships into the heterosexual model. While some advocates of same-sex
marriage argue that marital status would confer legitimacy on same-sex relationships, these critics argue that the
state should not confer legitimacy (and hence, implicitly, illegitimacy) on consensual adult relationships, any
more than it should so discriminate between children born in or out of wedlock. Such conferrals of legitimacy
are thought to discourage diversity. Moreover, same-sex marriage would expose gays and lesbians to the
disadvantages, even evils, of marriage: economic incentives to stay in loveless marriages and reduced exit
options which facilitate abuse and violence (Card 1996, 2007, Ettelbrick 1989).
Other philosophers of gay and lesbian oppression have responded in defense of same-sex marriage that it not
only serves gay liberation, it is essential to it. Excluding gays and lesbians from marriage marks them as inferior,
and so same-sex marriage would decrease stigmas against homosexuality. Further, the costs of same-sex
marriage must be weighed with benefits such as healthcare, custody and inheritance rights, and tax and
immigration status (Calhoun 2000, Chapter 5, Ferguson 2007, Mayo and Gunderson 2000). Finally, in response
to worries about gay and lesbian assimilation, defenders of same-sex marriage have argued that marriage can
incorporate diversity, rather than suppressing it. Marriage need not entail monogamy; indeed, it is argued that
same-sex marriage could perform the liberatory function of teaching heterosexuals that neither gender roles nor
monogamy are essential to love and marriage (Mohr 2005, 69–9, cf. Halwani 2003, Chapter 3; but see Brake
2018 for discussion of whether “subversive weddings” can transform social attitudes if they are not recognized
as initiating marriages).
The feminist and queer critiques of marriage as essentially sexist, or essentially heterosexist, face the same
objection as do other claims about the essence of marriage. Just because marriage has in the past possessed
certain features does not entail that they are inherent to it. Thus, rather than reproducing sexist and heterosexist
patterns, same-sex marriage could serve women’s and gay liberation by transforming marriage, even, perhaps,
opening the door to recognition of a still wider variety of family forms (Ferguson 2007, Mayo and Gunderson
2000, Calhoun 2005, Brake 2012).
Bibliography
Contemporary Works
Abbey, Ruth, and Den Uyl, Douglas, 2001, “The Chief Inducement? The Idea of Marriage As Friendship,”
Journal of Applied Philosophy, 18(1): 37–52.
Almeida, Luís Duarte d’, 2012, “Legal Sex,” Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law (Volume 2), Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. 277–310.
Altman, Matthew C., 2010, “Kant on Sex and Marriage: The Implications for the Same-Sex Marriage Debate,”
Kant-Studien, 101(3): 309–330.
Arneson, Richard, 2005, “The Meaning of Marriage: State Efforts to Facilitate Friendship, Love, and
Childrearing,” San Diego Law Review, 42: 979–1001.
Arroyo, Christopher, 2018, “Is the Same-sex Marriage Debate Really Just about Marriage?,” Journal of Applied
Philosophy, 35(1): 186–203.
Baltzly, Vaughn Bryan, 2012, “Same-Sex Marriage, Polygamy, and Disestablishment,” Social Theory and
Practice, 38(2): 333–362.
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 19/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Barry, Peter Brian, 2011, “Same-Sex Marriage and the Charge of Illiberality,” Social Theory and Practice, 37(2):
333–357.
Beckwith, Francis J., 2013, “Justificatory Liberalism and Same-Sex Marriage,” Ratio Juris, 26(4): 487–509.
Bennett, Christopher, 2003, “Liberalism, Autonomy, and Conjugal Love,” Res Publica, 9: 285–301.
Beyer, Jason A., 2002, “Public Dilemmas and Gay Marriage: Contra Jordan,” Journal of Social Philosophy,
33(1): 9–16.
Bhandary, Asha, 2018, “Arranged Marriage: Could It Contribute to Justice?,” Journal of Political Philosophy,
26(2): 193–215.
Blankschaen, Kurt, 2020, “Rethinking Same-Sex Sex in Natural Law Theory,” Journal of Applied Philosophy,
37(3): 428–445.
Boonin, David, 1999, “Same-Sex Marriage and the Argument from Public Disagreement,” Journal of Social
Philosophy, 30(2): 251–259.
Boswell, John, 1994, The Marriage of Likeness: Same-Sex Unions in Pre-Modern Europe, London:
HarperCollins.
Brake, Elizabeth, 2005, “Justice and Virtue in Kant’s Account of Marriage,” Kantian Review, 9: 58–94.
–––, 2012, Minimizing Marriage: Marriage, Morality, and the Law, New York: Oxford University Press.
–––, 2014, “Recognizing Care: The Case for Friendship and Polyamory,” Syracuse Law and Civic Engagement
Journal, 1, [available online].
–––, 2016, “Equality and Non-Hierarchy in Marriage: What Do Feminists Really Want?,” in After Marriage:
Rethinking Marital Relationships, E. Brake (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 100–124.
–––, 2018, “Do Subversive Weddings Challenge Amatonormativity? Polyamorous Weddings and Romantic Love
Ideals,” Analize: Journal of Gender and Feminist Studies, 11, [Brake 2018 available online].
Brennan, Samantha, and Bill Cameron, 2016, “Is Marriage Bad for Children? Rethinking the Connection
between Having Children, Romantic Love, and Marriage,” in After Marriage: Rethinking Marital
Relationships, E. Brake (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 84–99.
Brooks, Thom, 2009, “The Problem with Polygamy,” Philosophical Topics, 37(2): 109–22.
Buccola, Nicholas, 2005, “Finding Room for Same-Sex Marriage: Toward a More Inclusive Understanding of a
Cultural Institution,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 36(3): 331–343.
Calhoun, Cheshire, 2000, Feminism, the Family, and the Politics of the Closet: Lesbian and Gay Displacement,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
–––, 2005, “Who’s Afraid of Polygamous Marriage? Lessons for Same-Sex Marriage Advocacy from the History
of Polygamy,” San Diego Law Review, 42: 1023–1042.
Cannon, Loren, 2009, “Trans-Marriage and the Unacceptability of Same-Sex Marriage Restrictions,” Social
Philosophy Today, 25: 75–89.
Card, Claudia, 1996, “Against Marriage and Motherhood,” Hypatia, 11(3): 1–23.
–––, 2007, “Gay Divorce: Thoughts on the Legal Regulation of Marriage,” Hypatia, 22(1): 24–38.
Cave, Eric M., 2003, “Marital Pluralism: Making Marriage Safer for Love,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 34(3):
331–347.
–––, 2004, “Harm Prevention and the Benefits of Marriage,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 35(2): 233–243.
–––, 2017, “Liberalism, Civil Marriage, and Amorous Caregiving Dyads,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 36(1):
50–72.
Chambers, Clare, 2013, “The Marriage-Free State,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 113 (2): 123–143.
–––, 2016, “The Limitations of Contract: Regulating Personal Relationships in a Marriage-Free State,” in After
Marriage: Rethinking Marital Relationships, E. Brake (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 51–
83.
–––, 2017, Against Marriage: An Egalitarian Defence of the Marriage-Free State, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Chan, Sarah, and Daniela Cutas (eds.), 2012, Families ––Beyond the Nucelar Ideal, New York: Bloomsbury
Academic.
Chartier, Gary, 2016, Public Practice, Private Law: An Essay on Love, Marriage, and the State, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Collins, Patricia Hill, 1998, “It’s All in the Family: Intersections of Gender, Race, and Nation,” Hypatia, 13(3):
62–82.
Coontz, Stephanie, 2006, Marriage: a History, London: Penguin.
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 20/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Corvino, John, 2005, “Homosexuality and the PIB Argument,” Ethics, 115: 501–534.
Cott, Nancy, 2000, Public Vows: A History of Marriage and the Nation, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Cronan, Sheila, 1973, “Marriage,” in Radical Feminism, ed. Anne Koedt, Ellen Levine, Anita Rapone, New
York: Quadrangle, pp.213 –221.
Crookston, Emily, 2014, “Love and Marriage?,” Journal of Moral Philosophy, 11(4): 267–289.
De Marneffe, Peter, 2016, “Liberty and Polygamy,” in After Marriage: Rethinking Marital Relationships, E.
Brake (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 125–159.
Den Otter, Ron, 2015, In Defense of Plural Marriage, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Denike, Margaret, 2010, “The Racialization of White Man’s Polygamy,” Hypatia, 25(4): 852–874.
Devlin, Patrick, 1965, The Enforcement of Morals, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Emens, Elizabeth F., 2004, “Monogamy’s Law: Compulsory Monogamy and Polyamorous Existence,” New York
University Review of Law and Social Change, 29: 277–376.
Ettelbrick, Paula, “Since When is Marriage a Path to Liberation?,” 1989, Out/look: National Lesbian and Gay
Quarterly, 6(9): 14–17; reprinted in Andrew Sullivan (ed.), Same-Sex Marriage: Pro and Con, New York:
Vintage, 2004, pp. 122–128.
Ferguson, A., 2007, “Gay Marriage: An American and Feminist Dilemma,” Hypatia, 22(1): 39–57.
Ferguson, Michaele L., 2016, “Vulnerability by Marriage: Okin’s Radical Feminist Critique of Structural Gender
Inequality,” Hypatia (A Journal of Feminist Philosophy), 31(3): 687–703.
Ferracioli, Luara, 2016, “Family Migration Schemes and Liberal Neutrality: A Dilemma,” Journal of Moral
Philosophy, 13(5): 553–575.
Fineman, Martha, 2004, The Autonomy Myth: A Theory of Dependency, New York: The New Press.
Finnis, John, 1994, “Law, Morality, and ‘Sexual Orientation’,” Notre Dame Law Review, 69: 1049–1076.
–––, 1997, “The Good of Marriage and the Morality of Sexual Relations: Some Philosophical and Historical
Observations,” American Journal of Jurisprudence, 42: 97–134.
–––, 2008, “Marriage: A Basic and Exigent Good,” The Monist, 91(3–4): 388–406.
Firestone, Shulamith, 1970, The Dialectic of Sex: The Case for Feminist Revolution, New York: William
Morrow and Co.
Galston, William, 1991, Liberal Purposes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Garrett, Jeremy, 2008, “History, Tradition, and the Normative Foundations of Civil Marriage,” The Monist,
91(3–4): 446–474.
–––, 2008, “Why the Old Sexual Morality of the New Natural Law Undermines Traditional Marriage,” Social
Theory and Practice, 34(4): 591–622.
–––, 2009, “A Prima Facie Case Against Civil Marriage,” Southwest Philosophy Review, 25(1): 41–53.
George, Robert P., 2000, “‘Same-Sex Marriage’ and ‘Moral Neutrality’,” in Homosexuality and American Public
Life, Christopher Wolfe (ed.), Dallas: Spence Publishing Company, pp. 141–153.
Gheaus, Anca, 2016, “The (Dis)value of Commitment to One’s Spouse,” in After Marriage: Rethinking Marital
Relationships, E. Brake (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 204–224.
Girgis, Sherif, Robert P. George, and Ryan T. Anderson, 2010, “What is Marriage?” Harvard Journal of Law and
Public Policy, 34(1): 245–288.
Goldstein, Joshua D., 2011, “New Natural Law Theory and the Grounds of Marriage,” Social Theory and
Practice, 37 (3): 461–482.
Grisez, Germain, 1993, The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 2 Living a Christian Life, Quincy, IL: Franciscan Press.
Halwani, Raja, 2003, Virtuous Liaisons, Peru, IL: Open Court.
Hartley, Christie, and Watson, Lori, 2012, “Political Liberalism, Marriage and the Family,” Law and Philosophy,
31(2): 185–212.
Herman, Barbara, 1993, “Could it be worth thinking about Kant on sex and marriage?,” in A Mind of One’s Own,
Louise Antony and Charlotte Witt (eds.), Oxford: Westview Press, pp. 49–67.
Houlgate, Laurence, 2005, Children’s Rights, State Intervention, Custody and Divorce: Contradictions in Ethics
and Family Law, Lewiston, NY: The Mellen Press.
Johnson, Rebekah, 2013, “Marriage and the Metaphysics of Bodily Union,” Social Theory and Practice, 39(2):
288–312.
Jordan, Jeff, 1995, “Is It Wrong to Discriminate on the Basis of Homosexuality?,” Journal of Social Philosophy,
26(1): 39–52.
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 21/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Kleingeld, Pauline, 1998, “Just Love? Marriage and the Question of Justice,” Social Theory and Practice, 24(2):
261–281.
Kronqvist, Camilla, 2011, “The Promise That Love Will Last,” Inquiry, 54(6): 650–668.
Kymlicka, Will, 1991,“Rethinking the Family,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 20(1): 77–97.
Landau, Iddo, 2004, “An Argument for Marriage,” Philosophy, 79: 475–481.
–––, 2012, “Should Marital Relations be Non-Hierarchical?,” Ratio, 25(1): 51–67.
Lee, Patrick, 2008, “Marriage, Procreation, and Same-Sex Unions,” The Monist, 91(3–4): 422–438.
Li, Xiaorong, 1995, “Gender Inequality in China and Cultural Relativism,” in Women, Culture and
Development: A Study of Human Capabilities, Martha Nussbaum and Jonathan Glovers (eds.), New York:
Oxford University Press, pp. 407–425.
Macedo, Stephen, 1995, “Homosexuality and the Conservative Mind,” Georgetown Law Review, 84: 261–300.
–––, 2015, Just Married: Same-Sex Couples, Monogamy & the Future of Marriage, Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Mahoney, Jon, 2008, “Liberalism and the Polygamy Question,” Social Philosophy Today, 23: 161–174.
Manning, W., Fettro, M., and Lamidi, E., 2014, “Child Well-Being in Same-Sex Parent Families: Review of
Research Prepared for the American Sociological Association Amicus Brief,” Population Research &
Policy Review, 33(4): 485–502.
March, Andrew F., 2010, “What Lies Beyond Same-Sex Marriage? Marriage, Reproductive Freedom and Future
Persons in Liberal Public Justification,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 27(1): 39–58.
March, Andrew F., 2011, “Is There a Right to Polygamy? Marriage, Equality, and Subsidizing Families in
Liberal Political Justification,” Journal of Moral Philosophy, 8: 246–272.
Marquis, Don, 2005, “What’s Wrong with Adultery?,” in What’s Wrong?, Graham Oddie and David Boonin
(eds.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 231–238.
Martin, Mike W., 1993, “Love’s Constancy,” Philosophy, 68(263): 63–77.
–––, 1994, “Adultery and Fidelity,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 25(3): 76–91.
May, Simon, 2016, “Liberal Neutrality and Civil Marriage,” in After Marriage: Rethinking Marital
Relationships, E. Brake (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 9–28.
Mayo, David J. and Gunderson, Martin, 2000, “The Right to Same-Sex Marriage: A Critique of the Leftist
Critique,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 31(3): 326–337.
McClain, Linda C., 2013, “The Other Marriage Equality Problem,” Boston University Law Review, 93(3): 921–
970.
McMurtry, John, 1972, “Monogamy: A Critique,” The Monist, 56: 587–99.
Mendus, Susan, 1984, “Marital Faithfulness,” Philosophy, 59: 243–252.
Mercier, Adèle, 2001, Affidavit, Ontario Superior Court of Justice (Divisional Court), Between Halpern al.
(Applicants) and Canada (Attorney General) et al. (Respondents), Court file 30/2001, 30/2001, Nov.
[available online]
Metz, Tamara, 2010, Untying the Knot: Marriage, the State, and the Case for their Divorce, Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Mohr, Richard D., 2005, The Long Arc of Justice: Lesbian and Gay Marriage, Equality, and Rights, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Moller, Dan, 2003, “An Argument Against Marriage,” Philosophy, 78(1): 79–91.
Morse, Jennifer Roback, 2006, “Why Unilateral Divorce Has No Place in a Free Society,” in The Meaning of
Marriage, Robert P. George and Jean Bethke Elshtain (eds.), Dallas: Spence Publishing Co, pp. 74–99.
Moses, Julia (ed.), 2018, Marriage, Law and Modernity: Global Histories, New York: Bloomsbury.
Murphy, Timothy F., 2011, “Same-Sex Marriage: Not a Threat to Marriage or Children,” Journal of Social
Philosophy, 42(3): 288–304.
Narayan, Uma, 1995, “‘Male-Order’ Brides: Immigrant Women, Domestic Violence and Immigration Law,”
Hypatia, 10(1): 104–119.
–––, 1997, Dislocating Cultures: Identities, Traditions, and Third-World Feminism, Routledge: New York.
Nolan, Daniel, 2016, “Temporary Marriage,” in After Marriage: Rethinking Marital Relationships, E. Brake
(ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 180–203.
–––, forthcoming, “Marriage and its Limits,” Inquiry.
Nussbaum Martha, 1999, Sex and Social Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Okin, Susan Moller, 1979, Women in Western Political Thought, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 22/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
–––, 1989, Justice, Gender, and the Family, New York: Basic Books.
–––, 1994, “Political Liberalism, Justice, and Gender,” Ethics, 105(1): 23–43.
Papadaki, Lina, 2010, “Kantian Marriage and Beyond: Why It Is Worth Thinking About Kant on Marriage,”
Hypatia, 25 (2): 276–294.
Parsons, Kate, 2008, “Subverting the Fellowship of the Wedding Ring,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 39(3):
393–410.
Pateman, Carole, 1988, The Sexual Contract, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Posner, Richard, and Silbaugh, Katharine, 1996, A Guide to America’s Sex Laws, Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press.
Rajczi, Alex, 2008, “A Populist Argument for Same-Sex Marriage,” The Monist, 91(3–4): 475–505.
Rawls, John, 1997, “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,” The University of Chicago Law Review, 64(3): 765–
807.
Raz, Joseph, 1986, The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Robson, Ruthann, 2007, “A Mere Switch or a Fundamental Change? Theorizing Transgender Marriage,”
Hypatia, 22 (1): 58–70.
Sandel, Michael, 1982, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Savulescu, Julian, and Sandberg, Anders, 2008, “Neuroenhancement of Love and Marriage: The Chemicals
Between Us,” Neuroethics, 1: 31–44.
Schaff, Kory, 2004, “Equal Protection and Same-Sex Marriage,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 35(1): 133–147.
Scruton, Roger, 1986, Sexual Desire, London: The Free Press.
Shanley, Mary Lyndon, et al., 2004, Just Marriage, Oxford: Oxford University Press (includes title essay by
Shanley and short replies by 13 others).
Shrage, Laurie, 2013, “Reforming Marriage: A Comparative Approach,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 30(2):
107–121.
–––, 2016, “Polygamy, Privacy, and Equality,” in After Marriage: Rethinking Marital Relationships, E. Brake
(ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 160–179.
–––, 2018, “Decoupling Marriage and Parenting,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 35(3): 496–512.
Sommers, Christina Hoff, 1989, “Philosophers Against the Family,” in Person to Person, George Graham and
Hugh LaFollete (eds.), Philadelphia: Temple University Press, pp. 82–105.
Steinbock, Bonnie, 1986, “Adultery,” QQ: Report from the Center for Philosophy and Public Policy, 6(1): 12–
14.
Sticker, Martin, 2020, “The Case against Different-Sex Marriage in Kant,” Kantian Review, 25(3): 441–464.
Stivers, Andrew, and Valls, Andrew, 2007, “Same-sex marriage and the regulation of language,” Politics,
Philosophy and Economics, 6(2): 237–253.
Strauss, Gregg, 2012, “Is Polygamy Inherently Unequal?,” Ethics, 122(3): 516–544.
Sunstein, Cass, and Thaler, Richard, 2008, “Privatizing Marriage,” The Monist, 91(3–4): 377–387.
Tjaden, Patricia, and Thoennes, Nancy, 2000, “Full Report of the Prevalence, Incidence, and Consequences of
Violence Against Women,” Findings from the National Violence Against Women Survey, published by the
U. S. Department of Justice, NCJ 183781.
Toop, Alison, 2019, “Is Marriage Incompatible with Political Liberalism,” Journal of Moral Philosophy, 16(3):
302–326.
Tuana, Nancy, 2004, “Coming to Understand: Orgasm and the Epistemology of Ignorance,” Hypatia, 19(1):
194–232.
Vanderheiden, Steve, 1999, “Why the State Should Stay Out of the Wedding Chapel,” Public Affairs Quarterly,
13(2): 175–190.
Waldron, Jeremy, 1988, “When Justice Replaces Affection: The Need for Rights,” Harvard Journal of Law and
Public Policy, 11(3): 625–647.
–––, 1988–89, “Autonomy and Perfectionism in Raz’s Morality of Freedom,” Southern California Law Review,
62: 1097–1152.
Walker, Greg, 2015, “Public Reason Liberalism and Sex-Neutral Marriage A Response to Francis J. Beckwith,”
Ratio Juris, 28(4): 486–503.
Wallenstein, Peter, 2002, Tell the Court I Love My Wife: Race, Marriage, and Law—An American History, New
York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Wasserstrom, Richard, 1974, “Is Adultery Immoral?,” in Philosophical Forum, 5: 513–528.
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 23/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Wedgwood, Ralph, 1999, “The Fundamental Argument for Same-Sex Marriage,” The Journal of Political
Philosophy, 7(3): 225–242.
–––, 2016, “Is Civil Marriage Illiberal?,” in After Marriage: Rethinking Marital Relationships, E. Brake (ed.),
New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 29–50.
Weitzman, Lenore, 1981, The Marriage Contract, New York: Macmillan.
Wellington, Adrian Alex, 1995, “Why Liberals Should Support Same Sex Marriage,” Journal of Social
Philosophy, 26(3): 5–32.
Williams, Reginald, 2011, “Same-Sex Marriage and Equality,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 14(5): 589–
595.
Wilson, John, 1989, “Can One Promise to Love Another?,” Philosophy, 64: 557–63.
Young, Iris Marion, 1995, “Mothers, Citizenship, and Independence: A Critique of Pure Family Values,” Ethics,
105: 535–556.
Historical Works
The following works were first published prior to 1950.
Abelard and Heloise, 2003, The Letters of Abelard and Heloise, Betty Radice (trans.), M. T. Clanchy (rev.),
London: Penguin, revised edition.
Aquinas, Thomas, 1981, Summa Theologiae, English Dominicans (trans.), New York: Christian Classics (reprint
of London: Burns, Oates, and Washbourne 1912–36).
Aristotle, 1984, The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, Jonathan Barnes (ed.),
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Astell, Mary, 1700, “Reflections upon Marriage,” in Political Writings, Patricia Springborg (ed.), Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996, pp. 1–80.
Augustine, 1999, Marriage and Virginity: The Excellence of Marriage, Holy Virginity, The Excellence of
Widowhood, Adulterous Marriages, Continence, vol. I/9, Ray Kearney (trans), David Hunter (ed.), John E.
Rotelle (series ed.), Hyde Park, New York: New City Press.
Augustine, 1998, Answer to the Pelagians, II: Marriage and Desire, Answer to the Two Letters of the Pelagians,
Answer to Julian, vol. I/24, Roland J. Teske (trans.), John E. Rotelle (series ed.), Hyde Park, New York:
New City Press.
de Beauvoir, Simone, 1949, Le Deuxième sexe, Paris: Gallimard. Translated as The Second Sex, H. M. Parshley
(trans.), New York: Vintage, 1972. [Page references to 1989 edition.]
Engels, Friedrich, 1884 [1972], The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State, Eleanor Burke
Leacock (ed.), New York: International.
Hegel, G. W. F., 1995, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, Allen W. Wood (ed.), H. B. Nisbet (trans.),
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hobbes, Thomas, 1962, Leviathan, Michael Oakeshott (ed.), New York: Simon and Schuster.
Kant, Immanuel, 1785 [1991], The Metaphysics of Morals, Mary Gregor (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
–––, 1798 [2006], Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, Robert B. Louden (trans., ed.), Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Kierkegaard, Søren, 1987, Either/Or, 2 vols., Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong (trans.), Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Locke, John, 1988, Two Treatises of Government, Peter Laslett (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mill, John Stuart, 1988, The Subjection of Women, Susan Moller Okin (ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing
Company.
Marx, Karl, 1848, The Communist Manifesto, in Selected Writings, Lawrence Simon (ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett,
1994, pp. 157–186.
Plato, 1997, Complete Works, John Cooper (ed.), D. S. Hutchinson (assoc. ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing
Co.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 1762 [1993], Émile, Barbara Foxley (trans.), P. D. Jimack (intro.), London: J. M. Dent.
Russell, Bertrand, 1929, Marriage and Morals, New York: Horace Liveright.
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 24/25
11/23/23, 10:27 AM Marriage and Domestic Partnership (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Wollstonecraft, Mary, 1792 [1997], The Vindications: The Rights of Men, The Rights of Woman, D.L. Macdonald
and Kathleen Scherf (eds.), Peterborough, ON.: Broadview.
Academic Tools
How to cite this entry.
Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society.
Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project
(InPhO).
Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.
Related Entries
love | Aquinas, Thomas: moral, political, and legal philosophy | Aristotle, General Topics: ethics | Augustine,
Saint | Beauvoir, Simone de | civil rights | ethics: natural law tradition | feminist philosophy, interventions: liberal
feminism | feminist philosophy, interventions: philosophy of biology | feminist philosophy, interventions:
philosophy of law | feminist philosophy, topics: perspectives on reproduction and the family | feminist
philosophy, topics: perspectives on trans issues | Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: social and political philosophy
| homosexuality | Kant, Immanuel: social and political philosophy | Mill, John Stuart: moral and political
philosophy | obligations: special | parenthood and procreation | personal relationship goods | Plato: ethics and
politics in The Republic | Russell, Bertrand: moral philosophy | sex and sexuality | social institutions |
Wollstonecraft, Mary
Acknowledgments
Thanks to Eric Cave, Laurence Houlgate, Ann Levey, Mark Migotti, and Nicole Wyatt for their very helpful
comments on drafts of this entry. Thanks also to Tina Strasbourg and Patricia Thornton for research assistance.
Copyright © 2021 by
Elizabeth Brake <elizabeth.brake@rice.edu>
Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.
Please Read How You Can Help Support the Growth and Development of the Encyclopedia
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab, Department
of Philosophy, Stanford University
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/marriage/#DefMar 25/25