Philosophy of Law and Comparative Law
Philosophy of Law and Comparative Law
Law Review
FOUNDED 1852
Formerly
American Law Register
VOL. 100 OCTOBER, 1951 No. 1
and teachers of law in the legal periodicals, and (4) uniform training
of the judges in their formative years which leads to identity of atti-
tude toward legal precepts and their interpretation and application,
and a received idea of values and body of received ideals as to the end
and purpose of social control and so of law. Here we get help,; even
if only help, from philosophy.
What are the problems of the science of law at the moment which
call for philosophical method? One set of problems grow out of the
rise of the service state and its effect upon Anglo-American constitu-
tional law. It is characteristic of the service state to make lavish
promises of satisfying desires which it calls rights. Thus, in the spirit
of the service state some projects for world declarations of rights re-
cently proclaim a right of every one everywhere to "release from the
bondage of poverty" and a right in all men to "just terms of leisure."
When a constitution promises such things to every individual those
who draft it do not ask themselves whether such provisions are laws,
parts of the supreme law of the land, or only preachments of policies
which no court can enforce and no executive and no legislative body
can be made to regard. Such preachments enfeeble a legal constitutional
structure. As they cannot be enforced they lend themselves to a doc-
trine that constitutional provisions in a written constitution which
declares itself the supreme law of the land and contains a bill of rights
declaring specific liberties, which have been secured to Englishmen
since the contests between courts and crown in the seventeenth century,
and to Americans from the beginnings of our constitutional policy, by
legal remedies in the courts available to all injured individuals, may be
disregarded at any time in the interest of political policy of the moment.
They weaken the whole constitutional polity which we have built up
in the United States. Setting up such .things in a declaration of guar-
anteed rights makes a farce of constitutions. Guarantees which are
no more than promissory declarations of policy not only deceive, they
go to undermine those which are enforceable and made to be enforced.
Rise of the service state, the state which, instead of preserving
peace and order and maintaining the general security, takes the whole
domain of human welfare, except the welfare of our souls in the here-
after, for its province and would cure all economic and social ills
through its administrative activities, has affected American constitu-
tional law at another point. After experience of resumption of grants
and revocation of franchises at every turn of fortune in seventeenth-
century England, and of colonial legislation interfering with enforce-
ment of contracts and revoking charters, Americans put in our federal
constitution a prohibition of state legislation impairing the obligation
1951] PHILOSOPHY OF LAW AND COMPARATIVE LAW 5
Ulpian so put it in the Digest. Domat had repeated it. The nine-
teenth century metaphysical jurists, to whom freedom of the individual
will was the central point in their science of law, developed and re-
fined it. The free wills of the parties had made the law for them.
The courts could no more change this than any other part of the
law. Even the legislator was bound to respect it as to contracts of the
past. That idea was put in the constitution of the United States.
This high valuing of contract has been disappearing all over the
world. In France it was covered up for a time by what Austin would
have called spurious interpretation. By assuming that the will of
the parties had not been fully expressed, courts could discover in con-
tracts terms which were not there and were not in the minds of the
parties and could modify the terms which they found there. French
legislation went further and gave judges power to suspend or rescind
contracts and change their conditions. The parties no longer made law
for' themselves by free contract. In this as in everything else the
omnicompetent state makes the law for them. Partly there was a
moral idea here. Contracts might be improvident or changes in the
economic situation might affect the value of the promised performance
or of the given or promised equivalent. Partly there was a political
idea of helping debtors under severe burdens in time of economic
crisis. This is akin to an idea we shall see at work in the theory of
liability everywhere-a humanitarian idea of lifting or shifting burdens
and losses so as to put them upon those better able to bear them.
Belief in the obligatory force of contracts and respect for the given word
are going, if not gone.
It means a shift to a directed economy. Planiol well says: "If
the state undertakes to direct the economy itself it cannot admit the
maintenance of contract relations contrary to those it envisages. Con-
tracts of long duration become impossible where in all cases they are
exposed to revision of their clauses. Legal reglementation is substi-
tuted for contractual reglementation. The contract is no more than
the submission of the parties to an obligatory regime."
Things have not gone so far in the English-speaking world, but
they are moving in the same direction., Standard contracts, adminis-
trative prescribing of contract provisions and control over making, per-
forming and enforcing of contracts are becoming everyday matters.
In the history of the Anglo-American common law we see con-
tinually more extended securing of claims to performance of agree-
ments and promises as such until the rise of administrative agencies
with control over contract begins a new development in another direc-
tion. In Roman law down to Justinian we see the same continually
19511 PHILOSOPHY OF LAW AND COMPARATIVE LAW
in certain cases "based upon public policy." The public policy to which
he referred was the social interest in the general security which called
for holding men without regard to fault where they maintained things
or employed agencies likely in ordinary experience tb get out of hand
and do damage, unless at their peril of answering for resulting damage
they restrained these things and agencies and kept them within bounds.
Cases of liability without fault within this category have steadily mul-
tiplied in Anglo-American law in the present century, and liability
for wrongs done by agents and servants which covered up liability
without fault by a fiction of representation identifying servant with
master and agent with principal, had a long and detailed development.
(4) The idea of ability to pass the loss on to the public, the
so-called insurance idea. We were all to bear the losses falling upon
any of us as risks of life in civilized society, and, as means of achieving
that just distribution of the burden of loss, the law should impose the
loss in the first instance upon those able to pass it on to the public at
large through charges for service in the case of public utilities, or price
of goods manufactured in case of products of the factory, or prices for
products raised in agriculture.
(5) Parallel with or else out of the so-called insurance idea a
new basis of liability has been increasingly advocated in recent years
and is making headway. It looks like an idea of greater ability to bear
the loss as a ground of liability. It is urged as a humanitarian idea
but is often coupled with the insurance idea which under administrative
regimes of the time is fallacious in actual application.
A shift from the idea of liability as attached to fault to some
newer basis of liability not based on morals nor primarily upon the
general security has been going on throughout the world. It is quite
as marked in the law of Continental Europe as in Anglo-American
law. But what it is and what idea is behind it can be shown sufficiently
for the present purpose from American law, and I shall confine myself
to American illustrations.
At the beginning of the present century, and increasingly since,
judges and law teachers have been saying that something more was in
the air than imposition of liability without fault in order to maintain
the general security where the person to be held had the right and
power of control of the thing or agency to which loss or damage was
attributable. Fifty years ago Mr. Justice Holmes, speaking for the
Supreme Court of Massachusetts, answering a type of argument fre-
quently made today, said it was not plain that a man's misfortunes or
necessities would justify shifting damages to his neighbor's shoulders.
1951] PHILOSOPHY OF LAW AND COMPARATIVE LAW 9
Forty years ago this began to be urged in the form of what was
then called the insurance theory of liability. In one phase of this
humanitarian movement there was a real and immediate shifting of
the burden from the luckless individual who was injured to the public
at large. It used to be that the state could not be held for injuries to
individuals through the wrongful acts of public officers. The officers
who wrought the injury were personally liable to repair it. But
throughout the world there has been for a generation a tendency by
legislation to provide that public funds shall respond for injuries to
individuals in the course of operation of governmental agencies. Legis-
lation in America has been extending the doctrine of respondeat
superior to the government. Here, just as in case of injuries due to
wilful or negligent action of servants of public utilities or of great
industrial enterprises done in the course of their employment, the
wrongdoing servant is seldom able to satisfy a judgment for damages
in this time of multiplying limitations upon the power of creditors or
injured parties to exact satisfaction of judgments for debts or dam-
ages. The proposition is that losses incidental to services performed
for the benefit of all of us should be borne by all of us. If we adopt
Duguit's teaching that the state is simply a great public service com-
pany, the extension to it of liability under the doctrine of respondeat
superioris understandable.
Here, however, as in the case bf liability of private employ&s for
what is done by their employees in the course of their employment,
there is liability only for a wrong done. There has been no extension
to the state of absolute liability on the ground of causation without
fault. Legislation has increasingly created, in order to maintain the
social interest in the general security, offenses which dispense with
criminal intent and impose penalties for creating danger to health or
safety although the offender has used all due care and has knowingly
done nothing more than put on the market a carefully manufactured
article, fully inspected and of a kind in itself in no wise dangerous,
which nevertheless bursts or otherwise develops a defect and causes
injury. There are now strong proponents of extending civil liability
without fault to such cases.
In a recent case in California one of the outstanding state judges
of today in a concurring opinion, which he has since repeated in another
case, proposed extension of the liability of manufacturers for injuries
to purchasers of manufactured articles made to be sold in the market,
put in circulation accordingly, and ultimately acquired by the person
injured. He said: "I believe that the manufacturer's negligence should
no longer be singled out as the basis of a plaintiff's right to recover.
12 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 100
ably the niost active group and the group of most influence in philo-
sophical jurisprudence today. But the Kantian idea of justice has done
its work as the natural law of pure reason had done its work at the
end of the eighteenth century. Must we not hope for some new Kant
to find the path for the jurisprudence of the era on which we are enter-
ing and to give us the theory of justice for another time of fruitful
philosophical science of law?