SSRN 1659450
SSRN 1659450
No. 486
Punishment: Consequentialism
David Wood
Electronic
Electroniccopy
copyavailable
availableat:
at:https://ssrn.com/abstract=1659450
http://ssrn.com/abstract=1659450
Punishment: Consequentialism
David Wood
Abstract
justified? This, the first of three papers on the philosophy of punishment (see also
attempts to justify the practice or institution according to its consequences. One claim
is that punishment reduces crime, and hence the resulting harms. Another is that
some forms of punishment) can serve to make restitution to victims, and a fourth is
that it can strengthen social values. The paper examines these claims, and finally
“Punishment: Nonconsequentialism”.)
* * *
Electronic
Electroniccopy
copyavailable
availableat:
at:https://ssrn.com/abstract=1659450
http://ssrn.com/abstract=1659450
INTRODUCTION
155, cf. Burgh 193). Some go further. Punishment “cripples people” (Gross 375). It
“commits the state to the ‘prima facie’ barbarity of deliberately damaging people’s
lives” (Gardner 2007: 203). Indeed, the “punitive side” of the criminal law is “an
introduce the important issues raised both by the need for justification and attempts to
paper is concerned with theories that attempt to justify punishment solely through its
consequences, whereas the other considers theories that try to justify punishment in
virtue of its innate worth, or some intrinsic characteristic it possesses. This paper also
(the main concern here), and as a private practice that takes place in, for instance,
Electronic
Electroniccopy
copyavailable
availableat:
at:https://ssrn.com/abstract=1659450
http://ssrn.com/abstract=1659450
This, at least, is the intended division of labour. However, theorising about
punishment resists neat packaging. Trying to enforce too rigid a demarcation between
Feinberg 2008: 624). Pluralist theories that are basically consequentialist, but include
retributive and other constraints on the aims and ends they endorse (“side-
constrained” consequentialist theories, as they have been called (Duff 2001: 11-14)),
made to examine problems raised by particular forms of punishment. The paper totally
sidesteps the huge literature generated, particularly in the United States, by the continued
usually pay too little attention to sentencing” (Duff 1996: 57), no attempt to start
maximises happiness or utility, as against other available options. However, this paper
harm, in particular, the very serious harms that criminal conduct causes (murders,
social concern, and does not have to be seen in utilitarian terms (Wood n. 1). One
any reasonable moral theorist will do so, and agree that, other things being equal,
harm is morally bad, and consequently, the less crime (the fewer murders, rapes, and
so on) the better. And one can say this making all due allowance to the controversial,
‘contested’ nature of the concept of crime. Obviously, the conduct in any particular
criminalised.
aim (if “community” sounds parochial, consider the global community), the paper turns
and some even its sole, genuine purpose. Following rehabilitation, the paper examines
the victim-related aim of restitution (that is, as a form of punishment, rather than a
replacement for it). Perhaps surprisingly, restitution has not achieved the prominence
aims, the paper returns to a further purported general aim of punishment, namely
considered. A major trend in theorising about punishment has been the development
considerations. The earliest such theories, Rawls’ (Rawls 1955) and Hart’s (Hart
1959; but see Ross 59-64, Quinton 140-2), had a dual-level structure, proposing
generally, on their pursuit. This paper finally considers such pluralist theories. (It may
Nonconsequentialism”.)
without difficulties. Perhaps the most fashionable approach is that taken by pluralist
briefly to consider what punishment is. The orthodox analysis of the concept of
“punishment” is that developed by H.L.A. Hart, who drew on the work of Antony
Flew (Flew) and Stanley Benn (Benn). According to the Flew-Benn-Hart definition of
“punishment”, as it is sometimes called (although Hart does not, in fact, claim to offer
must involve pain or other consequences normally considered unpleasant; (ii) it must
be for an offence against legal rules; (iii) it must be for an actual or supposed offender
for his offence; (iv) it must be intentionally administered by human beings other than
Benn; Scheid).
Joel Feinberg, for instance, has argued that, in addition to satisfying these conditions,
disapproval and reprobation, on the part either of the punishing authority himself or of
those ‘in whose name’ the punishment is inflicted” (Feinberg 1965: 400). The
13; Husak 2008 (2): 92-4; see “Punishment: Nonconsequentialism”: “Expression” and
subject of these papers, rather than punishment as a private practice. This is not to deny
that many of the same issues arise with both (Hildebrandt). However, it is the state
which imposes the most severe forms of punishment, imprisonment and even death.
Even if a moral case for punishment can be made out in the abstract, there is the
role for the state to perform (Duff 1992, Duff 1996: 9). In particular, insofar as the
The problem for liberal political theory is that a state that pursues retributive
ends appears to engage in legal moralism, the view (on one account) that “[i]t can be
even though it causes neither harm nor offense to the actor or others” (Feinberg 1985:
4; see also Duff 2007: 47-49, 83-89). (More extreme – or just thorough-going –
liberals would delete the reference to “offence”.) The problem is particularly acute
where the state pursues these ends through punishment rather than other coercive
means, such as taxation, let alone in non-coercive ways, for instance, public
provide, the state breaches Mill’s harm principle, that “the only purpose for which
power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community against
his will, is to prevent harm to others” (Mill, ch. 1, para 9; cf. Hampton 1994).
theory, since retribution does not appear to be among the permissible functions of the
“protection against force, theft, fraud, enforcement of contract, and so on” (Nozick
1974: ix). It seems surprising, then, that libertarians – notably Nozick himself (1981:
Perhaps a further right should be added to Nozick’s list, namely that of crime
victims to see perpetrators justly punished. Hampton’s view, which sees the point of a
retributive response as repairing the victim’s “moral injury” (Hampton 1992: 1666-
this. On the other hand, note Nozick’s dismissal of a “‘utilitarianism of rights’” that
Punishment as a state institution creates further problems – not just for liberals
and libertarians, but political theorists of all persuasions – and irrespective of whether
power and authority (which forms of private punishment may be as well, if generally
(Husak 2000: 975; Husak 2008 (1): 109). In the case of imprisonment, the punishment
is not just the official loss of liberty, but “typically” as well, “impositions which are
injurious, brutalising, often painful and deeply degrading” (Galligan 159, cf. Golash
2-4, Kleinig 273, Signler). There is the inevitable moral price of the susceptibility of a
system of criminal law to wrongful convictions and hence punishments (Husak 2000:
975: Husak 2008 (1): 109). Obviously, this is most alarming in the case of the death
penalty, where DNA evidence has demonstrated a shocking incidence of conviction and
(in the United States) execution of perfectly innocent persons. But there is also the
Berman 266). Why should a government pursue punishment, rather than health,
benefit of helping ameliorate the social causes of crime (Golash 155-160; Hampton,
“Retribution”), and so reduce not just the incidence of crime, but likewise of
punishment?
HARM-REDUCTION
raises numerous issues. Most obvious is the question of what counts as harm for its
conduct. Harm-reductivists may obviously differ on how they identify different types
of harm, and rank them (and individual instances of harm) for relative seriousness.
Consider physical and psychological harm, harm to property and financial interests,
and harm to public interests, such as the interest in a clean environment and in a
functioning social and economic infrastructure. Consider also the moral harms created
by the criminal law itself – not just cases of wrongful convictions and hence
and ostracising treatment, and consequential material harms and losses (for instance,
from discrimination in employment and rental markets). Consider further the more
intangible social costs of “so ambitious, intrusive and burdensome an institution as the
criminal sanction” (von Hirsch 1993: 14; von Hirsch and Ashworth 24).
Must the conduct cause the harm, or can a weaker connection suffice for criminal
liability (and if so, under what conditions), such as the conduct’s “inducing”,
“encouraging”, or even “not discouraging” the harm? How far should the ambit of
instigators, and those more broadly who offer material or moral support?
instances of harm is to be gauged (von Hirsch and Jareborg 1991, and von Hirsch and
Jareborg in von Hirsch and Ashworth: Appendix 3). What makes one type or instance of
harm more or less serious than another? One complication is that criminalised conduct
as serious enough to warrant criminalising the responsible conduct – that is, where it
is sufficiently culpable, and other conditions are satisfied, such as the crime’s
occurring within the relevant jurisdiction, and the defendant’s being old enough to be
criminally liable: “[t]he problem is to develop criteria for harmfulness and culpability
that are more illuminating than simple intuition” (von Hirsch and Jareborg, in von
relevant type required to warrant criminalising the responsible conduct (again, subject
10
be recognised, and if so, the criteria for distinguishing them: “the jurisprudence of
crime seriousness has received comparatively little attention” (von Hirsch and Jareborg,
in von Hirsch and Ashworth 186; see also “Punishment: The Future”: “Looking
Ahead”).
Moving from harm to its reduction, both the material costs of criminal law
intervention must be taken into account, the social resources that could be used
elsewhere, and more importantly, the moral costs, such as the stigmatisation of
criminal conviction, and most worryingly, the risk of wrongful conviction. The aim
must be to reduce overall harm or loss – of the crime, the crime-reductive measures
themselves, and the broader costs of the institutional arrangements to implement them
they hold are the available means). For instance, one harm-reductivist may place
more weight on deterrence, a second (perhaps with a more optimistic view of human
nature) on rehabilitation, and a third, on the combination of the capacity for prudential
and moral motivation, merging them into the notion of “general prevention” (von
11
and other monetary penalties (for instance, restitution orders), community service and
on the grounds that it is no more effective a deterrent than lengthy prison terms, a
second accept it as a deterrent on the basis of different evidence, a third (at least, a
and a fourth hold that it should be reserved for exceptional cases, such as the most
heinous murders, or the murder of particular classes of victims, for instance, law-
enforcement officers.
Any form of hard treatment can in principle serve deterrence purposes, as it can
retributive purposes. Alternatively, a means may not be available because of the lack
of a measure to implement it. The town gaol, the only viable place of incarceration,
may have burnt down, or even more fancifully, capital punishment may not be
one harm-reductive means. For instance, imprisonment serves the end of harm-
and incapacitation.
12
description of the criminal process as “a great moral machine” (Feinberg 1987: 260)),
the only real question is the extent of the required hard treatment. But this may be
harm-reduction (or utility) may require punishment of the innocent (Boonin 31-52),
and the disproportionately harsh punishment of the guilty (Boonin 54-8). It is not
enough to appeal to the lack of likelihood of their arising in practice, critics claim – it
is the possibility in principle that is objectionable (Lessnoff 142). But unless the
harm-reductivist can adequately answer this objection, he must retreat from a pure to
through punishment, restricting its imposition to the guilty, and its severity according
to the seriousness of the offender’s crime or the extent of his culpability. The paper
REHABILITATION
aim and policy concern. The pertinent issue is whether it has sufficient, and indeed
13
any consequentialist punishment aim), are the three following questions: first, of what
actually rehabilitates, what are the available rehabilitative measures (or combination of
measures); secondly, of which such measures are the most effective, which best
rehabilitate; and thirdly, of the moral justifiability of the most effective, available
measures, whether moral constraints must be placed on their use, either general
is held that the relevant moral considerations are, in virtue of being such, overriding.
Rehabilitation had its heyday in the 1950’s and 1960’s (Allen) a period of
considerable faith in people’s capacity (rather misplaced as it turned out), with the aid
of the then rapidly developing human and social sciences, to solve individual and
social problems: “[t]he hope of providing humane and constructive treatment for
punishment with treatment (Wootton ch. 2), led to the extensive use of forms of
therapy and other techniques that often were far more harsh than punishment based
treatment was liable to be imposed on individuals under the guise that they were not
14
1976) to limit the extent of harsh, but supposedly rehabilitative, treatment. According
to this idea, offenders ought to receive only what they morally deserve. Typically, for
therapy is to give offenders more than their “just deserts”. Some philosophers of
punishment, such as Herbert Morris (but see most notably G.W.F. Hegel 126-7), even
suggested that offenders have “a right to be punished”, which is entailed by their right
to be treated as responsible moral agents (Morris, see also Deigh). The thought here is
therapy on them instead, is to fail to treat them as responsible moral agents, capable of
slogan “a right to be punished” must be contrasted with the stronger, but more
dubious idea of the right of the offender to have his wrongdoing annulled (see the
hence the moral burden of the crime lifted from him. Underlying the notions of “just
deserts” and “a right to be punished”, and perhaps most influential of all, was the
growing recognition and influence of liberal ideals of human dignity and individual
rights.
However, the fate of the “rehabilitative ideal” was sealed more at the level of
practice than theory, with the growing realisation that rehabilitation was failing in its
15
difficult to see what worked and why, which programs and methods produced
worthwhile results, and for what reasons. There was evidence of some success with
specialised programs directed at specific offender sub-groups (Rex, Zedner 97), but
the incarceration required for most rehabilitative programs was itself profoundly
“dehabilitative”.
The “nothing works” thesis also had resonance with deterrence, although there
the problem was more one of trying to determine the marginal effectiveness of
with retribution the requirement of hard treatment, deterrence was able to piggy-back
“just deserts”). Deterrence therefore was better placed than rehabilitation in the face
of empirical doubts.
rehabilitation, concerned more deeply and ambitiously with the moral reform of
offenders, indeed, their moral education, with their becoming better citizens and
16
The important issue here (apart from paternalistic dangers: Zedner 98) concerns
the standards by which persons subjected to such measures are to be judged rehabilitated
accepted and shared by a given group” (Hart 1963: 20), or alternatively according to
critical moral standards, “the general moral principles used in the criticism of actual
social institutions including positive morality” (Ibid)? Insofar as the aims are to be
assessed according to the latter, the question arises of what are the applicable moral
standards?
RESTITUTION
unjust enrichment, but more generally of tort law, in the broad sense that encompasses
making good a loss, and so goes beyond the technical sense of returning – or
“disgorging” – a gain. Restitution in this broad sense is a quite general social policy
concern, which may be supported by taxation and insurance. It has increasingly been
17
to what must be done to restore the victim to the “status quo ante”, it must look back
at what that position was, and determine the effect of the crime on the victim. Perhaps
a misnomer where, as is often the case, the “rehabilitee” never was in the supposed
“habilitated” state, and hence there is no question of any return to such a state. This
to push the point too far (otherwise, one could even say that retributivism is likewise
just retribution is inflicted on the offender), one must not suppose that the distinction
warning in the “Introduction”, that trying to enforce too rigid a demarcation between
kept in mind.
That restitution has not achieved the status of harm-reduction and rehabilitation
crime, notwithstanding the best efforts of vociferous victims’ rights groups, and the rapid
18
a peripheral aim of the criminal law, however important it may be in private law. (See
without Hard Treatment”.) But if punishment, and the criminal law more broadly, is
224-6). The latter is hardly contentious (Boonin 216). However, material restitution is
scarcely important enough to play such a role. Only the far more ambitious and
offender, has the potential to be a new paradigm, or even a major punishment aim.
But Barnett discusses material rehabilitation only. (See further Boonin 216-8, the
theory of punishment. Certainly, such a view serves as a much needed antidote to the
“Communication and Retribution Again”), with the offender and his moral reform.
19
social values. The key claim in relation to this justification of punishment is that
(Gould and Scholz, Scholz), or to use Durkheim’s term, the “collective conscience”
particular classes of individuals – offenders and victims respectively – this aim, like
generally.
aim irrespective of what the values are – or only subject to their meeting some critical
moral standard. Is there merely a formal or functional relation between the aim and
the relevant social values, or more importantly, a substantive relation that brings in
their content? Why strengthen a society’s values simply because they are its values?
Some suggest that a society should take an active role in developing its values,
adopt a positive program of moral education and reform, indeed, that it is the role of
some recent examples from Australian television) to drive safely, stop smoking, drink
responsibly, and even to be alert to overhead power lines when boating. Into more
20
Cynics may ridicule the notion of the moral development of an individual, and
likewise the parallel notion of the moral development of a society or community. And
both notions are certainly open to abuse, the latter even more so than the former.
‘proper’ values. Certainly, any legitimate process of rational persuasion must respect
individuals’ moral autonomy and independence, must “take seriously the distinction
a society as a whole, and not just individuals and particular social institutions and
organisations, with better and worse values, however contentious it may be to decide
Consider a society with a strong sense of justice (Rawls 1963; Rawls 1999: ch.
VIII) and deep commitment to humanitarian values and human rights (in substance,
irrespective of the terminology used), that genuinely respects the equal worth of each
the basic needs (liberally interpreted) of all its members are satisfied, and that all have
But even if these ideals are enthusiastically endorsed, it is not easy to see how
punishment could usefully help to implement such a moral agenda, and in any case,
how this could justify such punishment. Punishment to maintain a minimal level of
social life and survival is one thing – but punishment for such aspirational purposes,
21
THEORIES
time, however – at least since the publication in the 1950’s of two seminal articles,
John Rawls’ “Two Concepts of Rules” (Rawls 1955) and H.L.A. Hart’s “Prolegomenon
to the Principles of Punishment” (Hart 1959) – most punishment theorists (Husak 1992:
452) have been pluralists of one kind or another (other terms include “dualist”,
own. Instead, they have been engaged in the project of trying to show how such
considerations, and more recently, other considerations like the moral reform of the
that in the practice of punishment we are often confronted with a number of different
considerations, each not reducible to the others, and each having a contribution to
make” (Ten 6). Ten accordingly identifies as his main target, “any theory of
22
respecting a set of different values which cannot necessarily be reduced to each other,
or into some overriding common currency such as general utility” (Lacey 199).
This is not to say that all theorists have succumbed to pluralism. Michael
retribution (and retributive considerations alone) not only sets limits on when
punishment may be justifiably imposed, but also provides (and alone provides) the
state with a positive reason for punishing offenders. Moore’s theory, as a “pure
good to serve as part of, or be included in, what Hart calls the “general justifying aim”
However, it is with Rawls and Hart that we should start. Rawls’ rule-utilitarian
23
although Rawls famously went on to reject utilitarianism, and with it his own version of
normative political philosophy) to oppose the utilitarian tradition, he did not revisit the
topic of punishment or revise his theory in “Two Concepts of Rules” (Rawls 1955).
Hart’s theory similarly involves a distinction between two stages, first, as just
which divides into two further questions, of “liability” (who to punish?) and “amount”
(how much to punish?) (Hart 1959). He holds that utilitarian considerations are relevant
to the first issue, of why have an institution of punishment at all, whereas retribution, and
considerations of justice and fairness more generally, are relevant to the second issue,
criminal offence, and its severity according to the seriousness of their crimes or the
extent of their culpability. Hart makes this move to avoid an important criticism of
“pure” utilitarian theories of punishment, namely, that such theories imply that it is
doing so maximises utility, or brings about some other consequentialist good. According
to Hart’s theory of punishment, the retributive considerations that are relevant to the
question of liability ensure that we never punish the innocent, and that the retributive
considerations that are relevant to the question of amount ensure that we never impose
24
are accused of not treating it seriously enough. Rather than merely another crime-
notion: “[t]o many people there is a deeply embedded intuition that part at least of the
general purpose of criminal justice is the correction of wrongs, quite apart from any
there are separate retributive and utilitarian conditions on punishment, and both “enter
into the justification of every case of punishment. Each condition is necessary, and the
two conditions are jointly sufficient for the justification of punishment” (Ten 79).
(Although Ten modifies both conditions to yield his “Revised Compromise Theory”
(Ten 80), the changes do not affect the relation between them.)
considerations to the second level, and according to the objection, this is to assign them a
lesser role. Taking the above intuition seriously requires a different type of pluralist
theory, one that recognises retribution as itself a goal or an end of punishment, and not
just a constraint on the pursuit of other punishment goals or ends, such as utility-
25
establish the connection between the two levels – in the case of Rawls, the rules of the
rule-utilitarian theory in question and individual acts, and with Hart, the general
justifying aim of punishment and the principle of distribution. To focus on Hart’s theory,
considerations to the level of the general justifying aim, and retributive considerations to
that of distribution. To move from one type of consideration to the other in this way is
like changing horses mid-stream: “[s]o the reasons given for punishing at all, and the
guiltiness of the offender float, as it were, side by side, without being able to make
Thirdly, while pure retributivists hold that retribution alone can be a sufficient
justification for punishment, more pluralistically minded retributivists object that it has
insufficient weight on its own to justify punishment as a social, and indeed state
moralistic to create a system of punishment for the sole purpose of exacting retribution
from offenders. There is insufficient reason (some would say no reason at all) to
systematically pursue retribution as an end in its own right, let alone for the state to do so
26
that even though retribution does not by itself offer a sufficient justification of
their own accounts. Lacey, for instance, broadens Hart’s utilitarian understanding of
this aim to include the protection of the values of autonomy and welfare (Lacey ch. 6;
Wood 314-7). The general justifying aim in John Braithwaite’s and Philip Pettit’s
(Braithwaite and Pettit 54). Alvin Goldman goes much further in proposing desert as
“the central justifying factor” in punishment, with utilitarian justification required “for
desert principle” (Goldman 55). John Tasioulas replaces Hart’s utilitarian “general
justifying aim” with that of the communication of censure for wrongdoing, conceived
as a formal end, but one which encompasses the substantive ends of retributive
Indeed, inverting the order of the two levels has become something of a new
Again”). Interestingly, Douglas Husak suggests that retributive justice should be the
drawbacks with any system of state punishment (“Public and Private Punishment”,
27
liability as with any system of authority to the abuse of power, and sheer cost, the
CONCLUSION
very strong need of justification. This paper examined attempts to justify punishment
also strengthening social values). The paper also considered pluralist theories that
Acknowledgments
For very helpful comments and criticisms, I wish to thank Jes Bjarup, Deirdre Golash,
28
Wiley-Blackwell Publishing gives David Wood proper credit as the original author of
this article. Wiley-Blackwell also acknowledges that the article draws upon pages 302
and 304-6 of an earlier article by the same author: Wood, D., “Retribution, Crime
Studies 301. Reproduced by kind permission of the Oxford Journal of Legal Studies.
Works Cited
Allen, Francis A. The Decline of the Rehabilitative Ideal. New Haven: Yale
1982.
279-301.
Benn, S.I. “An Approach to the Problems of Punishment”. Philosophy 33 (1958): 325
-341.
29
2008.
Braithwaite, John and Pettit, Philip. Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of
Burgh, R.W. “Do the Guilty Deserve Punishment?”. Journal of Philosophy 94 (1982):
193-210.
Deigh, John. “On the Right to be Punished: Some Doubts”. Ethics 94 (1984):191-211.
William, ed., Retributivism and its Critics. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner, 1992. 43-68.
Crime and Justice: A Review of Recent Research (ed. Michael Tonry; University of
Press, 2001.
------------. Answering for Crime: Responsibility and Liability in the Criminal Law.
30
Macmillan, 1984.
-----------------. Offence to Others: The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, Vol. Two.
(1987): 249-275.
----------------. “The Classic Debate”. Philosophy of Law (8th ed.). Ed. Joel Feinberg
Galligan, D.J. “The Return to Retribution in Penal Theory”. Crime, Proof and
31
Gardner, John. Offences and Defences. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007. 201-221.
Golash, Deirdre. The Case Against Punishment. New York: New York University
Press, 2005.
Goldman, Alvin. “The Paradox of Punishment”. Philosophy and Public Affairs 9 (1979):
42-58.
Gould, Carol C. and Scholtz, Sally J., eds. “Solidarity”, special issue of Journal of
Gross, Hyman. A Theory of Criminal Justice. New York: Oxford University Press,
1979.
32
Hegel, G.W.F. Elements of the Philosophy of Right (trans. N.B. Nisbet, ed. Allen W.
Hildebrandt, Mirelle. “Justice and Police: Regulatory Offences and the Criminal
2006.
959-86.
------------------. (1) “Why Criminal Law: A Question of Content?”. Criminal Law and
Kleinig, John. “The Hardness of Hard Treatment”, in Ashworth, Andrew and Wasik,
33
(1971): 141-8.
Mackie, J.L. “Morality and the Retributive Emotions”. Criminal Justice Ethics 1
(1982): 3-10.
Martinson, Robert. “What Works? Questions and Answers about Prison Reform”.
Clarendon, 1997.
34
1999.
Rex, Sue. “A New Form of Rehabilitation”, in von Hirsch, Andrew and Ashworth,
Ross, W.D. The Right and the Good. London: Oxford University Press, 1930.
(1980): 453-62.
Press, 2008.
Signler, Mary. “By the Light of Virtue: Prison Rape and the Corruption of Character”.
35
von Hirsch, Andrew. Doing Justice: The Choice of Punishments (Report of the
Committee for the Study of Incarceration). New York: Hill and Wang, 1976.
von Hirsch, Andrew and Ashworth, Andrew. Proportionate Sentencing. Oxford: Oxford
von Hirsch, Andrew and Jareborg, Nils. “Gauging Criminal Harm: A Living Standard
Analysis”. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies. (1991) 11: 1- 38. Republished with minor
Wootton, Barbara. Crime and the Criminal Law. London: Stevens, 1963.
36