Democracy and Development
Democracy and Development
• All adult members of the collectivity ought to have the status of citizens
(that is, there ought to be no restriction in political rights for different
groups of people within the polity; universal citizenship principle).
• All citizens ought to have the broadest set of political rights and liberties
possible, compatible with the extension of equal rights to all (that is, there
ought to be full equality and the broadest possible liberty for all citizens; the
liberty principle and the equality principle).
• Legislation ought to reflect the principle of the sovereignty of the people.
When and where legislation is required, it ought to result from a process
which involves the meaningful expression of interest and preference by all
citizens (popular sovereignty principle).
• The legislative process ought to weight no individual’s or group’s
preferences more heavily than those of any other individual or group (equal
weight principle).
• Finally, a democratic society is one that is fully subject to the rule of law:
legislation rather than personal authority produces limitations on individual
liberty, and legislation is neutral across persons (legality principle).
Democratic institutions
These represent the chief desiderata of a democratic polity. But these
principles do not dictate a specific implementation. Rather, it is necessary for a
1
4
given polity to design a set of political institutions through which the principles
of liberty, equality, and sovereignty are realized. There is a logical gap between
the principles and the institutional implementation, in the sense that people can
always debate whether the particulars of local institutions adequately realize the
relevant underlying values. It is likely, moreover, that different institutional
arrangements represent different ways of accommodating the underlying values,
and represent different types of tradeoffs among them.
In discussing institutional design it is useful to recall the discussion in
several different ways of aggregating and comparing multiple goods. A
democratic state is a complex system involving multiple features (electoral
institutions, parties, constitutional protections) and producing multiple goods
(individual liberty, effective legislation, secure property rights, popular
sovereignty). Institutions can be designed de novo, or they can be adjusted
through a series of corrections and reforms. And as we consider the process of
adjustment of an institution, it is necessary to consider carefully the “objective
function” by which we intend to guide the adjustment and reform process. Are
we willing to make tradeoffs among the goods produced by the institution—e.g.
give up some popular sovereignty in order to achieve more equality of assets?
Or do we mean to accept only Pareto-improving innovations—that is, those that
improve at least one good without reducing any other good?
2
6
polity
constitution no constitution
financiers. Finally, even the most autocratic regime must give some weight to
the preferences of the masses of the population. Coercion has its limits, and the
autocrat must remain aware of the potential of popular unrest in response to
unpopular policies (increases in staple prices, increases in taxes, reduction in
customary rights).
What are some of the common characteristics of authoritarian regimes?
Transition to democracy
It is common in recent history to find developing societies in a state of
transition from authoritarian regimes to democratic regimes. Military
dictatorships, bureaucratic oligarchies, and other authoritarian regimes have
found themselves subject to irresistible forces which compel them in the
direction of a degree of progressive democratic reform: extension of political
rights to citizens, establishment of limited electoral processes, extension of the
ability of independent parties to organize themselves, extension of some degree
of freedom of press, and so forth. Here a series of questions demand answer.
First, to what extent is it possible for skillful elites and rulers to orchestrate the
process of democratic liberalization in such a way as to preserve their power and
privilege within the resulting regime? Second, what are the features of
institutions which best serve to bring about effective democratization? Third, is
there a relatively clear distinction between effective democracies and sham
democracies? Finally, what if anything can we say about the progressive
features of hybrid political systems—polities that are intermediate between
authoritarianism and democracy? Are the steps along the road to democracy
unambiguously positive with regard to individual freedom and other democratic
virtues?
them)? Is there a principled basis on which others may criticize one’s scheme of
preferences? And, finally, is there an objective basis for saying that some of a
person’s preferences are more important than others—or that one person’s
preferences are more important than another’s? These problems are critical for
democratic theory, because collections of individual preferences underlie the
principle of popular sovereignty. If I prefer one zoning code over another
because I prefer to have silence in the neighborhood while doing my early
morning exercises, whereas you prefer the second option to the first because it
alone will allow you to earn your living—should your preferences be given
more weight than mine?
Empirical issues
To this point we have focused largely on the normative theory of
democracy. However, it is crucial to recognize that democratic institutions are
institutions—they have real empirical and causal properties, and function
according within the context of forces that give them a real empirical trajectory
that may be at odds with the ideal theory. So at this point in the story it is
appropriate to turn to a realist theory of democratic institutions, and to ask sharp
empirical questions about the actual characteristics and tendencies of democratic
political institutions.
Let us turn now to some of the empirical questions that surround the
issue of democracy within the context of developing societies. How do the
typical institutions of electoral democracy affect the process, character, and rate
of economic development? Do the institutions of electoral democracy have the
effect of inducing more egalitarian economic development? Do such institutions
serve to emphasize the interests of the poor? Can broader political participation
improve the situation of the poor?
of thought which holds that democracy is neither positive nor negative with
respect to economic development. ((Sirowy and Inkeles 1990) provides a
careful review of this issue and the empirical data that pertains to assessment of
the various hypotheses.)
The issue of the dynamic causal relations between democratic political
institutions and the pace and character of economic development can be probed
in several different ways. First, we can approach the problem theoretically or
deductively: given what we know about the character and institutional dynamics
of democratic institutions, and given what we know about the character and
needs of economic development, what causal connections does underlying
theory lead us to expect? Second, we can approach the problem through multi-
case studies in which we operationalize the concepts of democracy and rate and
character of development, and then examine to see whether there are meaningful
statistical associations among the resulting variables. Both approaches have
been pursued in the literature of the political economy of development, with
deeply mixed results.
Conflict theory
• Development requires decisive policy choice and effective policy
implementation; authoritarian regimes are more decisive and more effective
in implementing policy.
• Ethnic and sub-national conflicts interfere with economic development, and
are most effectively suppressed by strong authoritarian government.
10
Compatibility theory
• Progressive development requires policy choices that lead to a development
pathway that produces a wide distribution of the benefits of growth;
democratic regimes are more effective at producing wide distribution of
benefits (because of the strong tendency of authoritarian regimes to
structure economic activity towards “rent-seeking” activities, enrichment of
the ruling circle, and widespread corruption).
• democratic regimes are less prone to corruption and rent-seeking; they are
less “predatory”.
3
11
basis for conclusion about the causal properties of democratic institutions with
regard to development (Przeworski and Limongi 1993 : p. 60). Both of these
review essays point to the methodological difficulties that stand in the way of
effective statistical test of these causal hypotheses.4
This suggests, however, that it is reasonable to work on the assumption
that democratic institutions are compatible with effective economic
development.
4
12
channels through which elite interests can subvert the political goals of a party
of the poor. And second, there are structural constraints on the policies that such
a party can advocate, let alone implement, without creating an economic crisis
that worsens the condition of the poor.
6
13
groups, so that their collective action problems are more easily handled than
those of more numerous groups.7 These considerations suggest that elites are
well-positioned to defend their economic interests within an electoral
competition—with the result that they will be able to preserve the benefits of
pre-existing anti-poor biases in economic policies.
Second, to the extent that non-elite groups emerge as politically
significant it is possible, perhaps likely, that the groups that stand to gain the
most political influence through democratization are not the poor, but the near-
poor: urban workers and consumers, better-off farmers, and the like. And the
interests of these groups are not identical with those of the poor. Consider one
example of a process that is almost ubiquitous in the developing world: the
political influence of civil servants, urban workers, and urban consumers. These
groups have an interest in securing food price policies that guarantee lower food
costs; they have an interest in development strategies that enhance urban
amenities (transportation, sanitation); and they have an interest in wage policies
that favor them. Further, these groups are well-positioned to back up their
demands with effective political action: mobilization around political parties,
personal and political relationships with government officials, and the threat of
urban unrest. So it is common to find that LDC policies reflect an urban bias:
food price policies, provision of infrastructure, and wage policies that favor
urban workers and civil servants. These politically-created benefits have the
effect of improving the material welfare of these groups—but at the expense of
the rural poor. The result of these policies is to depress the market-determined
incomes of farmers, to reduce the level and quality of amenities flowing to the
rural sector, and to further exacerbate the wage differentials between rural and
urban sectors. A consequence of this line of analysis, then, is to raise the
possibility that more democracy may in fact reduce the amount of attention the
poor (and particularly the rural poor) receive within the politics of development
policy.8
These arguments are not intended to discredit the significance of
democratic institutions in furthering a poverty-first economic strategy. Indeed,
it is unlikely that such a strategy will emerge except through an effective,
politically competent demand for such a strategy by the rural poor, supported by
an effective and administratively competent party strongly committed to its
interests. But democratization is not the only ingredient of a successful poverty-
first policy, and arguments in preceding paragraphs are designed merely to show
that it is quite possible for democratic electoral mechanisms to lead to outcomes
that neglect the poor or are positively biased against them.
8
14