Paraconsistent Logic: 1. The Problem
Paraconsistent Logic: 1. The Problem
edu
Paraconsistent Logic
A paraconsistent logic is a way to reason about inconsistent information without lapsing into absurdity. In a non-paraconsistent logic, inconsistency explodes, in the sense that if a contradiction obtains, then everything (everything!) else obtains, too. Someone reasoning with a paraconsistent logic can begin with inconsistent premisessay, a moral dilemma, a Kantian antinomy, or a semantic paradoxand still reach sensible conclusions, without completely collapsing into incoherence. This article offers a brief discussion of some main ideas and approaches to paraconsistency developed to date. Modern logics are couched in the language of mathematics and formal symbolism. Nevertheless, this article is not a tutorial on the technical aspects of paraconsistency, but rather a synopsis of the underlying ideas. See the suggested readings for formal expositions, as well as historical material.
Table of Contents
1. 2. The Problem Logical Background 1. Definitions 2. Two Grades of Paraconsistency 3. Requirements for a Logic to Be Paraconsistent Schools of Paraconsistent Logic 1. Discussive Logic 2. Preservationism 3. Adaptive Logic 4. Relevance 5. Logics of Formal Inconsistency 6. Dialetheism Applications 1. Moral Dilemmas 2. Law, Science, and Belief Revision 3. Closed Theories Truth and Sets 1. Nave Axioms 2. Further Logical Restrictions 4. Learning, Beliefs, and AI Conclusion References and Further Reading
3.
4.
5. 6.
1. The Problem
Consider an example due to Alan Weir, concerning a political leader who absolutely, fundamentally believes in the sanctity of human life, and so believes that war is always wrong. All the same, a situation arises where her country must enter into war (else people will die, which is wrong). Entering into war will inevitably mean that some people will die. Plausibly, the political leader is now embroiled in a dilemma. This is exactly when paraconsistent inference is appropriate. Imagine our leader thinking, War is always wrong, but since we are going to war anyway, we may as well bomb civilians. Absurdist reasoning of this sort is not only bad logic, but just plain old bad. David Hume once wrote (1740, p. 633), I find myself involvd in such a labyrinth, that, I must confess, I neither know how to correct my former opinions, nor how to render them consistent. As Schotch and Jennings rightly point out, it is no good telling Hume that if his inconsistent opinions were, all of them, true then every sentence would be true. The best we could tell Hume is that at least some of his opinions are wrongbut this, so far from being news to Hume, was what occasioned much of the anguish he evidently felt (Schotch et al. p. 23). We want a way to keep sensible and reasonable even whenespecially whensuch problems arise. We need a way to keep from falling to irrational pieces when life, logic, mathematics or even philosophy leads us into paradox and conundrum. That is what paraconsistent logics are for.
2. Logical Background
a. Definitions
A logic is a set of well-formed formulae, along with an inference relation . The inference relation, also called logical consequence, may be specified syntactically or semantically, and tells us which formulae (conclusions) follow from which formulae (premises). When a sentence B follows from a bunch of sentences A0, A1, , An, we write A0, A1, , An B. When the relation holds, we say that the inference is valid. The set of all sentences that can be validly inferred in a logic is called a theory. A key distinction behind the entire paraconsistent enterprise is that between consistency and coherence. A theory is consistent if no pairs of contradictory sentences A, A are derivable, or alternatively iff no single sentence of the form A & A is derivable. Coherence is a broader notion, sometimes called absolute (as opposed to simple) consistency, and more often called non-triviality. A trivial or absurd theory is one in which absolutely every sentence holds. The idea of paraconsistency is that coherence is possible even without consistency. Put another way, a paraconsistent logician can say that a theory is inconsistent without meaning that the theory is incoherent, or absurd. The former is a structural feature of the theory, worth repair or further study; the latter means the theory has gone disastrously wrong. Paraconsistency gives us a principled way to resist equating contradiction with absurdity. In classical logic, the logic developed by Boole, Frege, Russell et al. in the late 1800s, and the logic almost always taught in university courses, has an inference relation according to which A, A B is valid. Here the conclusion, B, could be absolutely anything at all. Thus this inference is called ex contradictione quodlibet (from a contradiction, everything follows) or explosion. Paraconsistent logicians have urged that this feature of classical inference is incorrect. While the reasons for denying the validity of explosion will vary according to ones view of the role of logic, a basic claim is that the move from a contradiction to an arbitrary formula does not seem like reasoning. As the founders of relevant logic, Anderson and Belnap, urge in their canonical book Entailment, a proof submitted to a mathematics journal in which the essential steps fail to provide a reason to believe the conclusion, e.g. a proof by explosion, would be rejected out of hand.
Mark Colyvan (2008) illustrates the point by noting that no one has laid claim to a startlingly simple proof of the Riemann hypothesis: Riemanns Hypothesis: All the zeros of the zeta function have real part equal to 1/2. Proof: Let R stand for the Russell set, the set of all sets that are not members of themselves. It is straightforward to show that this set is both a member of itself and not a member of itself. Therefore, all the zeros of Riemanns zeta function have real part equal to 1/2. Needless to say, the Riemann hypothesis remains an open problem at time of writing. Minimally, paraconsistent logicians claim that there are or may be situations in which paraconsistency is a viable alternative to classical logic. This is a pluralist view, by which different logics are appropriate to different areas. Just as a matter of practical value, explosion does not seem like good advice for a person who is faced with a contradiction, as the quote from Hume above makes clear. More forcefully, paraconsistent logics make claim to being a better account of logic than the classical apparatus. This is closer to a monistic view, in which there is, essentially, one correct logic, and it is paraconsistent.
classically invalid inferences are going to become valid by dint of inconsistent information.) That is the whole ideathat classical logic allows too much, and especially given the possibility of inconsistency, we must be more discriminating. This is sometimes expressed by saying that paraconsistent logics are weaker than classical logic; but since paraconsistent logics are more flexible and apply to more situations, we neednt focus too much on the slang. Classical logic is in many ways more limited than paraconsistent logic (see 4c.). A third point, which we will take up in 3d, is that the invalidity of DS shows, essentially, that for the basic inference of modus ponens to be valid in all situations, we need a new logical connective for implication, not defined in terms of disjunction and negation. Now we turn to some weak and strong systems of paraconsistency.
b. Preservationism
Around 1978, the Candadian logicians Schotch and Jennings developed an approach to modal logic and paraconsistency that has some close affinities with the discussion approach. Their approach is now known as the preservationist school. The fundamental idea is that, given an inconsistent collection of premises, we should not try to reason about the collection of premises as a whole, but rather focus on internally consistent subsets of premises. Like discussion logics, preservationists see an important distinction between an inconsistent data set, like {A, A}, which is considered tractable, versus an outright contradiction like A & A, which is considered hopeless. The whole idea is summarized in a paraphrase of Gillman Payette, a major contributor to the preservationist program: Question: How do you reason from an inconsistent set of premises? Answer: You dont, since every formula follows in that case. You reason from consistent subsets of premises. Preservationists begin with an already defined logic X, usually classical logic. They assert that we, as fallible humans, are simply sometimes stuck with bad data; and this being the case, some kind of repair is needed on the logic X to insure coherence. Preservationists define the level of a set of premises to be the least number of cells into which the set must be divided for every cell to be internally consistent. They then define an inference relation, called forcing, in terms of the logic X, as follows: A set of sentences forces A iff there is at least one subset of such that A is an X-valid inference from . Forcing preserves the level of . If there is any consistency to preserve, forcing ensures that things do not get any more inconsistent. In particular, if a data set is inconsistent but contains no single-sentence contradictions, then the forcing relation is paraconsistent. Aside from paraconsistent applications, and roots in modal logic, preservationists have recently proved some deep theorems about logic more generally. Payette has shown, for example, that two logics are identical iff they assign any set of sentences the same level. Detour: Chunk and Permeate Closely related to the preservationist paradigm is a technique called chunk and permeate, developed by Bryson Brown and Graham Priest to explain the early differential calculus of Newton and Leibniz (see inconsistent mathematics). It is known that the early calculus involved contradictions of some kind, in particular, infinitesimal numbers that are sometimes identical to zero, and other times of a non-zero quantity. Brown and Priest show how reasoning about infinitesimals (and their related notions of derivatives) can be done coherently, by breaking up the reasoning into consistent chunks, and defining carefully controlled permeations between the chunks. The permeations show how enough but not too much information can pass from one chunk to another, and thus reconstruct how a correct mathematical solution can obtain from apparently inconsistent data.
c. Adaptive Logic
Taking applied examples from scientific reasoning as its starting point, the adaptive logic program considers systems in which the rules of inference themselves can change as we go along. The logics are dynamic. In dynamic logics, rules of inference change as a function of what has been derived to that point, and so some sentences which were derivable at a point in time are no longer derivable, and vice versa. The program has been developed by Dederik Batens and his school in Ghent. The idea is that our commitments may entail a belief that we nevertheless reject. This is because, as humans, our knowledge is not closed under logical consequence and so we are not fully aware of all the consequences of our commitments. When we find ourselves confronted with a problem, there may be two kinds of dynamics at work. In external dynamics, a conclusion may be withdrawn given some new information; logics in which this is allowed are called non-monotonic. External dynamics are widely recognized and are also important to the preservationist program. In internal dynamics, the premises themselves may lead to a conclusion being withdrawn. This kind of dynamic is less recognized and is more properly within the ambit of paraconsistency. Sometimes, we do derive a consequence we later reject, without modifying our convictions. Adaptive systems work by recognizing abnormalities, and deploying formal strategies. Both of these notions are defined specifically to the task at hand; for instance, an abnormality might be an inconsistency, or it might be an inductive inference, and a strategy might be to delete a line of a proof, or to change an inference rule. The base paraconsistent logic studied by the adaptive school is called CLuN, which is all of the positive (negation-free) fragment of classical logic, plus the law of excluded middle A A.
d. Relevance
Relevant logic is not fundamentally about issues of consistency and contradiction. Instead the chief motivation of relevant logic is that, for an argument to be valid, the premises must have a meaningful connection to the conclusion. For example, classical inferences like B A B, or (A B) A, seem to relevance logicians to fail as decent logical inferences. The requirement that premises be relevant to the conclusion delivers a paraconsistent inference relation as a byproduct, since in ex contradictione quodlibet, the premises A and A do not have anything to do with an arbitrary conclusion B. Relevant logic begins with Ackermann, and was properly developed in the work of Anderson and Belnap. Many of the founders of relevant logic, such as Robert Meyer and Richard Routley, have also been directly concerned with paraconsistency. From our perspective, one of the most important aspects of relevant logic is that it provides an implication connective that obeys modus ponens, even in inconsistent situations. In 2c, we saw that the disjunctive syllogism is not paraconsistently valid; and so in any logic in which implication is defined by negation and disjunction, modus ponens is invalid, too. That is, A B := A B does not, as we saw in 2c above, define a conditional that obeys A, A B B. In the argot, we say that hook is not detachable or ponenable. In relevant logic, implication A B is not defined with truth-functional connectives at all, but rather is defined either axiomatically or semantically (with worlds or algebraic semantics). Going this way, one can have a very robust implication connective, in which not only modus ponens is valid, A B, A; therefore, B. Other widely used inferences obtain, too. Lets just mention a few that involve negation in ways that might seem suspect from a paraconsistent point of view. We can have contraposition A B B A, which gives us modus tollens A B, B A. With the law of non-contradiction (A & A), this gives us reductio ad absurdum, in two forms, A (B & B) A, A A A, and consequentia mirabilis: A A A. Evidently the relevant arrow restores a lot of power apparently lost in the invalidity of disjunctive syllogism. There are a great number of relevant logics differing in strength. One can do away with the laws of non-contradiction and excluded middle, giving a very weak consistent paraconsistent logic called B (for basic). Or one can add powerful negation principles as we have just seen above for inconsistent but nontrivial logics. The relevant approach was used in Meyers attempt to found a paraconsistent arithmetic in a logic called R# (see inconsistent mathematics). It has also been used by Brady for nave set theory (4c), and, more recently, Beall for truth theory. On the other hand, relevant logics validate fewer entailments than classical logic; in order for A B to be valid, we have additional requirements of relevance besides truth preservation in all possible circumstances. Because of this, it is often difficult to recapture within a relevant logic some of classical mathematical reasoning. We return to this problem in 4c below.
mathematics (with applications to physics), and his attitude toward paraconsistency is more open minded than some of the others we have seen. Da Costa considers the investigation of inconsistent but not trivial theories as akin to the study of non-Euclidean geometry. He has been an advocate of paraconsistency not only for its pragmatic benefits, for example in reconstructing infinitesimal calculus, but also as an investigation of novel structure for its own sake. He gives the following methodological guidelines: In these calculi, the principle of contradiction should not be generally valid; From two contradictory statements it should not in general be possible to deduce any statement whatever; The extension of these calculi to quantification calculi should be immediate. Note that da Costas first principle is not like any weve seen so far, and his third is more ambitious than others. His main system is an infinite hierarchy of logics known as the C systems. The main idea of the C systems is to track which sentences are consistent and to treat these differently than sentences that may be inconsistent. Following this method, first of all, means that the logic itself is about inconsistency (hence the more recent name, logics of formal inconsistency). The logic can model how a person can or should reason about inconsistent information. Secondly, this gives us a principled way to make our paraconsistent logic as much like classical logic as possible: When all the sentences are marked as consistent, they can be safely reasoned about in a classical way, for example, using disjunctive syllogism. To make this work, we begin with a base logic, called C(0). When a sentence A behaves consistently in C(0), we mark it according to this definition: A0 := (A & A). Then, a strong kind of negation can be defined: A := A & A0. The logic with these two connectives added to it, we call C(1). In C(1) then we can have inferences like A B, A, A0 B. And in the same way that we reached C(1), we could go on and define a logic C(2), with an operator A1 = (A0)0, that means something like behaves consistently in C(1). The C systems continue up to the first transfinite ordinal, C(). These logics have been used to model some actual mathematics. The axioms of ZermeloFraenkel set theory and some postulates about identity (=) can be added to C(1), as can axioms asserting the existence of a universal set and a Russell set. This yields an inconsistent, non-trivial set theory. Arruda and Batens obtained some early results in this set theory. Work in arithmetic, infinitesimal calculus, and model theory has also been carried out by da Costa and his students. A driving idea of da Costas paraconsistency is that the law of non-contradiction (A & A) should not hold at the propositional level. This is, philosophically, how his approach works: (A & A) is not true. Aside from some weak relevant logics, this is a unique feature of the C systems (among paraconsistent logics). In other schools like the discussion and preservationist schools, non-contradiction holds not only at the level of sentences, but as a normative rule; and in the next school we consider, non-contradiction is false, but it is true as well.
f. Dialetheism
The best reason to study paraconsistency, and to use it for developing theories, would be if there were actually contradictions in the world (as opposed to in our beliefs or theories). That is, if it turns out that the best and truest description of the world includes some inconsistency, then paraconsistency is not only required, but is in some sense natural and appropriate. Dialetheism is a neologism meaning two-way truth and is the thesis that some sentences are both true and false, at the same time and in the same way. Dialetheism is particularly motivated as a response to the liar paradox and set theoretic antinomies like Russells Paradox, and was pioneered by Richard Routley and Graham Priest in Australia in the 1970s. Priest continues to be the best known proponent. A dialetheic logic is easiest to understand as a many-valued logic. This is not the only way to understand dialetheism, and the logic we are about to consider is not the only logic a dialetheist could use. Dialetheism is not a logic. But here is a simple way to introduce the concept. In addition to the truthvalues true and false, sentences can also be both. This third value is a little unusual, maybe, but uncomplicated: if a sentence A is both, then A is true, and A is false, and vice versa. The most straightforward application of a both truth-value is Priests logic of paradox, or LP. In LP the standard logical connectives have a natural semantics, which can be deduced following the principle that a sentence is designated iff it is at least truei.e. iff it is true only, or both true and false. If A is true when A is false, and A is false when A is true, for example, then A is both iff A is both. So inconsistent negation is something like a fixed point. An argument is valid in LP iff it is not possible for the conclusion to be completely false but all the premises at least true. That is, suppose we have premises that are all either true or both. If the argument is valid, then the conclusion is also at least true. In LP, any sentence of the form (A & A) is always true, and also some instances are sometimes false. So the law of non-contradiction is itself a dialetheia the schema (A & A) is universal but also has counterexamplesand furthermore, dialetheism says of itself that it is both true and false. (The statement there are true contradictions is both truethere are someand falseall contradictions are false.) This may seem odd, but it is appropriate, given dialetheisms origins in the liar paradox. LP uses only extensional connectives (and, or, not) and so has no detachable conditional. If one adds to LP a detachable conditional, then, given its semantics, the most natural extension of LP to a logic with an implication connective is the logic called RM3. Unfortunately, this logic is not appropriate for nave set theory or truth theory (see 4c.ii). If a fourth neutral truth value is added to LP, the logic is weakened to the system of first degree entailment FDE. In FDE, the inference B A A is not valid any more than explosion is. This makes some sense, since if the former is invalid by dint of not representing actual reasoning, then the latter
should be invalid, too, since the premise does not lead to the conclusion. Because of this, FDE has no theorems, of the form A, at all.
4. Applications
A paraconsistent logic becomes useful when we are faced with inconsistencies. Motivations for and applications of paraconsistency arise from situations that are plausibly inconsistentthat is, situations in which inconsistency is not merely due to careless mistakes or confusion, but rather inconsistency that is not easily dispelled even upon careful and concentrated reflection. A student making an arithmetic error does not need a paraconsistent logic, but rather more arithmetic tutorials (although see inconsistent mathematics). On the other hand, people in the following situations may turn to a paraconsistent toolkit.
a. Moral Dilemmas
A mother gives birth to identical conjoined twins (in an example due to Helen Bohse). Doctors quickly assess that if the twins are not surgically separated, then neither will survive. However, doctors also know only one of the babies can survive surgery. The babies are completely identical in all respects. It seems morally obligatory to save one of life at the expense of the other. But because there is nothing to help choose which baby, it also seems morally wrong to let one baby die rather than the other. Quite plausibly, this is an intractable moral dilemma with premises of the form we ought to save the baby on the left, and, by symmetrical reasoning about the baby on the right, also we ought not to save the baby on the left. This is not yet technically a contradiction, but unless some logical precautions are taken, it is a tragic situation on the verge of rational disaster. A moral dilemma takes the form O(A) and O(A), that it is obligatory to do A and it is obligatory to do A. In standard deontic logica logic of moral obligationswe can argue from a moral dilemma to moral explosion as follows (see Routley and Plumwood 1989). First, obligations aggregate: O(A), O(A) O(A & A). Next, note that A & A is equivalent to (A & A) & B. (Equivalent here can mean classically, or in the sense of C. I. Lewis strict implication.) Thus O(A & A) O((A & A) & B) But O((A & A) & B) O(B). So we have shown from inconsistent obligations O(A), O(A), that O(B), that anything whatsoever is obligatoryin standard, non-paraconsistent systems. A paraconsistent deontic logic can follow any of the schools we have seen already. A standard paraconsistent solution is to follow the non-adjunctive approach of Jakowski and the preservationists. One can block the rule of modal aggregation, so that both O(A), O(A) may hold without implying O(A & A). Alternatively, one could deny that A & A is strictly equivalent to (A & A) & B, by adopting a logic (such as a relevant logic) in which such an equivalence fails. Taking this path, we would then run into the principle of deontic consistency, O(A) P(A), that if you ought to do A, then it is permissible to do A. (You are not obliged not to do A.) Accordingly, from O(A & A), we get P(A & A). If we had the further axiom that inconsistent actions are not permitted, then we would now have a full blown inconsistency, P(A & A) and P(A & A). If reductio is allowed, then we would also seem to have obligations such that O(A) and O(A). This move calls attention to which obligations are consistent. One could drop deontic consistency, so that A is obligatory without necessarily being permissible. Or one could reason that, however odd inconsistent actions may sound, there is no obvious reason they should be impermissible. The result would be strange but harmless statements of the form P(A & A). A principle even stronger than deontic consistency is the Kantian dictum that ought implies can, where can means basic possibility. Kants dictum converts moral dilemmas to explicit contradictions. This seems to rule out moral dilemmas, since it is not possible, e.g., both to save and not to save a baby from our conjoined twins example, it is not obligatory to save one of the two babies, appearances to the contrary. So an option for the paraconsistent deontic logician is to deny Kants dictum. Perhaps we have unrealizable obligations; indeed, this seems to be the intuition behind moral dilemmas. A consequence of denying Kants dictum is that, sometimes, we inevitably do wrong. Most liberally, one can keep everything and accept that sometimes inconsistent action is possible. For example, if I make a contract with you to break this very contract, then I break the contract if and only if I keep it. By signing, I am eo ipso breaking and not breaking the contract. In general, though, how one could do both A and its negation is a question beyond the scope of logic.
using paraconsistency is, at least to start with, straightforward. We will look at two paradigm cases, followed by some detail on how they can be pursued. i. Nave Axioms In modern logic we present formal, mathematical descriptions of how sentences are true and false, e.g. (A & B) is true iff A is true and B is true. This itself is a rational statement, presumably governed by some logic and so itself amenable to formal study. To reason about it logically, we would need to study the truth predicate, x is true. An analysis of the concept of truth that is almost too-obviously correct is the schema T(A) iff A. It seems so obviousuntil (even when?) a sentence like This sentence of the IEP is false, a liar paradox which leads to a contradiction, falls out the other side. A paraconsistent logic can be used for a theory of truth in which the truth schema is maintained, but where either the derivation of the paradox is blocked (by dropping the law of excluded middle) or else the contradiction is not explosive. In modern set theory, similarly, we understand mathematical objects as being built out of sets, where each set is itself built out of pre-given sets. The resulting picture is the iterative hierarchy of sets. The problem is that the iterative hierarchy itself is a mathematically definite object, but cannot itself reside on the hierarchy. A closed theory of sets will include objects like this, beginning from an analysis of the concept of set that is almost too-obviously correct: the nave comprehension schema, x is a member of {y: A(y)} iff A(x). A way to understand what nave comprehension means is to take it as the claim: any collection of objects is a set, which is itself an object. Nave set theory can be studied, and has been, with paraconsistent logics; see inconsistent mathematics. Contradictions like the existence of a Russell set {y: y is not a member of y} arise but are simply theorems: natural parts of the theory; they do not explode the theory. ii. Further Logical Restrictions For both nave truth theory and nave set theory, there is an additional and extremely important restriction on the logic. A logic for these schemas cannot validate contraction, If (if A then (if A then B)), then (if A then B). This restriction is due to Currys paradox, which is a stronger form of the liar paradox. A Curry sentence says If this sentence is true, then everything is true. If the Curry sentence, call it C, is put into the truth-schema, then everything follows by the principle of contraction:
1) T(C) iff (if T(C) then everything). 2) If T(C) then (if T(C) then everything). 3) If T(C) then everything. 4) T(C) 5) Everything. [truth schema] [from 1] [from 2 by contraction] [modus ponens on 1, 3] [modus ponens on 3, 4]
Since not everything is true, if the T schema is correct then contraction is invalid. For set theory, analogously, the Curry set is C = {x: If x is a member of x, then everything is true}, and a similar argument establishes triviality. As was discovered later by Dunn, Meyer and Routley while studying nave set theory in relevant logic, the sentence (A & (A B)) B is a form of contraction too, and so must similarly not be allowed. (Let A be a Curry sentence and B be absurdity.) Calling this sentence (schema) invalid is different than blocking modus ponens, which is an inference, validated by a rule. The above sentence, meanwhile, is just thata sentenceand we are saying whether or not all its instances are true. If nave truth and set theories are coherent, instances of this sentence are not always true, even when modus ponens is valid. The logic LP does not satisfy contraction and so a dialetheic truth or set theory can be embedded in it. Some basic contradictions, like the liar paradox and Russells paradox, do obtain, as do a few core operations. Because LP has no conditional, though, one does not get very far. Most other paraconsistent logics cannot handle nave set theory and nave truth theory as stated here. A hard problem in (strong) paraconsistency, then, is how to formulate the iff in our nave schemata, and in general how to formulate a suitable conditional. The most promising candidates to date have been relevant logics, though as we have seen there are strict limitations.
decision functions, and the unsolvability of the halting problem, are both proved by reductio ad absurdum: if a universal decision procedure were to exist, it would have some contradictions as outputs. Classically, this has been interpreted to mean that there is no such procedure. But, Sylvan suggests, there is more on heaven and Earth than is dreamt of in classical theories of computation.
5. Conclusion
Paraconsistency may be minimally construed as the doctrine that not everything is true, even if some contradictions are. Most paraconsistent logicians subscribe to views on the milder end of the spectrum; most paraconsistent logicians are actually much more conservative than a slur like Quines deviant logician might suggest. On the other hand, taking paraconsistency seriously means on some level taking inconsistency seriously, something that a classically minded person will not do. It has therefore been thought that, insofar as true inconsistency is an unwelcome thoughtmad, bad, and dangerous to knowparaconsistency might be some kind of gateway to darker doctrines. After all, once one has come to rational grips with the idea that inconsistent data may still make sense, what, really, stands in the way of inconsistent data being true? This has been called the slippery slope from weak to strong paraconsistency. Note that the slippery slope, while proposed as an attractive thought by those more inclined to strong paraconsistency, could seem to go even further, away from paraconsistency completely and toward the insane idea of trivialism: that everything really is true. That is, contradictions obtain, but explosion is also still valid. Why not? No one, paraconsistentist or otherwise, is a trivialist. Nor is paraconsistency an invitation to trivilalism, even if it is a temptation to dialetheism. By analogy, when Hume pointed out that we cannot be certain that the sun will rise tomorrow, no one became seriously concerned about the possibility. But people did begin to wonder about the necessity of the laws of nature, and no one now can sit as comfortably as before Hume awoke us from our dogmatic slumber. So too with paraconsistent logic. In one sense, paraconsistent logics can do much more than classical logics. But in studying paraconsistency, especially strong paraconsistency closer to the dialetheic end of the spectrum, we see that there are many things logic cannot do. Logic alone cannot tell us what is true or false. Simply writing down the syntactic marking A does nothing to show us that A cannot be false, even if A is a theorem. There is no absolute safeguard. Defending consistency, or denying the absurdity of trivialism, is ultimately not the job of logic alone. Affirming coherence and denying absurdity is an act, a job for human beings.
Philosophy of Mathematics: Set Theory, Measuring Theories and Nominalism, Frankfurt: Verlag, 2008, pp. 2839. Hume, David (1740). A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge. Second edition 1978. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Author Information
Zach Weber University of Melbourne Email: zweber@unimelb.edu.au University of Sydney Email: z.weber@usyd.edu.au
Article printed from Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://www.iep.utm.edu/para-log/ Copyright 2010 The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. All rights reserved.