0% found this document useful (0 votes)
58 views35 pages

3066 ch03

Uploaded by

Siti nurpiah
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPT, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
58 views35 pages

3066 ch03

Uploaded by

Siti nurpiah
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPT, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 35

Chapter 3

PREFERENCES AND UTILITY

Copyright ©2005 by South-Western, a division of Thomson Learning. All rights reserved. 1


Axioms of Rational Choice
• Completeness
– if A and B are any two situations, an
individual can always specify exactly one of
these possibilities:
• A is preferred to B
• B is preferred to A
• A and B are equally attractive

2
Axioms of Rational Choice
• Transitivity
– if A is preferred to B, and B is preferred to
C, then A is preferred to C
– assumes that the individual’s choices are
internally consistent

3
Axioms of Rational Choice
• Continuity
– if A is preferred to B, then situations suitably
“close to” A must also be preferred to B
– used to analyze individuals’ responses to
relatively small changes in income and
prices

4
Utility
• Given these assumptions, it is possible to
show that people are able to rank in order
all possible situations from least desirable
to most
• Economists call this ranking utility
– if A is preferred to B, then the utility assigned
to A exceeds the utility assigned to B
U(A) > U(B)

5
Utility
• Utility rankings are ordinal in nature
– they record the relative desirability of
commodity bundles
• Because utility measures are not unique,
it makes no sense to consider how much
more utility is gained from A than from B
• It is also impossible to compare utilities
between people

6
Utility
• Utility is affected by the consumption of
physical commodities, psychological
attitudes, peer group pressures, personal
experiences, and the general cultural
environment
• Economists generally devote attention to
quantifiable options while holding
constant the other things that affect utility
– ceteris paribus assumption
7
Utility
• Assume that an individual must choose
among consumption goods x1, x2,…, xn
• The individual’s rankings can be shown
by a utility function of the form:
utility = U(x1, x2,…, xn; other things)
– this function is unique up to an order-
preserving transformation

8
Economic Goods
• In the utility function, the x’s are assumed
to be “goods”
– more is preferred to less
Quantity of y
Preferred to x*, y*

y*

?
Worse
than
x*, y* Quantity of x
x* 9
Utility and the MRS
• Suppose an individual’s preferences for
hamburgers (y) and soft drinks (x) can
be represented by
utility  10  x  y
• Solving for y, we get
y = 100/x

• Solving for MRS = -dy/dx:


MRS = -dy/dx = 100/x2
10
Utility and the MRS
MRS = -dy/dx = 100/x2
• Note that as x rises, MRS falls
– when x = 5, MRS = 4
– when x = 20, MRS = 0.25

11
Marginal Utility
• Suppose that an individual has a utility
function of the form
utility = U(x,y)
• The total differential of U is
U U
dU  dx  dy
x y

• Along any indifference curve, utility is


constant (dU = 0)
12
Deriving the MRS
• Therefore, we get:
U
 x
dy
MRS  
dx Uconstant
U
y
• MRS is the ratio of the marginal utility of
x to the marginal utility of y

13
Diminishing Marginal Utility
and the MRS
• Intuitively, it seems that the assumption
of decreasing marginal utility is related to
the concept of a diminishing MRS
– diminishing MRS requires that the utility
function be quasi-concave
• this is independent of how utility is measured
– diminishing marginal utility depends on how
utility is measured
• Thus, these two concepts are different
14
Convexity of Indifference
Curves
• Suppose that the utility function is

utility  x  y
• We can simplify the algebra by taking the
logarithm of this function
U*(x,y) = ln[U(x,y)] = 0.5 ln x + 0.5 ln y

15
Convexity of Indifference
Curves
• Thus,

U * 0.5
MRS  x  x 
y
U * 0.5 x
y y

16
Convexity of Indifference
Curves
• If the utility function is
U(x,y) = x + xy + y
• There is no advantage to transforming
this utility function, so
U
x 1 y
MRS  
U 1  x
y
17
Convexity of Indifference
Curves
• Suppose that the utility function is
utility  x 2  y 2

• For this example, it is easier to use the


transformation
U*(x,y) = [U(x,y)]2 = x2 + y2

18
Convexity of Indifference
Curves
• Thus,

U *
MRS  x 
2x x

U * 2y y
y

19
Examples of Utility Functions
• Cobb-Douglas Utility
utility = U(x,y) = xy
where  and  are positive constants
– The relative sizes of  and  indicate the
relative importance of the goods

20
Examples of Utility Functions
• Perfect Substitutes
utility = U(x,y) = x + y
Quantity of y
The indifference curves will be linear.
The MRS will be constant along the
indifference curve.

U3

U2
U1
Quantity of x
21
Examples of Utility Functions
• Perfect Complements
utility = U(x,y) = min (x, y)
Quantity of y
The indifference curves will be
L-shaped. Only by choosing more
of the two goods together can utility
be increased.

U3

U2

U1
Quantity of x
22
Examples of Utility Functions
• CES Utility (Constant elasticity of
substitution)
utility = U(x,y) = x/ + y/
when   0 and
utility = U(x,y) = ln x + ln y
when  = 0
– Perfect substitutes   = 1
– Cobb-Douglas   = 0
– Perfect complements   = -
23
Examples of Utility Functions
• CES Utility (Constant elasticity of
substitution)
– The elasticity of substitution () is equal to
1/(1 - )
• Perfect substitutes   = 
• Fixed proportions   = 0

24
Homothetic Preferences
• If the MRS depends only on the ratio of
the amounts of the two goods, not on
the quantities of the goods, the utility
function is homothetic
– Perfect substitutes  MRS is the same at
every point
– Perfect complements  MRS =  if y/x >
/, undefined if y/x = /, and MRS = 0 if
y/x < /
25
Homothetic Preferences
• For the general Cobb-Douglas function,
the MRS can be found as
U
 1 
x  x y  y
MRS    1  
U x y  x
y

26
Nonhomothetic Preferences
• Some utility functions do not exhibit
homothetic preferences
utility = U(x,y) = x + ln y

U
MRS  x 1
 y
U 1
y y

27
The Many-Good Case
• Suppose utility is a function of n goods
given by
utility = U(x1, x2,…, xn)
• The total differential of U is

U U U
dU  dx1  dx2  ...  dxn
x1 x2 xn

28
The Many-Good Case
• We can find the MRS between any two
goods by setting dU = 0
U U
dU  0  dxi  dx j
xi x j

• Rearranging, we get
U
dx j x i
MRS( x i for x j )   
dx i U
x j 29
Multigood Indifference
Surfaces
• We will define an indifference surface
as being the set of points in n
dimensions that satisfy the equation
U(x1,x2,…xn) = k
where k is any preassigned constant

30
Multigood Indifference
Surfaces
• If the utility function is quasi-concave,
the set of points for which U  k will be
convex
– all of the points on a line joining any two
points on the U = k indifference surface will
also have U  k

31
Important Points to Note:
• If individuals obey certain behavioral
postulates, they will be able to rank all
commodity bundles
– the ranking can be represented by a utility
function
– in making choices, individuals will act as if
they were maximizing this function
• Utility functions for two goods can be
illustrated by an indifference curve map
32
Important Points to Note:
• The negative of the slope of the
indifference curve measures the marginal
rate of substitution (MRS)
– the rate at which an individual would trade
an amount of one good (y) for one more unit
of another good (x)
• MRS decreases as x is substituted for y
– individuals prefer some balance in their
consumption choices
33
Important Points to Note:
• A few simple functional forms can capture
important differences in individuals’
preferences for two (or more) goods
– Cobb-Douglas function
– linear function (perfect substitutes)
– fixed proportions function (perfect
complements)
– CES function
• includes the other three as special cases
34
Important Points to Note:
• It is a simple matter to generalize from
two-good examples to many goods
– studying peoples’ choices among many
goods can yield many insights
– the mathematics of many goods is not
especially intuitive, so we will rely on two-
good cases to build intuition

35

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy