Social Insurance Notes
Social Insurance Notes
New Function of
Government
Emmanuel Skoufias
LKY School
2023-24:S2
1 of 38
Social Insurance: The New Function of Government
2 of 38
Social Insurance: The New Function of
Government
3 of 38
Government Spending by Function,1953 and
2014
1953 2014
Defense 69.4% 17.2%
Disability and 5.0 14.7
Unemployment
Social Security 3.6 24.3
Health 0.4 26.4
Other 21.6 17.5
4 of 38
Social Insurance: The New Function of
Government
5 of 38
What Is Insurance?
6 of 38
Why Do Individuals Value Insurance?
7 of 38
Why Do Individuals Value Insurance?
Diminishing Marginal Utility
8 of 38
Formalizing This Intuition: Expected Utility
Model
9 of 38
The Expected Utility Model: Health insurance
10 of 38
Full Insurance Is Optimal
11 of 38
Full Insurance Is Optimal
12 of 38
The Role of Risk Aversion
13 of 38
Why Have Social Insurance? Asymmetric
Information and Adverse Selection
14 of 38
Adverse Selection Example
15 of 38
Insurer Breaks Even with Full Information
Pricing
16 of 38
Asymmetric Information Pricing: Separate
17 of 38
Asymmetric Information Pricing: Separate
18 of 38
The Problem of Adverse Selection
19 of 38
Does Asymmetric Information Necessarily Lead
to
Market Failure?
21 of 38
APPLICATION: Adverse Selection and Health
Insurance “Death Spirals”
22 of 38
How Does the Government Address Adverse
Selection?
23 of 38
Other Reasons for Government Intervention in
Insurance Markets
24 of 38
APPLICATION: Flood Insurance and the
Samaritan’s Dilemma
25 of 38
APPLICATION: Flood Insurance and the
Samaritan’s Dilemma
• NFIP has paid out $51.1 billion since 1969 and has
lead to improved building standards.
• But nearly half of the victims of Hurricane Katrina in
2005 did not have flood insurance, and the claims of
people with insurance bankrupted the system.
• NFIP failed in part because people avoid buying flood
insurance if they are assured the government is going
to continue to help individuals in disaster areas.
• Acts were passed in 2012 and 2014 to more
accurately price flood insurance and control the rate
adjustments for flood insurance premiums in
vulnerable areas.
26 of 38
Social Insurance versus Self-Insurance: How
Much Consumption Smoothing?
27 of 38
Example: Unemployment Insurance
28 of 38
Example: Unemployment Insurance
29 of 38
Example: Unemployment Insurance
30 of 38
Lessons for Consumption-Smoothing Role of
Social Insurance
31 of 38
The Problem with Insurance: Moral Hazard
32 of 38
APPLICATION: The Problems with Assessing
Workers’ Compensation Injuries
34 of 38
The Problem with Insurance: Moral Hazard
35 of 38
The Consequences of Moral Hazard
36 of 38
Putting It All Together: Optimal Social Insurance
37 of 38
Conclusion
38 of 38
39 of 38
Chetty and Looney
• Studies of risk in developing economies have focused on
consumption fluctuations as a measure of the value of
insurance. A common view in the literature is that the welfare
costs of risk and benefits of social insurance are small if
income shocks do not cause large consumption fluctuations.
• They present a simple model showing that this conclusion is
incorrect if the consumption path is smooth because
individuals are highly risk averse. Hence, social safety nets
could be valuable in low-income economies even when
consumption is not very sensitive to shocks.
• Small consumption fluctuations need not imply that existing
insurance is “adequate” in developing economies. In fact, the
converse may be true: consumption may be smooth precisely
because the welfare costs of consumption fluctuations are
very high.
40 of 38
Chetty and Looney
• To evaluate the welfare consequences of insurance policies,
one must determine why and how households smooth
consumption—because of high risk aversion (high γ) or
through good insurance arrangements (low θb)? This question
is of practical relevance because many households in low-
income countries could have high γ, e.g. due to subsistence
constraints. Evidence that household resort to costly
consumption-smoothing mechanisms (e.g. Frankenberg et al.,
1999; Dercon, 2002; Miguel, 2005; Chetty and Looney, in
press) also suggests that γ could potentially be high for many
households. Distinguishing between the two explanations of
consumption smoothness would be a useful direction for
future research on risk and insurance
41 of 38
Expected Utility Model
• The model is described by the following parameters:
– You are hit by the car with some probability p.
– Your income is W, regardless of whether you get hit or not.
– However, if you get hit, you incur medical costs d.
– You can buy insurance, with premium m per dollar of insurance.
• That insurance will pay you $b if you are hit by the car. In this case, we can write
your expected utility (EU) as
EU = (1 -p)*U(W - mb) + p*U(W – d – mb + b)
• The problem with this expression is that we have one equation, with two
unknowns (m and b). To solve this equation, we need to add one more condition:
that insurance is priced in an actuarially fair manner, so that insurance companies
make zero expected profits (we assume, for now, zero administrative costs). In that
case, the zero expected profit (E) condition for the insurer is
E mb - pb = 0
Or premiums received (mb) minus expected benefits paid out (pb), equals zero.
42 of 38
Expected Utility Model
This, in turn, implies that the premium equals
That is, if the risk is 10%, then m =10¢ per dollar of insurance. We can now go back
and maximize expected utility by plugging in b from this equation. As in the example in
the text, we assume that utility is of the form , So maximize
Setting this equal to zero and solving for the optimal level of insurance benefits (b*),
we get b*= d. That is, individuals should buy enough insurance so that if they have the
adverse outcome, their benefits exactly offset their costs: individuals should buy full
insurance to smooth their consumption across states.
43 of 38
Expected Utility Model
Another way to see this is to plug the optimal benefit level (b*=d) back into the utility
function:
That is, we obtain the result that consumption is equalized ( ) in both states of the
world.
Thus, facing actuarially fair insurance markets, individuals will want to insure
themselves fully against risk.
44 of 38
Adverse Selection
To understand more formally the implications of adverse selection, we now consider
two groups, the careful and the careless, where the probability of accident for the
careful is pc, and the probability of accident for the careless is pa > pc.
With full information, then the insurance company charges prices
• ma=b*pa for the careless, and
• mc=b*pc for the careful.
Thus, the premium for the careless is higher, since pa > pc; those who are more likely
to have an accident have to pay more for insurance.
45 of 38
Adverse Selection
If there isn’t full information, so that insurance companies know only the proportions
of types in the population, then there are two possible pricing strategies.
One is to assume that individuals are honest and charge them according to their
reported types. However, as discussed, this strategy will lead all individuals to claim
that they are careful. In this world, the profits earned on the careful are:
that is, the insurance company breaks even on the share of the population that is
careful. However, the profits earned on the careless are
since pa > pc profits are negative overall and thus insurance is not offered.
46 of 38
Adverse Selection
The other strategy is to offer insurance at an average price, mv, that is based on the
average of the accident probabilities pa > pv > pc. At this price, insurance is a good
deal for the careless but a bad deal for the careful, and may be bought only by the
careless. In that case, the expected profits of the insurer are again negative:
since pa >pv
So even with this alternative strategy (offering insurance at an average price based on
the accident probabilities) expected profits or insurer are negative and insurance may
not be offered Market failure
47 of 38
Adverse Selection
NOTE: It is possible, however, that the careful still would buy full insurance (the
pooling equilibrium). For example, they would buy insurance if expected utility with
insurance (at the unfair price) is still higher than expected utility without insurance;
that is, if
>
where
48 of 38