0% found this document useful (0 votes)
31 views25 pages

18 Propositional Logic First Order Logic 27-02-2024

Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPTX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
31 views25 pages

18 Propositional Logic First Order Logic 27-02-2024

Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPTX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 25

First-Order Logic: Review

1
First-order logic
• First-order logic (FOL) models the world in terms of
• Objects, which are things with individual identities
• Properties of objects that distinguish them from other objects
• Relations that hold among sets of objects
• Functions, which are a subset of relations where there is only one “value”
for any given “input”
• Examples:
• Objects: Students, lectures, companies, cars ...
• Relations: Brother-of, bigger-than, outside, part-of, has-color, occurs-after,
owns, visits, precedes, ...
• Properties: blue, oval, even, large, ...
• Functions: father-of, best-friend, second-half, one-more-than ...
2
User provides
• Constant symbols, which represent individuals in the world
• Mary
•3
• Green
• Function symbols, which map individuals to individuals
• father-of(Mary) = John
• color-of(Sky) = Blue
• Predicate symbols, which map individuals to truth values
• greater(5,3)
• green(Grass)
• color(Grass, Green)
3
FOL Provides
• Variable symbols
• E.g., x, y, foo
• Connectives
• Same as in PL: not (), and (), or (), implies (), if and only if
(biconditional )
• Quantifiers
• Universal x or (Ax)
• Existential x or (Ex)

4
Sentences are built from terms and atoms

• A term (denoting a real-world individual) is a constant symbol, a


variable symbol, or an n-place function of n terms.
x and f(x1, ..., xn) are terms, where each xi is a term.
A term with no variables is a ground term
• An atomic sentence (which has value true or false) is an n-place
predicate of n terms
• A complex sentence is formed from atomic sentences connected by the
logical connectives:
P, PQ, PQ, PQ, PQ where P and Q are sentences
• A quantified sentence adds quantifiers  and 
• A well-formed formula (wff) is a sentence containing no “free”
variables. That is, all variables are “bound” by universal or existential
quantifiers.
5
(x)P(x,y) has x bound as a universally quantified variable, but y is free.
Quantifiers
• Universal quantification
• (x)P(x) means that P holds for all values of x in the domain associated
with that variable
• E.g., (x) dolphin(x)  mammal(x)
• Existential quantification
• ( x)P(x) means that P holds for some value of x in the domain associated
with that variable
• E.g., ( x) mammal(x)  lays-eggs(x)
• Permits one to make a statement about some object without naming it

6
Quantifiers
• Universal quantifiers are often used with “implies” to form “rules”:
(x) student(x)  smart(x) means “All students are smart”
• Universal quantification is rarely used to make blanket statements about
every individual in the world:
(x)student(x)smart(x) means “Everyone in the world is a student and is smart”
• Existential quantifiers are usually used with “and” to specify a list of
properties about an individual:
(x) student(x)  smart(x) means “There is a student who is smart”
• A common mistake is to represent this English sentence as the FOL
sentence:
(x) student(x)  smart(x)
• But what happens when there is a person who is not a student?
7
Quantifier Scope
• Switching the order of universal quantifiers does not change the
meaning:
• (x)(y)P(x,y) ↔ (y)(x) P(x,y)
• Similarly, you can switch the order of existential quantifiers:
• (x)(y)P(x,y) ↔ (y)(x) P(x,y)
• Switching the order of universals and existentials does change
meaning:
• Everyone likes someone: (x)(y) likes(x,y)
• Someone is liked by everyone: (y)(x) likes(x,y)

9
Connections between All and Exists

We can relate sentences involving  and  using De Morgan’s


laws:
(x) P(x) ↔ (x) P(x)
(x) P(x) ↔ (x) P(x)
(x) P(x) ↔  (x) P(x)
(x) P(x) ↔ (x) P(x)

10
Quantified inference rules
• Universal instantiation
• x P(x)  P(A)
• Universal generalization
• P(A)  P(B) …  x P(x)
• Existential instantiation
• x P(x) P(F)  skolem constant F
• Existential generalization
• P(A)  x P(x)

11
Universal instantiation
(a.k.a. universal elimination)
• If (x) P(x) is true, then P(C) is true, where C is any constant in the
domain of x
• Example:
(x) eats(Ziggy, x)  eats(Ziggy, IceCream)
• The variable symbol can be replaced by any ground term, i.e., any
constant symbol or function symbol applied to ground terms only

12
Existential instantiation
(a.k.a. existential elimination)
• From (x) P(x) infer P(c)
• Example:
• (x) eats(Ziggy, x)  eats(Ziggy, Stuff)
• Note that the variable is replaced by a brand-new constant not
occurring in this or any other sentence in the KB
• Also known as skolemization; constant is a skolem constant
• In other words, we don’t want to accidentally draw other inferences
about it by introducing the constant
• Convenient to use this to reason about the unknown object, rather
than constantly manipulating the existential quantifier
13
Existential generalization
(a.k.a. existential introduction)
• If P(c) is true, then (x) P(x) is inferred.
• Example
eats(Ziggy, IceCream)  (x) eats(Ziggy, x)
• All instances of the given constant symbol are replaced by the new
variable symbol
• Note that the variable symbol cannot already exist anywhere in the
expression

14
Translating English to FOL

Every gardener likes the sun.


x gardener(x)  likes(x,Sun)
You can fool some of the people all of the time.
x t person(x) time(t)  can-fool(x,t)
You can fool all of the people some of the time.
x t (person(x)  time(t) can-fool(x,t)) Equivalent
x (person(x)  t (time(t) can-fool(x,t))
All purple mushrooms are poisonous.
x (mushroom(x)  purple(x))  poisonous(x)
No purple mushroom is poisonous.
x purple(x)  mushroom(x)  poisonous(x) Equivalent
x (mushroom(x)  purple(x))  poisonous(x)
There are exactly two purple mushrooms.
x y mushroom(x)  purple(x)  mushroom(y)  purple(y) ^ (x=y)  z (mushroom(z) 
purple(z))  ((x=z)  (y=z))
Clinton is not tall.
tall(Clinton)
X is above Y iff X is on directly on top of Y or there is a pile of one or more other objects directly on 15
top of one another starting with X and ending with Y.
Example: A simple genealogy KB by FOL
• Build a small genealogy knowledge base using FOL that
• contains facts of immediate family relations (spouses, parents, etc.)
• contains definitions of more complex relations (ancestors, relatives)
• is able to answer queries about relationships between people
• Predicates:
• parent(x, y), child(x, y), father(x, y), daughter(x, y), etc.
• spouse(x, y), husband(x, y), wife(x,y)
• ancestor(x, y), descendant(x, y)
• male(x), female(y)
• relative(x, y)
• Facts:
• husband(Joe, Mary), son(Fred, Joe)
• spouse(John, Nancy), male(John), son(Mark, Nancy)
• father(Jack, Nancy), daughter(Linda, Jack)
• daughter(Liz, Linda)
• etc. 16
• Rules for genealogical relations
• (x,y) parent(x, y) ↔ child (y, x)
(x,y) father(x, y) ↔ parent(x, y)  male(x) (similarly for mother(x, y))
(x,y) daughter(x, y) ↔ child(x, y)  female(x) (similarly for son(x, y))
• (x,y) husband(x, y) ↔ spouse(x, y)  male(x) (similarly for wife(x, y))
(x,y) spouse(x, y) ↔ spouse(y, x) (spouse relation is symmetric)
• (x,y) parent(x, y)  ancestor(x, y)
(x,y)(z) parent(x, z)  ancestor(z, y)  ancestor(x, y)
• (x,y) descendant(x, y) ↔ ancestor(y, x)
• (x,y)(z) ancestor(z, x)  ancestor(z, y)  relative(x, y)
(related by common ancestry)
(x,y) spouse(x, y)  relative(x, y) (related by marriage)
(x,y)(z) relative(z, x)  relative(z, y)  relative(x, y) (transitive)
(x,y) relative(x, y) ↔ relative(y, x) (symmetric)
• Queries
• ancestor(Jack, Fred) /* the answer is yes */
• relative(Liz, Joe) /* the answer is yes */
• relative(Nancy, Matthew)
/* no answer in general, no if under closed world assumption */
• (z) ancestor(z, Fred)  ancestor(z, Liz) 17
Semantics of FOL
• Domain M: the set of all objects in the world (of interest)
• Interpretation I: includes
• Assign each constant to an object in M
• Define each function of n arguments as a mapping Mn => M
• Define each predicate of n arguments as a mapping Mn => {T, F}
• Therefore, every ground predicate with any instantiation will have a truth
value
• In general there is an infinite number of interpretations because |M| is
infinite
• Define logical connectives: ~, ^, v, =>, <=> as in PL
• Define semantics of (x) and (x)
• (x) P(x) is true iff P(x) is true under all interpretations
• (x) P(x) is true iff P(x) is true under some interpretation

18
• Model: an interpretation of a set of sentences such that every
sentence is True
• A sentence is
• satisfiable if it is true under some interpretation
• valid if it is true under all possible interpretations
• inconsistent if there does not exist any interpretation under which the
sentence is true
• Logical consequence: S |= X if all models of S are also
models of X

19
Axioms, definitions and theorems
•Axioms are facts and rules that attempt to capture all of the
(important) facts and concepts about a domain; axioms can be
used to prove theorems
• Mathematicians don’t want any unnecessary (dependent) axioms –ones
that can be derived from other axioms
• Dependent axioms can make reasoning faster, however
• Choosing a good set of axioms for a domain is a kind of design problem
•A definition of a predicate is of the form “p(X) ↔ …” and can be
decomposed into two parts
• Necessary description: “p(x)  …”
• Sufficient description “p(x)  …”
• Some concepts don’t have complete definitions (e.g., person(x))
20
More on definitions
• Examples: define father(x, y) by parent(x, y) and male(x)
• parent(x, y) is a necessary (but not sufficient) description of
father(x, y)
• father(x, y)  parent(x, y)
• parent(x, y) ^ male(x) ^ age(x, 35) is a sufficient (but not necessary) description
of father(x, y):
father(x, y)  parent(x, y) ^ male(x) ^ age(x, 35)
• parent(x, y) ^ male(x) is a necessary and sufficient description of father(x, y)
parent(x, y) ^ male(x) ↔ father(x, y)

21
More on definitions

S(x) is a P(x)
necessary (x) P(x) => S(x)
S(x)
condition of P(x)

S(x) is a S(x)
sufficient (x) P(x) <= S(x)
P(x)
condition of P(x)

S(x) is a P(x)
necessary and (x) P(x) <=> S(x)
S(x)
sufficient
condition of P(x)

22
Higher-order logic
• FOL only allows to quantify over variables, and variables can
only range over objects.
• HOL allows us to quantify over relations
• Example: (quantify over functions)
“two functions are equal iff they produce the same value for all arguments”
f g (f = g)  (x f(x) = g(x))
• Example: (quantify over predicates)
r transitive( r )  (xyz) r(x,y)  r(y,z)  r(x,z))
• More expressive, but undecidable.

23
Expressing uniqueness
• Sometimes we want to say that there is a single,
unique object that satisfies a certain condition
• “There exists a unique x such that king(x) is true”
• x king(x)  y (king(y)  x=y)
• x king(x)  y (king(y)  xy)
• ! x king(x)
• “Every country has exactly one ruler”
• c country(c)  ! r ruler(c,r)
• Iota operator: “ x P(x)” means “the unique x such
that p(x) is true”
• “The unique ruler of Freedonia is dead”
• dead( x ruler(freedonia,x)) 24
Notational differences
• Different symbols for and, or, not, implies, ...
•         
• p v (q ^ r)
• p + (q * r)
• etc
• Prolog
cat(X) :- furry(X), meows (X), has(X, claws)
• Lispy notations
(forall ?x (implies (and (furry ?x)
(meows ?x)
(has ?x claws))
(cat ?x)))
25

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy