Ethics and Intelligence
Ethics and Intelligence
207]
On: 01 August 2014, At: 18:57
Publisher: Routledge
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered
office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK
To cite this article: Sir David Omand & Mark Phythian (2013) Ethics and Intelligence: A
Debate, International Journal of Intelligence and CounterIntelligence, 26:1, 38-63, DOI:
10.1080/08850607.2012.705186
To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08850607.2012.705186
Sir David Omand GCB is Visiting Professor in the Department of War Studies
at Kings College London. In 2002, he was appointed the United Kingdoms first
Security and Intelligence Coordinator, responsible to the Prime Minister for the
professional health of the Intelligence Community, national counterterrorism
strategy, and homeland security. He served for seven years on the UKs Joint
Intelligence Committee. From 1997 to 2000, he was Permanent Secretary of
the Home Office, and before that was Director of the Government
Communications Headquarters (GCHQ). Sir David is the author of
Securing the State (London: C. Hurst, 2010).
Dr. Mark Phythian is Professor of Politics at the University of Leicester,
United Kingdom. Among the eleven books he has authored, edited, and
co-edited are: Intelligence in an Insecure World (with Peter GillLondon:
Polity, 2006); PSI Handbook of Global Security and Intelligence: National
Approaches, Volumes 1 and 2 (with Stuart Farson, Peter Gill, and Shlomo
ShpiroNew York: Praeger, 2008); and Commissions of Inquiry and
National Security: Comparative Approaches (with Stuart FarsonNew
York: Praeger, 2011). He has also written numerous journal articles and
book chapters.
38
39
The idea for this particular debate arose from a workshop organized by the
Oxford Intelligence Group and the International Intelligence Ethics
Association on The Ethics of National Security Intelligence, held at
Nuffield College, Oxford, in March 2011, at which we both spoke. We
found that, while we agreed on many points, we disagreed or our
emphases differed on several specific points. To an extent, doing so may
well reflect our different backgrounds: one of us is a former senior
intelligence professional with the perspective this brings, the other an
academic engaged in developing Intelligence Studies as a social science
project. Inevitably, in a discussion of this nature, what we agree on tends
to be put to one side in discussing areas where we differ in understanding,
approach, and emphasis, as we contribute to the emerging debate on the
ethicsintelligence relationship.
MARK PHYTHIAN
The starting point for any discussion about the relationship between ethics
and intelligence has to be the perennial debate within Intelligence Studies
about how intelligence should be defined. Specifically, should intelligence
be understood to include covert action? No consensus exists here. The
respected scholar and practitioner Michael Herman represents one strand of
thought in arguing that Intelligence is information and information
gathering, not doing things to people; no one gets hurt by it, at least not
directly. Some agencies do indeed carry out covert action, which confuses
the ethical issues, but this is a separable and subsidiary function. 1
However, the post-9=11 era has clearly shown that intelligence collection
can involve doings things to people and hurting them. Post-9=11, covert
action (and, indeed, overt action) became a more central dimension of U.S.
intelligence, where one corollary of the shift in the formal defense posture
of the U.S. to one of pre-emptive defense was a parallel shift in the posture
of its intelligence agenciesone well captured in former Central Intelligence
Agency (CIA) officer Charles Cogans characterization of a shift in the role
of intelligence from gatherers to hunters. Cogan argued that, in the
future, intelligence operatives will not simply sit back and gather
information that comes in, analyze it and then decide what to do about it.
Rather they will have to go and hunt out intelligence that will enable them
to track down or kill terrorists.2 The increasing reliance of the CIA on the
use of armed Predator drones to identify and eliminate suspected terrorists
across several territories has been emblematic of this shift.
Perhaps saying that covert action is not part of the intelligence cycle would
be more accurate rather than not part of intelligence. But the concept of the
intelligence cycle has often been criticized for being a poor representation of
the intelligence process, perhaps because of its exclusion of covert action.3
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE
40
If it is accepted that intelligence collection can take covert forms (which raise
their own ethical dilemmas), then I see no good reason to exclude from a
definition of intelligence covert actions that may arise out of the intelligence
process, are undertaken by intelligence personnel, and are paid for from
intelligence budgets. This has clear implications for the breadth of issues
that arise in discussing the ethicsintelligence relationship.
Many ethical dilemmas that face intelligence professionals, agencies, and
governments arise from a simple fact: national intelligence agencies are
precisely thatnational. Their responsibilities and obligations are defined
by reference to the state for which they are an information-gathering and
early-warning arm. In the context of the anarchic international
environment in which states find themselves (a key proposition of the
Realist approach to International Relations that intelligence professionals
implicitly or explicitly accept), their role is to help facilitate the principal
goal of statessurvival. John Mearsheimer characterizes the core
assumptions about the nature of the international system that underpin
Offensive Realism as being: (1) that great powers are the main actors in
world politics, and operate in an anarchic international system; (2) that all
states possess some offensive military capability; (3) that states can never
be certain about the intentions of other states; (4) that the main goal of
states is survival; and (5) that states are rational actors.4 The third of these
particularly explains the need for intelligence. The purpose of intelligence is
to break down this uncertainty, translating it into estimates about risk and
facilitating informed and timely decisionmaking.5
The Human Right
In contrast, the discussion of ethics and human rights is rooted in a
cosmopolitanism that views all individuals as being of equal moral standing,
regardless of national borders or nationality. This communitarian
cosmopolitan tension has been exacerbated in recent years by changes to
understandings of what is meant by human rights. Whereas in the
immediate post-1945 era human rights were essentially understood in
relation to rights provided by the state and as being a consequence of
citizenship (the rights of man), they came to have a different meaning by
the latter part of the twentieth century: as entitlements that might
contradict the sovereign nation-state from above and outside rather than
serve as its foundation.6 Hence, rights transcended states. Not only did
states have an obligation to avoid engaging in activities that would infringe
these rights, they also had an obligation to intervene where these rights were
being denied or seriously compromised by individual states.
However, this new cosmopolitanism represented a challenge for national
intelligence agencies with their state-level focus. Writing in his memoirs in
41
Figure 1. From Perspective to Goal on Human Rights. (Color figure available online.)
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE
42
Figure 2. From Perspective to Goal in Seeking Security. (Color figure available online.)
43
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE
44
45
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE
46
regard to ethics while at the same time protecting the national interest, its core
business. This would have the effect of turning the problem of dirty hands
into one of democratic dirty hands, in that once shared with, and debated
by, citizens the problem of dirty hands does not rest with just policymakers
and intelligence professionals, but more generally with society. This would
allow policymakers and intelligence agencies to meet the test outlined by
Stansfield Turner. Overseers of intelligence have a particular responsibility
for leading this debate. However, at the core of the problematic relationship
between ethics and intelligence is the fact that nations exist in an inherently
competitive environment, where agencies contribute to efforts to enhance,
as well as protect, the national interest. This may well mean that mitigation,
rather than elimination, of ethical dilemmas is the more realistic aim for
any such debate.
SIR DAVID OMAND
Reflecting on the fundamental shift in attitudes to secret intelligence over the
twentieth century is my starting point for the debate about the relationship
between ethics and intelligence.
Coupling ethics and secret intelligence in a single sentence would have
surprised the founders of British intelligence. The first Chief of the Secret
Intelligence Service tried to persuade the author Compton Mackenzie, one
of his officers during the First World War, to remain in service with the
words, Here, take this swordstick. I always took it with me on spying
expeditions before the war. Thats when this business was really amusing.
After the war is over well do some amusing secret service work together.
Its capital sport. Capital sport indeed for gentleman-ruffians, but in those
far-off days with the ability to make up the rules by which the game was
played or if the national survival stakes were high enough, to dispense with
rules altogether. As put to the British author, Bickham Sweet-Escott, on his
recruitment in 1940 into the Special Operations Executive (SOE): I cant
tell you what sort of a job it would be. All I can say is that if you join us,
you musnt be afraid of forgery, and you musnt be afraid of murder.
Contrast this with the evidence presented to the U.S. Congress a few years
ago by the then Director of the CIA Gen. Michael V. Hayden that We cant
break the law . . . You just cant go to that place . . . I actually said fairly
publicly to our workforce that, as director, I have to be certain that that
which Im asking a CIA officer to do is consistent with the Constitution,
the laws and the international treaty obligations of the United States. . . . If
I cant say that, I cant ask an officer to do it.22 Comparable statements
of reassurance would certainly be made today by the Heads of the British
intelligence agencies, and indeed were publicly made on their behalf by
Foreign Secretary William Hague in a speech in the Foreign Office on 16
47
November 2011: I believe it is vital that the British public and Parliament
have confidence in the Agencies ability to keep us safe and to do so
within the framework of the law; and that they also have confidence in
government using this capability wisely, and in accordance with our
democratic values and principles of domestic and international law,
adding: Because I work so closely with them, I know that their values are
the finest values of the United Kingdom.23
An Authorized State Activity
What this illustrates is the way that secret intelligence has been made into an
accepted and properly authorized state activity, regulated so as to operate
within national law. The relevant UK domestic legislation has, however, a
unique character since it legitimizes activity that could otherwise involve
breaking domestic law, such as an agent posing as a member of a
prohibited terrorist organization. UK domestic law also provides that, by a
warrant from the Secretary of State, intelligence officers can carry out acts
overseas for which they would be liable in the UK, with the implication
that the acts in question will break the laws of another country, as they
certainly would in conducting espionage. Legal compliance certainly may
reduce the need for ethical concern if the public accepts, as it should in the
UK, that the law in a democracy embodies the prevailing moral consensus.
Nevertheless, in the U.S. after 9=11, President George W. Bush used his
powers as Commander in Chief to create in effect secret law as part of his
War on Terror, permitting for example extreme methods of coercive
interrogation, now prohibited by President Barack Obama. The UK
Foreign Secretarys reference to values is a reminder that necessary
compliance with domestic law does not remove the duty of thinking
ethically from those involved in authorizing and using secret intelligence.
Foreign Secretary Hague has described the nature of the decisions needed:
As Foreign Secretary, I see operational proposals from the Agencies
every day, amounting to hundreds every year. The proposals are
detailed. They set out the planned operation, the potential risks and
the likely benefits of the information to be gained. They include
substantial legal sections which set out the basis for the operation and
comments from senior Foreign Office officials and lawyers. I discuss
these with them and with officials from the Agencies, and I often work
closely with the Home Secretary. These are often not easy decisions,
and the majority involve judgments about cooperating with other
countries. I take ultimate responsibility for these operations, and I do
not approve them all.24
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE
48
49
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE
50
51
well over three-quarters of the British intelligence effort now goes toward
countering what has been described by the United Nations as the dark side
of globalization.32 The UK intelligence budget is no longer sustained by
just state-on-state espionage.
Recognizing Moral Hazards
At this point in the argument the nature of the inevitable moral hazards
involved with secret intelligence must be recognized. To overcome the
obstacles that are placed in the way of obtaining such secret intelligence
requires extraordinary methods, involving a different morality than that of
everyday life: the equivalent in domestic terms of steaming open the
familys letters, hacking into their e-mails, listening at keyholes, spying on
their movements, and persuading them to inform on their friends.
Any important agent in place inside a terrorist network is, for example,
likely to be involved in criminal behaviorotherwise he or she is unlikely
to continue being in a position to acquire the inside information being
sought. But such an agent in place will create all the risks Professor
Phythian outlines of allegations of collusion with serious wrongdoing.
Much has been written33 about the powerful surveillance technology now
available for monitoring Internet communication, and the use of advanced
data mining of electronically stored personal information. Such exploitation
of personal data raises ethical issues over the extent and justification of
state surveillance, with the risk of a Panoptic chilling effect on public
behavior. Moral considerations will therefore be involved in intelligence
work across the spectrum, from the officer recruiting an agent in the field
to the analysts back in headquarters seeking to establish the degree of
confidence in a controversial assessment. Secret intelligence must be secret
because it is information others, be they military adversaries, terrorists, or
criminal gangs, are trying the utmost to prevent their opponents from
acquiring. Exposed agents may face torture and execution. The fact that the
individual sources and methods involved have to be kept highly secret (even
if the general nature of the type of activity is being acknowledged as part of
the intelligence arsenal) increases the potential for moral hazard.
In days far past, moral hazard may have been accepted as part of the
unwritten recruitment deal, with a willingness of the officer to accept
personal responsibility for his actions, and if it came to it, disavowal by
the authorities. But, the modern British intelligence agencies are an
acknowledged part of government, not just operating within a framework
of law, but also with the British public and Parliament retaining, in the
words of Foreign Secretary Hague, confidence in government using this
capability wisely, and in accordance with our democratic values and
principles of domestic and international law.34 I sense agreement between
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE
52
53
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE
54
55
Defensible Positions
In summary, an ethically defensible position is possible based on these
propositions:
The security and intelligence authorities are charged with the protection of the
public. They have a duty to seek and use secret information to help manage
threats to national security.
. Secret intelligence, because it involves overcoming the efforts of others to prevent
its acquisition, inevitably involves running a moral hazard.
. Intelligence activity can nevertheless be constrained by an ethical code that
embodies several well understood and tested Just War concepts, while also
embodying respect for human rights, including the prohibition of torture and
inhumane and degrading treatment.
. The effectiveness of secret intelligence rests on sources and methods that must
remain hidden, not least to protect the lives of those involved. Oversight has to
be by proxy: by senior judges and Parliamentarians who can, on the publics
behalf, be trusted to enter the ring of secrecy and to give citizens confidence
that these ethical standards are being maintained.
MARK PHYTHIAN
While our approaches to this debate are somewhat differentI focus on
problems and dilemmas while David Omand (perhaps more helpfully)
focuses on possible solutionsI agree with much in Sir Davids argument.
But our perspectives differ in some areas. These seem to be rooted in
differing understandings of the states role at the domestic level and the
role and relative significance of states in the international system. This
point is important because it suggests that thinking about the relationship
between ethics and intelligence needs to be rooted in an understanding of
the role of the state, and of states internationally. This aspect determines
the realm of the feasible and, therefore, what can be expected of
intelligence in terms of compliance with ethical norms.
In terms of the states role, Sir David combines a broadly Weberian
conception of the state as being defined by its claim to the monopoly of
legitimate violence with the idea of the protecting statea distinct shift
from the national security state of the Cold War era. Although I agree
that a Weberian conception of the state is an appropriate starting point for
thinking about the role of intelligence, we may differ slightly here. Max
Webers original 1919 definition was that a state could be considered to
exist if and insofar as its administrative staff successfully upholds a claim
on the monopoly of the legitimate use of violence (das Monopol legitimen
physischen Zwanges) in the enforcement of its order.40 The implication of
this, as John Hoffman has suggested, is that:
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE
56
The very need to exercise a monopoly of legitimate force arises only because
states are challenged by rebels and criminals who themselves resort to force,
and who (either implicitly or explicitly) contest the legitimacy of the laws
they break. . . . The state which actually succeeds in imposing a monopoly
of legitimate force thereby makes itself redundant since a gulf between
ideals and reality is essential to the states very raison detre.41
In other words, the fate of the state is to assert its monopoly but never fully
achieve it. For example, all states face potential challenges from those who
contest their territorial claims and reject the territorial identity ascribed to
them. Individual policies, whether economic (e.g., the prioritization of debt
reduction over public expenditure), political (e.g., whether to go to war in
Iraq), or ethical (e.g., whether to ban fox hunting) can all result in
challenges to this monopoly, thus generating the requirement for
intelligence. At any one time, even the protecting state will be involved in
shielding some citizens against others, although the composition of the
others will shift over time and by issue.42 This has clear implications for
the role of intelligence and the question of intelligence ethics.
Sir David and I also differ over the emphasis that should be attached to
state-on-state espionage in framing the intelligence ethics debate. Again,
this may be rooted in different understandings of the states role in
international relations. At issue is the nature of risks and threats in an era
of globalization. David Omand points out that, as a consequence of the
threat posed by al-Qaeda, affiliated groups, and self-identifying individuals
that largely dominated the security and intelligence landscape over the last
10 to 15 years, UK intelligence has developed a significant
counterterrorism focus. However, risk lies in assuming that the challenges
of a specific era define those of the future, and thereby overlooking the
persistence of concurrent risks and concerns generated by state activities.
For example: Irans nuclear program; questions relating to Pakistan
(indicative of the importance of focusing on states having the possibility of
their becoming failing states with all of the attendant risks such a shift
would poseexacerbated in Pakistans case by its nuclear weapons status);
the challenges involved in relations with Russia (highlighted in the UK
context by the Litvinenko case); for the U.S. in particular, the implications
of the rise of Chinaall these are issues of first-order importance for
intelligence. Moreover, one development held to be most emblematic of the
dark side of globalizationthe rise of cyber crime and the emphasis that
now needs to be placed on cyber securityclearly has a significant state
basis. As Sir David suggests, cyber security may well require a distinct
ethical code of its own (I would have little confidence in the effectiveness
of any international regulatory regime in this field), and presents severe
challenges for the democratic oversight of intelligence. Hence, I retain my
emphasis on the centrality of states and the importance of recognizing this
57
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE
58
59
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE
60
61
4
5
6
7
8
Michael Herman, Ethics and Intelligence after September 2001, Intelligence and
National Security, Vol. 19, No. 2, 2004, p. 342.
Charles Cogan, Hunters Not Gatherers: Intelligence in the Twenty-First
Century, Intelligence and National Security, Vol. 19, No. 2, 2004, p. 317.
For a critique of the intelligence cycle concept, see, for example, Arthur S. Hulnick,
Whats Wrong with the Intelligence Cycle? International Journal of Intelligence
and CounterIntelligence, Vol. 21, No. 4, Winter 20062007, pp. 959979.
John J. Mearsheimer, The Tragedy of Great Power Politics (New York: W.W.
Norton, 2001), pp. 3031.
This characterization of the role of intelligence draws on Mark Phythian,
Policing Uncertainty: Intelligence, Security and Risk, Intelligence and
National Security, Vol. 27, No. 2, 2012, and the definitional debate in Peter
Gill and Mark Phythian, Intelligence in an Insecure World (Cambridge: Polity
Press, 2006), Chapter 1.
Samuel Moyn, The Last Utopia: Human Rights in History (Cambridge, MA:
Belknap=Harvard University Press, 2010), p. 13.
Stansfield Turner, Secrecy and Democracy: The CIA in Transition (Boston:
Houghton Mifflin, 1985), p. 48.
For example, Michael Quinlan, Just Intelligence: Prolegomena to an Ethical
Theory, Intelligence and National Security, Vol. 22, No. 1, 2007, pp. 113; and
David Omand, Securing the State (London: Hurts & Co. 2010).
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE
62
Cited in Charles E. Lathrop, The Literary Spy (New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press, 2004), p. 205.
10
On this, see Mark Phythian, Policing Uncertainty.
11
Dennis F. Thompson, Political Ethics and Public Office (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1987), p. 11.
12
Niccolo` Machiavelli, The Prince (London: Penguin, 2003), Chapter 15.
13
http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/1994/13/section/7
14
For example, Philippe Sands, Torture Team: Uncovering War Crimes in the Land
of the Free (London: Allen Lane, 2008).
15
George Tenet, At the Center of the Storm: My Years at the CIA (New York:
HarperCollins, 2007), p. 241.
16
Harold Hongju Koh, The Obama Administration and International Law,
Speech to the Annual Meeting of the American Society of International Law,
Washington, D.C., 25 March 2010, at http://www.state.gov/s/l/releases/
remarks/139119.htm
17
On this, see Bob Brecher, Torture and the Ticking Bomb (Malden, MA: Blackwell
Publishing, 2007).
18
See, for example, Mary Ellen OConnell, When Is a War Not a War? The Myth
of the Global War on Terror, ILSA Journal of International and Comparative
Law, Vol. 12, No. 2, 2005, pp. 535540.
19
http://www.newyorker.com/online/blogs/newsdesk/2009/10/jane-mayerpredators-drones-pakistan.html
20
Bernard Williams, A Critique of Utilitarianism, in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard
Williams, eds., Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1973), p. 113.
21
Dennis F. Thompson, Political Ethics and Public Office, p. 3.
22
Evidence to Congress, Gen. Michael V. Hayden, April 2007, at http://
www.q-and-a.org/Transcript/?.ProgrameID=1123, on 24 September 2009.
23
William Hague, Securing our Future, speech given in the Foreign and
Commonwealth Office, London, on 16 November 2011, at http://www.fco.
gov.uk/en/news/latest-news/?view=Speech&id=692973282
24
Ibid.
25
Extract from the Chambers Dictionary definition of ethics.
26
A. John Radsan, The Unresolved Equation of Espionage and International
Law, Michigan Journal of International Law, Vol. 28, No. 3, 2007, pp. 595623.
27
UK legislation was passed in 1985 requiring the agencies and the police to seek
warrants to permit interception of communications, an approach that was
subsequently extended in an Act to regulate all intrusive investigative powers.
Legislation putting first the Security Service (1989) and then the other
intelligence agencies (1994) on a statutory footing with oversight by senior
judges and Parliamentarians inevitably followed.
28
Peter Hennessy, The Secret State (London: Allen Lane, 2002).
29
David Omand, Securing the State.
30
63
AND COUNTERINTELLIGENCE