0% found this document useful (0 votes)
131 views6 pages

A Brief Overview of Logical Theory

This document provides an overview of key concepts in logical theory, including: 1. It defines an argument as one or more premises offered to support a conclusion. Arguments can be deductive, aiming to conclusively prove the conclusion, or inductive, aiming to show the conclusion is probable. 2. Valid deductive arguments are those where the conclusion must be true if the premises are, while strong inductive arguments make the conclusion probable if the premises are true. 3. Sound deductive and cogent inductive arguments have premises that are true in addition to being valid/strong. 4. Logical relationships like consistency and implication relate how statements can be combined or what follows from others.

Uploaded by

Hyman Jay Blanco
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
131 views6 pages

A Brief Overview of Logical Theory

This document provides an overview of key concepts in logical theory, including: 1. It defines an argument as one or more premises offered to support a conclusion. Arguments can be deductive, aiming to conclusively prove the conclusion, or inductive, aiming to show the conclusion is probable. 2. Valid deductive arguments are those where the conclusion must be true if the premises are, while strong inductive arguments make the conclusion probable if the premises are true. 3. Sound deductive and cogent inductive arguments have premises that are true in addition to being valid/strong. 4. Logical relationships like consistency and implication relate how statements can be combined or what follows from others.

Uploaded by

Hyman Jay Blanco
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 6

A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF LOGICAL THEORY

1. Some Basic Concepts of Logic


Argument
Logical theory begins with the concept of an argument. An argument, as the word is used in logic

and in intellectual contexts generally, is reasoning that has been put into words. When you put your

reasoning into words, you produce what logicians call an argument. Simple enough, but for the

purposes of logical theory, a more precise definition is needed. Most logic textbooks include a more

detailed definition, usually one that sounds much like this:


An argument is one or more statements, called premises, offered as a reason to believe that a further statement,
called the conclusion, is true, that is, corresponds to reality.

It is true that in some contexts we use the word argument differently, to refer to people angrily

yelling at each other, or to people having a heated emotional dispute. But in logic, and in academic
and intellectual contexts generally, the word just means one or more premises offered as reasons or

as evidence for the truth of a conclusion.

When we listen to an argument, it is sometimes difficult to tell which statements are premises and

which statement is the conclusion. This is why the English language contains what logicians call

argument indicator words. To tell your audience that you are drawing your conclusion, introduce

your statement using a word or phrase such as therefore, in conclusion, thus, consequently,

and so on. To indicate a premise, introduce a statement using words such as because, since, for

the reason that, and so on. Premise and conclusion indicator words help your audience follow the

flow of your reasoning.

Back to Top
Deductive vs Inductive Arguments
Following Aristotle, logicians divide all arguments into two broad types: deductive arguments and

inductive arguments.
A deductive argument is any argument that aims to show that its conclusion must be true. In other words, a
deductive argument aims to conclusively establish its conclusion. The implicit or explicit claim, in a deductive
argument, is therefore that if the premises are true then the conclusion is completely certain to be true as well.

An inductive argument is any argument that aims to show that its conclusion is probably true although not certainly
true. An inductive argument, in other words, claims (in so many words) only that if the premises are true, then the
conclusion is likely or reasonable (but not certain).

You can explicitly tell your audience that your argument is deductive by introducing your conclusion

with wording such as therefore it must be that, or it necessarily follows that, or therefore it is

certain that, or it is conclusively proven that, and so on. These phrases are called deductive

indicators.
You tell your audience that your argument is inductive by introducing your conclusion with wording

such as therefore it is probably the case that, or it is likely that, or therefore it is reasonable to

conclude that, and so on. These phrases are called inductive indicators.

Back to Top
Valid, Invalid, and Sound Deductive Arguments
A deductive argument that succeeds in showing that its conclusion must be true if its premises all are

true is called a valid deductive argument. A deductive argument that fails to show that its conclusion

must be true if its premises are true is called an invalid deductive argument.

Thus a valid argument may be defined as a deductive argument in which it is the case that if the

premises are true then the conclusion must be true. An invalid argument may be defined as a

deductive argument in which it is not the case that if the premises are true the conclusion must be

true.

Both of the following arguments are deductive, because each obviously aims to show that its

conclusion must be true if its premises all are true. However, only the first is valid, the second

is invalid:

1. All human beings are mammals.

2. All mammals are warm-blooded.

3. Therefore it must be that all human beings are warm-blooded.

1. All human beings are mammals.

2. All dogs are mammals.

3. Therefore it must be that all human beings are dogs.

Do you see the difference between these two arguments? Again: Not all reasoning is equal. Some

reasoning is better than other reasoning.


When logic students first learn the concept of validity, they almost always find one thing extremely

puzzling. An argument can be valid even though it has false premises and a false conclusion. Consider

the following deductive argument:

1. All students are millionaires.

2. All millionaires are Buddhists.

3. Therefore, all students must be Buddhists.

Although the premises are false, and although the conclusion is false, the argument is valid. It is valid

simply because if the premises were to be true then the conclusion would have to be true as well. The

argument fits the definition of a valid argument. Does this seem puzzling to you? The premises are
false, and yet the argument is perfectly valid! This shows that true premises are not required for
validity. In logic, valid does not mean true. An argument is valid as long as it is the case that if the

premises are true then the conclusion must be true. True premises are not required.

However, validity is not all we want in a deductive argument. We normally also want truth. If an

argument is valid, and in addition its premises are all true, then the argument is called

a sound argument. Thus, a sound argument has two characteristics:

1. All of its premises are true.

2. It is valid.

Since truthcorrespondence with realityis the ultimate goal of reasoning, soundness is the ultimate

goal of deductive argumentation, not mere validity. You know youve made it if your deductive

argument is sound as well as valid. The following argument is both valid and sound:

1. All whales are mammals.

2. All mammals are animals.

3. Therefore, it must be that all whales are animals.

The previous argument, about students and Buddhists, was valid, butunsound.

Back to Top
Strong, Weak, and Cogent Inductive Arguments
An inductive argument that succeeds in showing that its conclusion is probably (but not certainly) true

if its premises are true is called a strong inductive argument. An inductive argument that fails to

show that its conclusion is probably (but not certainly) true if its premises are true is called

a weak inductive argument.

Thus a strong argument may be defined as an inductive argument in which it is the case that if the

premises are true then the conclusion isprobably true. A weak argument may be defined as an

inductive argument in which it is not the case that if the premises are true then the conclusion is

probably true.

Both of the following arguments are inductive, because each aims to show that its conclusion is

probably (but not certainly) true. However, the first is strong while the second is weak:

1. In all of recorded history, it has never snowed 6 inches in Dallas in August.

2. Therefore, it probably will not snow 6 inches in Dallas next August.

1. Joe is a member of the Democratic Party.

2. Some known Communists have been members of the Democratic Party.

3. Therefore, Joe is probably a Communist.

Again, not all reasoning is equal. Some acts of reasoning are better than others. Do you agree?
Many logic students find this aspect of strength puzzling at first: An inductive argument can be strong

even though it has false premises and a false conclusion. Consider the following inductive argument:

1. For the past six months it has been snowing every day in Dallas, it is below 30 degrees in Dallas,

and the sky in Dallas is full of snow clouds.

2. Therefore, it will probably snow in Dallas today.

Although the premise is false, and although the conclusion is false, the argument is strong. It is strong

because if the premise were to be true then the conclusion would probably be true as well: If the

premise is true, then the conclusion is likely to be true although not certain. The argument fits the

definition of a strong argument!

But strength is not all we want in an inductive argument. We normally also want truth. If an argument

is strong, and in addition its premises are all true, then the argument is called a cogent argument.
Thus, a cogent inductive argument has two properties:

1. All of its premises are true.

2. It is strong.

Since truth is the ultimate goal of reasoning, cogency is the ultimate goal of inductive argumentation.

The following argument is both strong and cogent:

1. Most cars burn gasoline.

2. The Presidential Limousine is a car.

3. Therefore the Presidential Limousine probably burns gasoline.

The earlier argument, about Dallas and snow, was strong but not cogent.

Back to Top
Consistency, Implication, and Equivalence
We have been using our faculty of reason to judge deductive arguments as valid or invalid and to

assess the strength of inductive arguments, but we also use reason when we decide whether or not

two of our beliefs stand in logical conflict and when we look for certain logical relations among our

beliefs. For this reason, logical theory also studies the logical relationships that exist between

declarative statements and the logical properties of statements. Four terms are especially important:

Consistency, inconsistency, implication, and equivalence. Here are the first two definitions:

Two statements are consistent if and only if it is possible both are true

Two statements are inconsistent if and only if it is not possible both are true.

For example, the following statements, given their standard meanings, are consistent:

1. Sue is 33 years old.

2. Sue is an accountant.
And the following statements, given their standard meanings, are inconsistent:

1. Sue is 33 years old.

2. Sue is a teenager.

Next:

One statement implies a second statement if and only if it is not possible that the first statement is

true and the second statement is false.

In other words, a statement P implies a statement Q when and only when it is the case that if P is true

then Q is true. For example, in the following case, the first sentence implies the second:

1. Sam is 33 years old.

2. Sam is older than 21.

However, in the next case, the first sentence does not imply the second:

1. Sam is a Republican.

2. Sam is a millionaire.

Next:

Two statements P and Q are equivalent if and only if P implies Q and Q implies P.

In other words, two statements are equivalent when and only when it is not possible that they differ

as to truth and falsity: if one is true then the other is true and if one is false then the other is false. In

the following case, the two statements are logically equivalent.

1. Ann is taller than Bob.

2. Bob is shorter than Ann.

But these two statements are not equivalent:

1. Ann is older than Bob.

2. Bob is 33 years old.

Back to Top
Necessity and Contingency
We also use our faculty of reason when we decide whether a statement is necessary or contingent,

and logic is concerned to define the relevant terminology so that our thinking can be as clear as

possible on this matter as well. Four additional terms are important: Necessary truth, necessary

falsehood, contingent truth, contingent falsehood. Here are the definitions:

A statement is necessarily true if it is true and it cannot possibly be false.

In other words, it is true in all possible circumstances, there are no possible circumstances in which it

would be false. For the purposes of logical theory, a possible circumstance is defined as any
circumstance whose description is not self-contradictory. This is the broadest concept of possibility

humanly and consistently conceivable.

A statement is necessarily false if it is false and it cannot possibly be true.

In other words, it is false in all possible circumstances, there are no possible circumstances in which it

would be true.

For example, the following statements, given their standard meanings of course, are all necessarily

true:

1. All triangles have three sides.

2. The derivative of a constant is zero.

3. The number 3 is greater than the number 2.

Given their standard meanings, the following statements are necessarily false:

1. All triangles have 9 sides.

2. 1 + 1 = 5.

3. The number 12 is less than the number 3.

Next:

A statement is contingently true if it is true but there are possible circumstances in which it would

be false.

In other words, it is true but it might have been false if circumstances had been sufficiently different.

A statement is contingently false if it is false but there are possible circumstances in which it would

be true.

In other words, it is false but it might have been true if circumstances had been sufficiently different.

Examples of contingent truth would include:

1. Crosby, Stills, and Nash performed at Woodstock in 1969.

2. It is sunny in Seattle on September 9, 2011.

And examples of contingent falsehoods would include:

1. Bob Dylan performed at Woodstock in 1969.

2. Richard Nixon was elected President in 1960.


Conclusion
There you have it: A cooks tour of the main concepts of logical theory. I hope you found it helpful.

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy