Necessity or Contingency PDF
Necessity or Contingency PDF
or
CONTINGENCY
CSLI
Lecture Notes
No. 56
NECESSITY
or
CONTINGENCY
THE MASTER ARGUMENT
Jules Vuillemin
Publications
CENTER FOR THE STUDY OF
LANGUAGE AND INFORMATION
STANFORD, CALIFORNIA
Copyright © 1996
Center for the Study of Language and Information
Leland Stanford Junior University
Printed in the United States
99 98 97 96 96 5 4 3 H
Vuillemin, Jules.
[Ne'cessite' ou contingence. English]
Necessity or contingency : the master argument / Jules Vuillemin.
p. cm. — (CSLI lecture notes ; no. 56)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
1996
— dc2O 95-50100
CIP
CSLI was founded early in 1983 by researchers from Stanford University, SRI
International, and Xerox PARC to further research and development of integrated
:heories of language, information, and computation. CSLI headquarters and CSLI
Publications are located on the campus of Stanford University.
Introduction xi
Acknowledgements xiii
Acknowledgements
This book builds on earlier studies (Vuillemin, 1979, 1983) and espe-
cially on Necessite ou contingence, I'aporie de Diodore et les systemes
philosophiques (Les Editions de Minuit-La Fondation Singer Polignac,
Paris, 1984). I considerably shortened this last work and eliminated
the systematic considerations not directly pertinent to the Master
Argument. I corrected it on the occasion of an objection raised by
M.H. Angstl (his letter and my reply to it were published in the All-
gemeine Zeitschrift fur Philosophic, XI 3, 1986, pp. 79-87). Finally I
added the present, unpublished Epilogue. M. Thomas F. Morran has
translated into English this new French version.
My thanks go to Professor J. Moravcsik for his criticism, Bill Gra-
ham, who revised the text, Mrs. L. von Kampen, who transformed a
manuscript into a book, and to Patrick Suppes, my good friend.
Part I
at once, since in every case there is a conflict between one and the
other two.1
To this account Epictetus adds an ironic commentary on the virtues
of erudition. To one who boasted of having read Antipater's treatise
on the Master Argument he exclaims: "What more do you have, you,
for having read it? What opinion have you formed on the question?
You might just as well speak to us of Helen, of Priam and of that isle
of Calypso that hasn't existed in the least and never will".2
The irony of Epictetus is aimed neither at the doctrine nor at the
moral consequences that could be drawn from the argument, but only
at the vanity of logical quibbles. We cannot speculate then on any
opposition of principle that Epictetus might have had to the supposedly
morally disastrous consequences of the argument.
Such is the only explicit text on the Master Argument.
Most interpretations and reconstructions of the argument that have
been given can be put into one of three categories. They all agree,
implicitly at least, on denouncing its disastrous moral consequences
and on flushing out some ambiguity or other in the premises, which
they in turn hold responsible for these consequences. In order to save
human freedom called into question by the Master Argument it has
been postulated that Diodorus was guilty of making one of the following
confusions. He took the word 'follow' in two different senses in the first
two premises. He played, in the first premise, either on two possible
senses of the way in which a proposition can be concerned with the past
or on two senses of the word 'necessary'. Or finally, he played on a more
general ambiguity hidden in the usage of indeterminate grammatical
tenses.
it would necessarily entail, ipso facto, the logical possibility having that
same temporal statement as its object. Supposing it necessary that a
certain thing should have happened, it is a fortiori possible that that
thing should have happened. But when the modalities are applied to
temporal events, they are generally understood, and rightly so, in a
different sense. They are taken in a real, rather than in a logical sense.
Irrevocability, which is a factual kind of necessity, applies to any event
whatsoever, even a contingent one, once it has come to pass. It follows
then that the real modality itself must be assigned a temporal index
distinct from the one affecting the event to which the modality applies.
At present it is irrevocable, or necessary in the factual sense, that the
battle of Salamis took place. Factual possibility, the modal counterpart
of this factual necessity, will likewise be assigned a temporal index of
its own. But it is notable that there is no way of getting from the
past conceived of as a factual necessity to the corresponding factual
possibility, where that factuality is taken to be that of a future or, at
most, a present event, to the exclusion of any event having taken place.
We shall see that for Aristotle this privileged temporal direction of the
possible constitutes the entire content of the Master Argument's first
premise.
The Master Argument then could not be accused of having an am-
biguous first premise, unless, in order to be demonstrative, it confused
either the grammatical form of the past with the factual past or tem-
poral necessity with irrevocability. Neither the one nor the other of
these confusions is required. Each axiom of Epictetus will, in the same
way, be given an interpretation in terms of temporal modalities. As to
the logical demonstration that these axioms are incompatible, it will be
shown to simply obey the laws of first order extensional logic without
having to resort to arguments borrowed from modal logic. Therefore
there will be no risk of subreption between the logical and the factual
meanings of modalities.
we can detach its consequent to get 'if it is not possible that something
has never been never going to be the case, then it is not possible that
it be the case'.
On the other hand, given E and substituting 'something will never
be the case' for 'something is the case' in A, the rule of syllogism will
allow us to write:
Of whatever neither is nor ever will be the case it is not possible that
it has never been never going to be the case. But we have demonstrated
(B and D) that if it is not possible that something has never been never
going to be the case then it is not possible for that something to be the
case. Hence, whatever neither is nor ever will be the case is impossible.
This is the denial of the Master Argument's premise C according to
which there is a possible that will never be realized.
Once the ambiguous interpretation of premise A is admitted, the
whole question comes down to one of justifying the introduction of D
andE.
In favor of D one might invoke11 Chapter IX of De Interpretatione,12
or again Cicero's De Fato.13 But in one case it is the Megarians, in the
other the Stoics, to which this principle of retrogradation is attributed.
Aristotle refuses it implicitly.
As for the premise E, it means that "... if a statement is false and
will always remain so in the future, then there has been a past moment
at which it was true that that statement would always subsequently
be false".14 What makes this premise seem plausible is that "... if
p is now and always will be false then it has already been true in
the past, at least at the moment just past, that p will never be true
anymore—it hasn't always been true, because at least in the moment
just past it wasn't true, that p would be true again".15 This thesis is
valid only if time is discrete and non-dense,16 in other words, only if,
as Diodorus holds,17 every instant, and in particular the present one,
"Becker, 1961, pp. 250-253.
12
See below, 6.4, pp. 140-141.
13
Potest factum quicquam igitur esse, quod non verum fuerit futurum esse? (Ci-
cero, De Fato, XII (27)).
14
Boudot, 1973, p. 447.
15
Prior, 1967, p. 49; but cf. also p. 8.
16
Boudot, 1973, pp. 447-448 (for an intuitive resume); Prior, 1967, pp. 49-50.
17
D6ring, 1972, frag. 116-120, p. 129 sq. According to Fraenkel (1960, pp. 204-
211) the arguments of Zeno treat of space represented as continuous just as well as
discontinuous, whereas Diodorus envisaged solely the case of its discontinuity. In
the third proof of Festus, the d^epi), as logical conceptions, are introduced only to
render motion impossible. According to Sedley, 1977 (pp. 88-89), basing himself on
Chalcidius, Diodorus' influence on some of the Stoics was so great that they would
have incorporated the notion of indivisible units of matter into their doctrine. For
PRIOR'S INTERPRETATION / 11
23
Boudot, 1973, p. 451: "In tense-logic the conclusion from the truth to the ne-
cessity of 'Socrates will be sitting' does not follow. But in metric tense-logic, the
conclusion from the truth to the necessity of 'Socrates will be sitting tomorrow' does
follow, since that statement is equivalent to 'It was true yesterday that Socrates
will be sitting the day after tomorrow', which is itself necessary because past". This
variation of modal status with the formal expression of the tense of the statements
in question assures the originality of Diodorus with respect to the 'ancient' Megar-
ians (Blanche, 1965, pp. 133-149). It also limits the importance of that originality.
Sedley (1977, pp. 74-120) has contested Diodorus' adhesion to the Megarian 'school'
(pp. 74-78), making him rather a representative of the Dialectical 'school', which
had a separate existence. But even accepting this thesis, there remains sufficient
affinity between the two schools, from the point of view both of the theory of motion
and of that of the modalities, for us to still consider Diodorus to be a 'Megarian'
philosopher.
24
Prior, 1967, pp. 121 sq.
25
This constitutes the essentials of Boudot's elegant solution (1973).
14 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
26
With the exception of Cherniss (1962) and Hintikka (1973), though even here,
none of Hintikka's references to this passage (p. 94, p. 152, p. 164, p. 183) actually
analyzes Aristotle's manner of reasoning.
Reconstruction of the Master
Argument.
15
16 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
since its validity in no way depends on them, they will simply be taken
here as given.2
The three following principles, on the other hand, broken down into
four for the sake of clarity, are the very ones operative in the Master
Argument.
2
The principle of the conservation of modal status is a consequence of the Aris-
totelian distinction between three kinds of substance (Metaphysics A, 1069a30-
1069*2): a) the sensible corruptible substances, b) the sensible incorruptible sub-
stances, c) the immaterial and immobiles substances. The three kinds are such
that, if something belongs to one of them, it can never belong to another one. But
belonging to b) or to c) means being a necessary being, and belonging to a) means
being a contingent being. Themistius, in a subtle passage of his Commentary,
lays down the principle and shows the absurdities that its denial would entail. To
allow perishable substances to transgress their essence and accede to immortality
and indestructibility would be to destroy the very limits that define the nature of
things and to make contrary capacities persist indefinitely. "As the generable and
the perishable are not so by chance and by fortune, it is seen that they are so
by nature. Indeed, all that there is is either by nature or by chance-for we leave
aside here that which art produces; but all natural things maintain (custodiunt) the
capacities that are proper to them. If they don't keep them and they change into
other dispositions, their modification will be either the result of chance-in which
case there would be but one and the same disposition for both natural things and
for those resulting from chance and fortune-or the modification will come about,
even for chance things, according to nature. That is why, since there is conservation
of the modification even if the things themselves are to change, the modification in
turn will take place either by nature or as a result of chance. This is why natural
capacities must have limits. But if these capacities have limits, then that also,
which has a birth and is subject to death, will be so by nature before that death.
It can then be seen that what happens now to the nature and the matter thus
subject to these two dispositions, namely, on the one hand the generation of things
and their existence, on the other their privation and their inexistence, has a limit
beyond which it changes no more. That is why it is necessary that that which is
engendered should not be deprived of this power of being changed; that is why
death too will come to it, in its time. Likewise, we do not surprise that which is
always subject to death transgressing its proper nature. Otherwise, since it will
have persisted for some time by virtue of its nature, it will equally persist in the
disposition that renders it immortal and, keeping its nature, it will also retain the
capacity in virtue of which it was changed. That is why there must then be several
capacities at once for an infinite time, and since we have established that the action
of this capacity persists, then what we have established will be false, which can no
more be the case than the rest we have spoken of so often." (Themistius, De Caelo
A 12 [Arist. p. 28362-12] 1902, p. 86, lines 4-29).
18 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
8
Having recourse to the preceding thesis, let us posit p as existent. The condition
of validity of this position is that p be compatible with Mp. Suppose further that
the hypothesis of the argument imposes ~ p. Clearly ~ p excludes p but not Mp.
In other words:
~ p.M(p.Mp)
is compatible, for that conjunction is equivalent to:
~ p.Mp.MMp.
In order for the position that p is existent to enter into contradiction with the
hypothesis, this latter would have to impose ~ Mp. Then:
~ Mp.M(p.Mp)
is indeed incompatible, since that conjunction is equivalent to:
~ Mp.Mp.MMp.
9
Leibniz, Gerhardt, 1978, p. 359; Jalabert, 1962, p. 371. It is important to insist
here on the word 'may' which has as consequence the impossibility of applying
the rule in the case where the impossibility of the thing would have already been
posited.
10
Laurent warns Antoine that the philosophers' rule is false if one makes it say
that:
(1) (Mp.M ~ p ) 3 M(p. ~ p).
From (1), by contraposition, comes:
THE PRINCIPLE OF THE POSSIBLE REALIZATION OF THE POSSIBLE / 21
12
The sophism of the distribution of the modalities may be written thus:
* ~ M(3t)(pt- ~ pt) 3~ M(3t)(pt • Mt ~ pt).
The principle of conditional necessity is written:
~ (pt • Mt ~ pt) or ~ (~ Pt •
that is to say:
Mt ~ pt D~ pt or Mtpt
26 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
would have to come to be identified with the present and the present
with the past. In this way it would be denied that the past occupies a
different time from the present.
This text confirms the existence of a double temporal index of the
modalities, once they are used to characterize substances. The princi-
ple of the impossibility of realizing a possible in the past illustrates the
constraints affecting this double index just as the principle of condi-
tional necessity does. To say that a possible, which is forward looking,
has to do with the past, is to completely upset the order of time. It
comes down to postulating that the index of the possible at t\, which
must, by definition, be equal to or anterior to the index <2 of the event
whose possibility is in question, can, at the same time, be posterior to
it 16 .
16
This is attested to by the following Commentary of Simplicius: In L. De Caelo
I, 12, Ad 283i>6, 1894, pp. 355-356: "Having shown that the proposition saying
that a generated thing is indestructible implies that that thing has the capacity
of contraries' belonging to it at the same time, he goes on immediately to raise
the objection that can be brought against this line of reasoning. That which is
both generated and indestructible has the capacity of not being in the direction of
the past, since it was non-existent before being, and the capacity of being in the
direction of the future, since it is supposed indestructible. It is nevertheless not at
the same time that it will have the capacity of being and of not being, so that it
won't have the contraries in actuality either. But disposing of this objection, he
says that all potentiality is in the direction of present or future time. For above
all else we call possible the things which are not yet but are capable of becoming,
differing from existing things in that they will be but are not yet. If it is not true
then as regards anything to say now that it is last year or that it is not last year
(the two lessons exist = a./Kporepw; fap fpcuperai); for it is not true to say now
that the time of last year is, nor of any event that took place last year that it is
now, but neither was it true to say last year that now is a past of the time which
took place at the end of the year finished. In effect it is impossible to interchange
the times.
If this is then true, it is impossible that something which at some moment does
not exist should later be sempiternal, i.e., that that which was generated should
continue to be indestructible for the rest of time. Indeed, since that which after-
wards is was first inexistent it will also have, once having attained to being, the
possibility of not being, though not that of not being then when it has already
attained to being: indeed, at that moment it is supposed to be in actuality. It is
thus necessary that such an entity should have the potentiality of last year and in
the past. This is absurd, since there is no potentiality of that which has happened,
but only of that which is and of that which will be. Aristotle says even more clearly
moreover: 'let that of which it has the capacity exist in actuality: it will then be
true to say now regarding that which has the capacity now of not existing, not only
that it has last year the capacity of not existing, but even that it does not exist
last year'. What is even more absurd, the now itself is in the fact of not existing
last year. For last year will be now. Now is in effect supposed to have the capacity
of not existing last year. It is thus clear that the following reading is the more
consequent, namely, 'that it does not exist last year'. And it is in fact by these
THE IRREVOCABILITY OF THE PAST / 29
that the futures constitute a proper part of the possibles: they are the
events yet to take place of this world which was chosen by God, along
with the past and the present, as being the best. By possible, then, is
to be understood any idea in the mind of God. Those possibles that
are realized are realized by virtue of a "conditional necessity" which
is itself beyond the pale of chance and contingency and is thus fit to
retrograde, since it serves only to mark that which, in Creation, distin-
guishes the best from the non-contradictory. 3) One can again, with
Aristotle, distinguish two sorts of futures. Some have virtues that could
not not be realized. The others are contingent possibles. Among these
latter, some will be realized, but there remain others that will never
be realized. The range of possibles, then, is by no means exhausted
by the futures that will be realized. Diodorus wants to show that no
non-realized future is possible. But he need not for that suppose that
his adversary holds that all possibles are not and will not be; the fact
that Aristotle admits of the non-realization of some possibles is already
enough.
This is clearly the way Bayle understood the Master Argument's
third proposition. "The very famous dispute of possible things and
impossible things owed its inception to the doctrine of the Stoics re-
garding fate. The question was whether, among the things which never
have been and will never be, there are possibles, or if all that is not, all
that never has been, all that never will be, was impossible".18 And at
because it can be actualized (in de Int., 23a6-23°15). As for the natural (irrational)
possible ad unum, Cajetan (in St. Thomas, 1875, vol. 22, p. 89; Oesterle, 1962,
p. 219), in referring to the Metaphysics (Q, 2, 1046"36 sq.) remarks that, besides
their inapplicability to opposites, the active potency which is their raison d'etre
enters necessarily into operation as soon as the subject is present and impediments
are removed. Heat necessarily heats a material which is present, once all insulation
is removed.
To keep the original sense of the possible ad unum, that of a virtuality which
develops necessarily, once all impediments are dropped, let us call it a virtue. To
speak of the virtue of p is to say that it is possible that p ad unum. On the other
hand, let us call a possible in opposita chance. To speak of the chance of p is to
say that it is possible contingently that p.
Must we grant the axiom of necessity for virtue, while refusing it for chance
(23° 15-16)? If it is necessary that a material substance perish then it is possible ad
unum that it perish. This is in contrast to chance. If Socrates can be seated and
not be seated, in opposita, then there is no necessity of either one.
It must be added that a possible ad unum develops its actualization only on
the supposition of the existence of its subject. But that existence itself remains
contingent and has to do with possibles ad opposita. Once born, it is necessary
that Socrates die. That Socrates be born is contingent.
18
Leibniz, Gerhardt, 1978, p. 212; Jalabert, 1962, p. 223.
RECONSTRUCTION OF THE DE CAELO DEMONSTRATION / 33
the end of the passage19 he goes on to add: "I think that the Stoics took
it upon themselves to give a greater extension to possible things than
to future things in order to soften the awful and odious consequences
drawn from their dogma of fatalism". Leibniz too gives reasons, and
different from Aristotle's, as to "why one is mistaken or at least speaks
very incorrectly when one says that there is no possible but that which
is or what God has chosen; this is the error of Diodorus the Stoic in
Cicero, and of Abelard, Wyclef and Hobbes among the Christians". 20
Cicero's text is indeed definite. In the De Fato (VII, 13) he inter-
prets this third premise as: "Some events which will not take place are
possible", when "Diodorus says 'That alone (solum) is possible which
is either true or will be true; whatsoever (quicquid) will not be is im-
possible' ".
The Master Argument's third premise will then be accorded the
same sense as the corresponding De Caelo premise—the sense of a
particular proposition: namely, there is a possible that will not be
realized. It is precisely because this premise is a particular that we are
permitted to reason on an illustrative case. In doing this, we will be
justified in construing the premise as a conjunction where it is affirmed
that a same event is possible which neither is nor will be realized.21
relation).
D Ct0pt =D/~ Lto ~ pt- ~ LtoPt-
(a) (t0)[(3t')(t' < t0- ~ pt,) D (t)(t0 <t-~ Ltt
AA (t)(to){[(CtoPt •t<t0) = (t<t0-t0 = t)}-
(Ctopt • t < to)}
BA
Demonstration
tDN = tvN <tDN <t
(\~PDPVQ)
2- (t)[(CNpt • t< N) = (t < N • N < t)}
(A, Simplification, 1, Syll.).
3. (t)~(t<N-N<t)
(A, Simplification, 2, h (~ P • P = Q) D~ Q).
The following diagram will help the reader get a firmer grip of the
demonstration.
(B)
(Contraction)
-» v
N N
(A)
(Necessity
of the past)
(A,B)
(NH)
M P
(Conditional t t
necessity) P.t
(A, B, NH)
->t
N
(C)
(Existence of a
never realized T»t
possible)
Part II
43
44 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
In the second place, once this subsidiary question is taken care of,
the Diodorean definition still leaves a doubt. In eliminating modality in
As a matter of fact, propositions have an essential occurrence only within opaque
contexts of discourse, i.e. in contexts liable to change their truth-value in the case
of substitution of expressions having the same denotation but not the same sense,
and particularly of sentences having the same truth-value but not belonging to the
same proposition. The modal operators are among these opaque contexts. For
example, granted the identity:
Scott = the author of Waverley
and the modal logical truth
necessarily Scott is identical with Scott
it is doubtful that the following sentence can be held true:
necessarily the author of Waverley is identical with Scott.
But Diodorus, in defining the modalities the way he does, does not overstep the
bounds or the means of expression characteristic of first order predicate logic. That
is a logic comprising only the connectives (and, or, not) and quantifiers over only
individuals and instants of time, which in turn guarantee its extensionality. All
opaque contexts are excluded.
Under these conditions it is only by virtue of their truth-values that sentences
enter into reasoning. Since sentences having the same meaning, have a fortiori
the same truth value, any proposition could be replaced by one or the sentences
belonging to it as to a synonomy class.
Why not then just settle for talk about sentences rather than insisting on the
neutral term statement"?
In the first place, Sextus Empiricus (Adversus Mathematicos, VIII, 11-13, and
132-139) speaks of the disagreement among the dogmatic schools on the subject of
truth. Some placed truth and falsity in the thing signified, others in the sound, and
others in the movement of the intellect. The first then distinguish the signifier or
sentence, the reference or existing thing, and the signified or "proposition"; and it
is to the proposition that they attribute a truth-value. This is the stance taken by
the Stoics. The Epicureans do not admit or meanings (the signified) between the
signifier and the thing. It is to the sentence that they attribute truth-value. Sextus
does not specifically mention the adherents of the third doctrine, which we would
call "psychologist" today. It can be seen that Aristotle doesn't hesitate to insist on
the importance of beliefs. In any case, accordingly as one considers an individual
movement of the intellect or a class of such movements, one falls back upon the
distinction between sentence and proposition, psychologically interpreted. We do
not know to which of these parties Diodorus belonged. It is possible that it should
have been to the Stoic one.
In the second place, in its original formulation, the Master Argument does use
modal operators; and it can be taken as refuting Aristotle only on the supposition
that such operators have propositions as argument. Even if the Diodorean defini-
tions free us from making that supposition, it is still a good idea to carry over a
trace of it in the polemical means of expression Diodorus used.
It is important for the sequel (especially 3.5) that propositions, in the sense here
adopted, are temporally indexed. For example, the proposition that I shall be in
Paris on January 14, 1995, as the class of sentences like 'Ich werde am 14. Januar
1995 in Paris sein', is at the future as are all the sentences of the equivalence class.
Therefore the truth-value shifts are the same for the proposition and for these
48 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
axis of truth
Now Now
Interpreted in terms of statement, the necessary gives rise to two states
of affairs. The first is the same as that given above, to which is added:
T N P.(t)(t>N z>Ttp)
II
Now Now
where the 'T' in the formulas is to be taken as 'it is true that'. Analo-
gous schemata, symmetrical for the false, would model the sense of the
two interpretations for the impossible.
The situation is similar with respect to the weak modalities. In-
terpreted in terms of prepositional functions, the possible signifies that
it is true or that it will be true that a certain event should occur: in
50 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
other words, that a certain event is occurring or will occur. Two states
of affairs correspond to this first interpretation:
P| T N pv(3t)(t>N.T tP )
I 4 > !
Now „ ! !
P|
ii -^ L
Now t Now
Any model in which the realization of the verifying event would pre-
cede the now is excluded. The interpretation in terms of statement
however is not subject to this limitation. Whatever the statement is,
thus whatever the real time at which its verifying event is seen to be
realized, that statement is possible if it is true now or at some ulterior
moment of time. But any genuine past proposition fits in precisely
with this condition. There are consequently three states of affairs cor-
responding to the interpretation of the possible in terms of statement.
The first two are identical with those given above, to which is added:
T N pv(3t)(t>N.T tP )
III
Now
Analogous schemata, symmetric for the false, would model the sense
of the two interpretations for the possibly-not.
It is seen then, in the case of both the strong and the weak modali-
ties, that if a declaration is necessary, impossible, possible or possibly—
not on the interpretation in terms of prepositional function then it is
a fortiori necessary, impossible, possible or possibly—not on the in-
terpretation in terms of statement. The inverse implication does not
hold.
In the two interpretations can be found the trace, so to speak,
that the two modal usages have left in the very definition that elim-
inates them. The interpretation in terms of prepositional function
corresponds to the modalities de re, which, since they attach to the
properties of things, fall within the quantifier's scope. The interpre-
tation in terms of statement corresponds to the modalities de dicto,
THE OBJECT OF THE DlODORBAN MODALITIES / 51
drawn.12 The second example is: 'If there exist no indivisible elements,
then indivisible elements exist'. It begins with the false and ends with
the true, and that disposition always holds.13
We could, to begin with, construe the expressions 'motion exists',
'the void exists', 'indivisible elements exist' not as statements in them-
selves but as prepositional functions. The Epicurean conditional would
then signify that for any time t whatsoever, if motion exists at that
time then the void exists at that time. The complete and exact form of
the expressions 'motion exists', 'the void exists', 'indivisible elements
exist' would be rendered by 'motion exists at time t\ 'the void exists at
time t' and 'indivisible elements exist at time t\ Diodorean implication
then would not be different from a universal proposition in terms of
times.14 As the binding of the variable would be over two prepositional
functions, the implication would express nothing other than a law of
physics in the modern sense of the term. Its model would be a propo-
sition of the type 'Snow is white' that would be rendered in temporal
terms as 'if something is snow at time t, it is white at the same time V.
Consequently, since the truth-values are fixed simultaneously for the
antecedent and consequent of the conditional, it would be excluded
that, at one and the same time, the antecedent could be true when the
consequent is false. And this is in conformity with Diodorus' requisite.
The specious character of this interpretation becomes obvious as
soon as we consider what Diodorean implication was meant to do.
Sextus has conserved two of Diodorus' arguments intended to block
objections made to him when he said that there is nothing which is in
motion but only something that has been in motion.15 It was objected
that "if preterites are true, it is impossible that their presents should
be false and they must be true; and similarly, the preterites must be
false when the presents are false".16 Among Diodorus' replies, two
have to do with the question of the role played by the movement of
12
Sextus Empiricus, M, VIII, 330-333 (Bury, II, pp. 412-413; Doring, fr. 143, p. 44).
13
Sextus Empiricus, PH, II, 110-111 (Bury, I, pp. 222-223; Doring, fr. 141, p. 43).
14
Mates, 1961, pp. 45-46.
15
Sextus Empiricus M.X.86 (Bury, III, pp. 252-253; Doring, 1972, fr. 123, p. 35).
As pointed out by Sedley (1977, pp. 85-86), the Diodorean passage here echoes
that of Aristotle showing that if the theory of indivisibles applied to time is true,
then there will have been motion without there being motion (Physics, Z, 231*
21-232a17, 24068-24106). If we go along with Sedley in thinking that Diodorus
is replying to Aristotle here, this correspondence suggests that Diodorus takes the
Aristotelian implication as holding and that, since he does admit the antecedent
(temporal indivisibles) as well, he is contesting the absurdity of the consequent,
which Aristotle had simply rejected.
16
Sextus, M, X, 91 (Bury, III, pp. 255-256; D6ring, 1972, p. 35).
54 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
truth. To begin with,17 he says that preterites may be true when their
presents are false. The past-tense proposition 'these men married' may
be true at one and the same time when the corresponding present-tense
proposition 'these men are marrying' has never been true. It is suffi-
cient for this to be so that the men in question should have married
at different moments of the past. The correspondence would require
that they should have married simultaneously. The second argument18
is of the same sort. The past-tense proposition 'Helen had three hus-
bands' may be true, because Helen was married three times, without
it's ever having been the case that the present-tense proposition 'Helen
has three husbands' is true, since the three marriages in question were
successive.
Independently of whether these arguments are sophistical, as Sex-
tus maintains,19 they prove that Diodorus does systematically use com-
plete temporal statements as antecedents and consequents of the con-
ditional. Formal implication over time has nothing to do with the time
proper of the propositions but only with that of their truth values. The
following schema illustrates why the conditional of the second example
is invalid. It could only be valid if the antecedent was never true when
the consequent is false.
,t 0
first marriage second marriage
The antecedent is the past-tense proposition about the conjunction
of the marriage at time t\ and the marriage at time fa. It is true
immediately after the accomplishment of time t^ and will never be false.
The consequent, on the other hand, is never true; it says that there was
a moment of the past at which both marriages were simultaneous.20
To say that there has been a first marriage at time t\ and a second
at time t? is to utter authentic statements, and not to speak in terms
of prepositional functions as the first interpretation would have had
it. Formal implication has to do with the truth, which varies with the
time of these statements. Formal implication here is nominalist.
What is more, Diodorean implication, as opposed to a formal im-
plication that would directly involve propositional functions, must be
17
Sextus, M, X, 97 (Bury, III, pp. 258-259; Doring, 1972, pp. 35-36).
18
Sextus Empiricus, M, X, 98 (Bury, III, pp. 258-259; Doring, 1972, p. 36).
19
Sextus Empiricus, M, X, 99-100 (Bury, III, pp. 260-261; Doring, 1972, p. 36).
20
Formally, the falsified implication is the following:
THE MEANING OF DlODOREAN IMPLICATION / 55
ity. The future does not haunt the limit-present in the guise of a need.
It will be, or else it already is. There is time, but no becoming. There
is the generated and the destroyed, but no generation or destruction.
From the truth of the fact that there has been motion, it cannot be
concluded that it has been true that there was motion then—or, again,
that it is true that there was a passage. The whole demonstration
hinges on an implication of which the antecedent says that there has
been motion and the consequent that there has been passage. Those
are both complete statements: the first true, the second false. The
formal implication that fails to establish a connection between them
has to do with their truth-values and not with their content.
24
To use Rescher's expression, 1971.
25
Accordingly as dated declarations are made before, during or after the dated
event described, some languages maintain a reference to the time of speaking in
the verb of what is said. In such languages, this recourse to conjugation is seen as
encompassing the variations necessary for establishing the synonymy of statements
in virtue of the rule: accordingly as a statement about a dated event is made
before, during or after that event, the statement must be in the future, present or
past tense. The logical status of the declaration though is not affected by these
necessary grammatical modifications.
A date can only be determined with respect to a point of origin. The question
will still arise whether there isn't ultimately need of an "egocentric particular" for
fixing the point of origin. We won't go into this question here, as its solution would
have no bearing on the interpretation of the Diodorean definitions.
DlODOREAN NOMINALISM / 57
The plan the inquiry must follow lies traced before us. We must
determine the respective merits of the two interpretations distinguished
in section 3.2, first for the case of indefinite declarations, then for the
case of dates and pseudo-dates. It is the first case that presents the
major difficulties.
In cases where the modality governs an apparent present or a sub-
junctive, as in English and French, one will be tempted to think that
the realist interpretation is imperative: that the modal expression is
derived from a prepositional function and that the movement of truth
will have then determined the time of the event. Instead of indicating
the simultaneity of the event with the time of utterance, this present
and this subjunctive will be taken as indicating the simultaneity of
the event with the time induced on the variable of the prepositional
function by the truth predicates or directly by a grammatical tense.26
Quoting the Diodorean definition of the possible, Alexander of Aphro-
disias does away even with the predicates of truth and falsity, assign-
ing the time directly from a non-temporal verbal form. "According
to Diodorus it is possible for me to be in Corinth in the case where
I am in Corinth or in the case where I will go to Corinth. But if I
were never to be in Corinth, that would not have been possible. And
to become a grammarian is possible for a child, if it becomes one one
day".27 There is no room here for ambiguity. There is a possible when
the thing presently is or will be realized.28 Boethius also reports the
Diodorean definition of possibility in purely objective terms on two dif-
ferent occasions,29 without any mention of the truth-predicate. That
26
To designate the object of the modalities the definitions employ a neuter pronoun
(Cicero and Boethius use quod, Plutarch onep Alexander o). When any precision
is furnished it is by way of translation into a substantified infinitive (TO -fevecrdat.,
says Alexander). In short, one is tempted to think that where the French and
English employ the subjunctive ('il est possible que j'aille a Paris', 'it is possible
that I should go to Paris'), the Ancients use expressions that exclude a determinate
tense, consequently appealing to propositional functions determined by the truth
predicates, for want of a direct translation in terms of grammatical tense.
27
1883, p. 184.
28
Plutarch (De Stoic, rep. 46, 1055 D-E; Doring, 1972, fr. 134, p. 40; in Plutarch's
Moralia, 1976, XIII, 2, p. 589), Philoponus (1905, 169, 17-21; Doring, 1972, fr. 136,
p. 41), Simplicius (1907, 195, 31-196, 24. Doring, 1972, fr. 137, p. 41) all record
the Diodorean definition of the possible in objective terms of that which is or will
be. Cicero, in the De Fato (6, 12, 7; Doring, 1972, fr. 132 A, p. 39) links the two
definitions. Diodorus, he says, "says that that only can happen which is true or
will be true, and all that is future, he says that it is necessary that it happen, and
all that is not future, he denies that it may happen". The time that counts for
characterizing the modality is that of the event, not that of truth.
29
Boethius, 1880, 234, 10-235, 9 and 412, 8-21 (Doring, 1971; fr. 138-139, pp. 42-
43). The commentary of Boethius leaves no doubt as to his interpretation of the
58 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
is possible which is or will be, says the definition. The possible then
assigns the present or the future to an indefinite declaration in the
apparent present, which is nothing but a propositional function.
Those who would settle for this semblance, however, would be mak-
ing a double mistake. Historically, they would be taking over arguments
of the commentators close to Aristotelian realism to interpret Diodorus,
whom we saw staunchly refusing to admit the notion of real potential-
ity. Logically, they would be forgetting that a realist possible justifies
a nominalist possible a fortiori. Take the statement 'I am now or will
be in Corinth'. To say that that statement is possible is to say that it
is true now or that it will be true that I am now or that I will be in
Corinth. The truth conditions on the statement are the same as the
satisfaction conditions that were on the propositional function.
To decide between these interpretations two conditions must be
met.
1. Cases must be found in which the realist interpretation errs by
defect or, what comes down to the same thing, cases where the nom-
inalist interpretation errs by excess. The discovery of such cases is a
necessary condition for distinguishing between the two interpretations.
It would not be a sufficient condition however if one could impute an
equivocal usage to Diodorus.30
2. This supposed ambiguity, which moreover contradicts the rep-
utation Diodorus enjoyed,31 loses all verisimilitude if we show that
it upsets the relations of the 'logical square of opposition' that the
Diodorean definitions of the modalities lead us to expect.32
matter. "While there are two principal parts of the possible: one which is said of
that which, though non-existent, can nonetheless exist, the other which is predi-
cated of that which already is something in act and not just potentially, this sort
of possible that already is in act gives rise in turn to two further sorts of possi-
ble: one which, though existent, is not necessary, the other which, existing, further
renders this possible necessary. And it was not only the subtlety of an Aristotle
that recognized this fact. Diodorus too defined the possible as that which is or will
be. Thus Aristotle holds possible that which Diodorus calls 'future', which, while
it doesn't exist, can nonetheless come to be. As for what Diodorus called 'present',
it is what Aristotle interprets as being possible, which is said possible precisely
because it already is in act". Whatever the validity of the comparison Boethius
makes between Diodorus and Aristotle—for in speaking of a possible that is not
but can be, Aristotle is not automatically talking about what will be—there is one
thing that is sure: Boethius does take Diodorus to hold that the possible is that
which is or will be in act.
30
According to Mates (1961, p. 39), the attribution of necessity in the Master
Argument's first premise requires taking the word 'necessary' in another sense than
that used in the definitions of the modalities, or of the weak modalities at least.
31
Sedley, p. 103. See above ch. I, note 22, p. 10.
DlODOREAN NOMINALISM / 59
Necessary Impossible
[is true and will not be false) < tries (is false and will not be true)
SB SB
%>. -^P «
•Jx ,fN C
<X rv°
•y^'JO |-OJ
3
CO to
Possible Non-necessary
(is true or will be true) subcontraries (is false or will be false)
Square of Modal Opposition according to Diodorus.
(Kneale, 1962, p. 125). Of two contradictories one is true, the other false. Two
contraries cannot both be true, but can both be false at the same time. Two sub-
contraries cannot both be false, but can both be true at the same" time. There is a
relation of descending implication between subalternates: the necessary (impossi-
ble) is possible (non-necessary). A realist expositor like Mates agrees that the laws
of the logical square must be respected (p. 37).
33
See next page.
60 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
statement turns out to be true it will become false once the event is
accomplished, since from that moment on the death of Fabius at sea
will take place no more. If the statement is false it will always be false
and is therefore impossible. Both interpretations are seen to agree
on the two cases: impossibility in case of falsehood, contingency in
case of truth. Nevertheless, the contingency for the realist is based on
the unicity of the event, whereas for the nominalist it is based on the
changing truth-value. Both interpretations will confuse the case of the
eclipse with that of the death of Fabius in the same treatment. But
the nominalist confusion, based simply on the movement of truth, is
due to a more superficial reason and is therefore more acceptable than
the realist confusion that puts the two events on a par.
From the realist point of view 'There was a naval battle at Salamis'
is an assertion which stricto sensu is verified neither now nor in the
future:
^ [ I 1 i i I I ' 1 [ I I ' I I i ! ! I [ I i * t
p N
It is therefore impossible and entails a negative possibility. From the
nominalist point of view it is necessary and entails a positive possibility,
given that its truth-value doesn't change any more after the event.34
34
The nominalist interpretation may be written as follows:
(3t)(t<N-Pt) DTN[(3t)(t<N.pt)].
(t')(t'>NoTt,[(3t)(t<N.pt)])
= Lnom(3t)(t <N-pt)
3 Mnom(3t)(t <N-pt)
= TN[(3t)(t<N.pt)]
V(3t')(t'>N-Tt,[(3t)(t<N-pt)]).
(The symbols 'Ln0m' and 'M nom ' are here taken as designating nominalist necessity
and possibility respectively, as 'Lreai' and 'A/ reo /' will be taken as designating the
corresponding notions on the realist interpretation).
If, on the realist interpretation:
Mr€alP5PNV(3t')(t' >N-pt>),
the formula expressing that p is past is substituted for p:
Mreal P = [(3t)(t < N •Pt)]N V (3t')(t' > N • [(3t)(t < N •Pt)]t, )
the resulting formula will illustrate the Aristotelian De Caelo passage: it will be
true to say now that next year is last year. All semblance of paradox vanishes when
the invalidity of the conditional
*Lnom 3 A/reaf
is brought to light.
The realist can, with Aristotle, demonstrate the 'necessity' of the past in his
language. He will posit:
t < N D~ MptV ~ M ~ PJ,
DlODOREAN NOMINALISM / 61
69
70 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
nation and reprobation are of this sort, for they are all equivalently
about the future, even if grammatically they are in the present or the
past. Therefore 'Peter was predestinate' is contingent just as is 'Peter
is predestinate'."5
II. The entire difficulty lies in giving formal expression to that in-
tuition. Consider first a logic of pseudo-dates. To this effect we shall
construct an 'Ockhamist structure' representing a plurality of possi-
ble evolutions of a possible world. An 'Ockhamist model' is obtained
by the assignment of truth-values to the prepositional variables of a
structure. Since a structure is made up of a unique past, but of several
branches for the future, the evaluation of a variable will be relative to
a particular route. In such a model,8 a) the logical pre-determination
of the future is satisfied, just as it is in the metaphysics of Leibniz;
b) the distinction between propositions about the past and those sim-
ply formally in the past can be read off the formulas themselves; c)
propositions about the past are necessary; and d) the entailment of ne-
cessitarianism is blocked. It will be possible to distinguish between a
proposition about the past, even if couched in a grammatical future ('In
two days I shall have arrived four days ago'), and a proposition about
the future ('There will be a conflict in ten years') even if it occurs in a
grammatical past ('Three years ago there was bound to be a conflict in
thirteen years').7 In 'Ockham's system' thus conceived it is legitimate,
on the basis of p, to conclude to the necessity n units of time ago that
it will be true, n units of time later, that p; the necessity here being
de dicto. By contrast, it is not allowed to infer from p that n units of
time ago it was the case that necessarily n units of time later it will be
true that p. This would amount to a de re predication of necessity.8
Predetermination then is seen to be purely logical. From among all
future propositions, equally determined from the logical point of view,
we could distinguish the proper subset of propositions which are, in ad-
dition, causally true and determined in that the present or past causes
of their truth already exist. In any case, there is nothing that obliges
taking this subset as coextensive with the set of all futures. 9
5
Ockham, 1945, pp. 5-6; 1969, p. 38.
6
Boudot, 1973, p. 456.
Propositions about predestination and reprobation are of this last sort (Ockham,
1969, p. 38).
8
The formula p D LPnFnp is thus legitimate, but not the formula p D PnLFnp.
9
Boudot, 1973, pp. 460-462. It is seen here that predetermination in the sense
of the Ockhamist system is weaker than Leibnizian predetermination which in-
cludes, rather than excludes, causal necessity (Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, p. 27 and
pp. 123-124; Jalabert, 1962, p. 38 and p. 130). What is called predetermination
in Ockham's sense corresponds simply to foreknowledge and futurition, whereas
74 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
tion, the second with a grammatical one. They are in conformity with
the maxim of economy proper to Ockham but are characteristic of all
nominalism as well.
Nominalism applied to the modalities posits as principle that they
are properties of discourse, not of things. This principle, moreover, is
general, as can be seen from its application to the problem of universals.
Either language is separable from ontology and the laws governing the
entities of language commit us to nothing with respect to being: any
liberties taken then with the laws of language will be without danger,
since these laws govern only the use of signs. Or, if there is a suspicion
that such-and-such linguistic usage does commit us with respect to
being, all the laws having to do with those usages, and whose mixed
character would allow the surreptitious extension of simple linguistic
conventions to ontological commitments, will be eliminated as dubious.
As for the modalities then, either it will be posited that the modal laws
have to do only with the manipulation of certain symbols, or those that
seem to have a mixed—viz. a metaphysically dangerous—character will
be proscribed.
But just what is a modality that has to do only with discourse? It
is a modality whose scope contains a complete sentence , an expres-
sion of discourse. When the expression contains a quantifier, whether
explicitly or implicitly—as, for instance, when 'p was' is taken as equiv-
alent to 'it has not always been the case that not-p'—the modality is
de dicto if the modal operator precedes the quantifier. Consider on the
other hand an expression in which one of these quantifiers has been
'exported' and placed in front of the modal sign. This latter sign will
then govern an expression containing a free individual variable. This
is the case that arises, for instance, when it is said that there is an
x such that it is possible (necessary) that x has a certain property.
Two interpretations seem to be open here.12 Either exportation of the
quantifier will be given a weak sense in which modality and predicate
are still taken separately. The modal operator will govern a preposi-
tional function then, rather than a proposition. Or the predicate could
be taken as argument of the modal operator, in which case the two to-
gether would henceforth be treated as a single predicate. The reading
then would no longer be 'it is possible (necessary) that x has a certain
property' but 'a; has a certain possible-(necessary-) property'.
The Scholastics had a clear vision of the distinction between modal-
ity de re and modality de dicto. Buridan, for example, in his commen-
12
Hughes and Cresswell, 1972, pp. 183-184, footnote 131, which suggests distin-
guishing between L(ifx) and [Ltp}x.
THE FIRST CONJECTURE / 77
16
Id., ibid, p. 191.
16
Id., ibid, p. 195: cf. I' 2 .
I7
ld., ibid, pp. 199-200, ft.n. 151.
78 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
27
Boudot, 1973, pp. 471-472.
82 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
not will A. In the composed sense: the will that wills A does not will
A is an absurd and impossible proposition. In the divided sense and
taken in the order of succession the proposition is acceptable, for the
will37 can will a certain object at a moment A and not will it at mo-
ment B. But even in a given instant, the proposition remains true in
the divided sense; for even though the will that wills A cannot not will
it that will that wills A is such that it may not will it. Even willing it at
moment A, it is of itself capable of not willing it at moment A. Scotus
recognizes that this is a difficult distinction to grasp: obscurior, but it
is well-founded, for, in the divided sense, it justifies the possibility of
two distinct affirmative possibilities: the one saying that the will wills
at the moment A, the other that it is possible that the will not will at
the moment A. Being about the same time, but not about the same
object, they can be simultaneously true; and indeed they are, for it is
true that at the very moment at which the will is not willing it can
will, and that, willing one object, it could will another.
Ockham refuses Scotus' capacity without succession in arguing that
such a possible could not be realized. "This nonevident capacity can
be actualized by no capacity, since if it were actualized the will would
will something at t\ and not will it at ti, and so contradictories would
evidently be true at one and the same time".38 Therefore, "it is in-
consistent to say that the divine will as naturally prior posits its effect
in reality at t\ in such a way that it can not posit it in reality at the
same instant. For there are no such instants of nature as he [Scotus]
imagines, nor is there in the first instant of nature such an indiffer-
ence as regards positing and not positing. Rather, if at some instant
it posits its effect in reality, it is impossible by means of any capacity
whatever that both the instant occurs and the effect does not occur at
A because they signify that their predicates are attributed to the subject during
the same instant. But this is true. For proper to that will in the same instant is
not willing A together with the possibility of the opposite at A as is signified by
the proposition about the possible.
"There is an example of this distinction in the proposition: all men who are white
run. Being posited that all white men run and no blacks or dark-skinned men, it is
true in the composed, and false in the divided sense. In the sense of composition it
is a proposition having a unique subject determined by: who are white. In the sense
of division there are two propositions stating two predicates of the same subject.
Likewise for the proposition: all men who are white are necessarily animals. In the
sense of composition it is false, because the predicate is not proper necessarily to
all this subject. But in the sense of division it is true, because two predicates are
affirmed of a same subject, one necessarily, the other absolutely without necessity,
and both are appropriate, and the two categorical propositions are true".
37
Created.
38
Ockham, 1945, p. 33; 1969, p. 85.
88 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
with the potentiality of its opposite. Ockham replies that there is in-
compatibility here, since to realize the contrary possible would be to
enter into contradiction with the act. The divine will itself cannot do
that. What is clear is that Ockham admits the principle of conditional
necessity. The act, while it is, excludes the capacity for its opposite
whose realization can take place only after it itself will have disap-
peared. But that successive representation of potentiality, as legitimate
as it may be in suggesting something positive in the potentiality and
going beyond the simple logical reality or non-contradiction, appears
to be ill-founded in Ockham. When he claims to reduce Duns Scotus
to the absurd, he is, in reality, simply giving in himself to the sophism
of the distribution of the modalities, confusing the real contradiction
between act and contrary act with the apparent contradiction between
act and contrary possible.41
contradiction. It wills in willing them simultaneously, not however that they should
exist together, but it wills simultaneously that they should be able to happen [here
I propose correcting forte to fore] not in conjunction but in division. And just
as divine intuition sees the contingency of causes and the effects that will result
contingently from them, so does the divine will will that created causes act in a
contingent manner, or, on the contrary, a necessary one, according to the order of
causes" (see the end of note 36).
41
Duns Scotus explicitly contests the principle of conditional necessity in a text
that highlights his virtuosity as a dialectician: Vives, t. 10, 1843, In librum primum
sententiarum, pp. 630-631.
"Aristotle's proposition: it is necessary for whatever is that it be while it is can
be categorical or hypothetical, as is also the proposition: it is necessary that an
animal run, if a man runs. As a conditional, this latter gives rise to a distinction
accordingly as necessary can mean to say the necessity of consequence or of the
consequent. In the first sense it is true, in the second false. But the second which
is a categorical, signifies that the whole: should run if a man runs is predicated of
animal with the mode of necessity, and the categorical is true, because the predicate
thus determined belongs necessarily to the subject. But it is not a question of the
predicate absolutely and hence to conclude from the predicate thus determined to
the predicate taken absolutely is the error secundum quid ad simpliciter. Likewise
I say here that if Aristotle's proposition is accepted as a temporal hypothetical,
then the necessity notes the necessity of the consequence or that of the consequent.
If of the consequence, it is true; if of the consequent it is false. But if taken as a
categorical, then what is, while it is, does not determine an implicit composition
in what is, but a principal composition signified by the fact that what is should be,
and then the predicate that that be when it is is affirmed of the subject which is
with the mode of necessity, and in this way the proposition is true. Thus it doesn't
follow that it is necessary that it be, but there is a sophism of secundum quid ad
simpliciter, as appears in the other case. Hence no true sense of this proposition
denotes that being something in the instant where it is be simply necessary, but
only be necessary secundum quid, i.e. when it is, and as this is in harmony with the
fact that in the instant where it is the thing is simply contingent, it is consequently
in harmony also with the fact that in that instant its opposite can belong to it."
90 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
In all likelihood neither Scotus nor Ockham knew the Master Argu-
ment. It just happened that similar difficulties gave rise to responses
that can be compared systematically with those of the Ancients.
Scotus clearly expresses the consequence for freedom of calling conditional neces-
sity into question (ibid., p. 637).
"Just as our will, in so far as naturally prior with respect to its act, produces
that act in such a way that it should be able at the same instant to produce the
opposite act, so the divine will, in so far as it is itself under a volition, is naturally
prior with respect to such a tendency and tends to that object contingently, in such
a way that in the same instant it can tend to the opposite object. And this is so
from the point of view both of the logically possible (which is the non-contradiction
of terms, as was said regarding our will) and of the real capacity, which is prior
with respect to its natural act."
In his Commentary in the Vives edition, Lychet sets down Ockham's objections:
1. There is not such a nonevident capacity for opposites in the same instant, for
no capacity, not even an infinite one, could reduce such a capacity to act except by
a contradiction in the facts (p. 641). This argument is none other than the sophism
of distribution.
Gregory of Rimini answered this first argument in positing first (p. 643) "that
whatever is in a given instant can not-be in that instant, so that the proposition
stating that it is not can be true in that instant. This can be understood in three
ways, a) That this is possible in the composed sense, so that in that instant that
thing, at the same time as it is, is not in that instant. Then both the proposition
stating that it is and the proposition stating that it is not conjunctively and si-
multaneously in the same instant will be true. But this sense is truly impossible
because it implies a contradiction, b) It can be conceived or understood to be true
in the divided sense; and this in two ways. According to the first, the thing that
is in a given instant, can already, being posited in being, cease to be, and pass
from being to non-being in the same given instant. The proposition stating that
it is ceases to be true and from true becomes false, so that in that instant it is
false; and, conversely, its opposite ceases to be false and becomes true. But this
sense is impossible because such a passage and such a succession are not possible
in the instant. According to the second way, it is absolutely and simply possible
that this thing not be then and that it not be posited in being by its cause. The
proposition stating that it is not in that instant is true. This sense is true and in
no way improper."
2. Ockham's second argument against Scotus is based on the nature of the past
(p. 641).
"It is generally admitted by philosophers and theologians that God cannot make
a non-past of the past without its afterwards being true to say that the past was.
Therefore, since by hypothesis 'the will wills at A' is determinately true and, con-
sequently, always will be true afterwards, whereas 'the will does not will this at A'
never was true, 'the will did not will this at A' always was impossible."
Gregory of Rimini answers (p. 641). "Suppose that God can not make it happen
that the past not be the past (though many theologians contest that supposition).
I say that if the will wills something in the instant B, afterwards the proposition
'the will willed this in the instant B' will always be true, so that the consequence
'the will wills this at B' is necessary. Therefore, after B, the proposition 'the will
willed this in B' will always be true if it is formed. But I say that the antecedent
is contingent and can not-be-true, even in the instant B. And if one posits that it
is not true at B, as is possible to do in virtue of the third sense permitted, 'that
INADEQUACY OF OCKHAM'S SOLUTION / 91
Ockham hasn't really called the first premise into question. He has
simply removed an ambiguity attaching to one of its modal formula-
tions. He is not then comparable to Cleanthes. His entire thrust is
concerned with the distinction between the logical and the real, be-
tween predetermination of the true and predetermination of the cause.
If we measure the system we can attribute to him by its effectiveness
in resolving the Master Argument, Ockham's system remains weak
even when taken within the confines of Prior's reconstruction. Ockham
adopts the principle of conditional necessity. Applying to a sempiternal
event, it confers necessity on its whole duration. The one thing more
that could be said in Ockham's favor has to do with the negative char-
acter of the sempiternal event in question in the third premise: the
exact symmetry postulated between affirmative and negative propo-
sitions is dubious for the nominalist. What is more likely is that if
Ockham had known the Master Argument he would have taken it after
the manner of a Carneades: on the one hand, he would not have been
frightened by Diodorean necessitarianism since it concerns discourse
only but not reality; on the other, the formal truth of a proposition
does not entail a causal consequence, the predetermination of the true
is without ontological implication.42
will willed this at B', will not be true after B, nor, consequently, necessary either,
no more than its opposite will be impossible."
As for Ockham, it has been maintained that he too contested the Aristotelian
principle of conditional necessity. He does indeed write in his Commentary on
Chapter IX of the De interpretatione: "Sciendum est, quod ista propositio: Omne
quod est quando est necesse est esse, de virtute sermonis est simpliciter falsa."
(Quoted by Boehner in Ockham, 1945, p. 71). But by that Ockham means simply
that the absolute or simple necessity, i.e. not qualified by the temporal condition of
the quando of the thing or the event, must not be accepted. That false interpretation
of Aristotle rejected, Ockham accepts the principle in its authentic Aristotelian
form: "It is necessary, if a certain thing exists, that it exist then." (ibid.). He
elaborates: "...But the Philosopher says that this proposition is necessary: whatever
is, is, when it is; for this proposition cannot be false. The following proposition is
likewise necessary. Whatever was, was when it was. Likewise: whatever will be,
will be, when it will be." (ibid., p. 72).
What misled the commentator (ibid., pp. 70-72) is Lukasiewicz' interpretation
of Aristotle from which the temporal condition is omitted. The discussion against
Scotus proves the point. What is at stake, in the Aristotelian principle, is the
possibility of the coexistence at the same instant of an act and of the contrary
capacity. Ockham, along with Aristotle, denies that possibility that Scotus asserts
(cf. below, 9.1, pp. 227-228).
42
What Ockham refuses is not the principle of necessity but the inference that goes
from truth to necessary truth. His position is reminiscent of that of a Carneades
(cf. below, 8.2, pp. 209-210). Ockham does indeed refuse to pass from truth to nec-
essary truth. Boehner interprets this refusal (Ockham, 1945, p. 68) as a rejection
of the principle of conditional necessity, in view of Qu. Ha, B, ad sec. of the Trac-
92 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
changed, the other will not be and, with that posited, it cannot be
changed either."43
Leibniz seems to say that, after having identified the hypothetical
necessity of the past with that of the future, Cleanthes added something
to the hypothetical necessity of the past that explained why delibera-
tion could not apply to it. But what is that something else? Isn't it
precisely what for Aristotle and Diodorus and nearby all the Ancients
made the hypothetical necessity degenerate into a sort of absolute ne-
cessity, insisting that it is only a sort of absolute necessity because it is
solely retrospective and, insofar as the event is concerned, it has only
to do with its time, not its mode of production? And what was Leibniz'
own position? "Voluntary actions and their consequences", he writes
"will not take place whatever we do, whether we will then or not, but
because we will do and because we will will to do what leads to them.
And this is contained in the forecast and in the predetermination and is
even their reason for being. And the necessity of such an event is called
conditional, hypothetical, or again, necessity of consequence, because
it supposes the will and the other requisites; whereas the necessity that
destroys morals and that renders punishment unjust and reward su-
perfluous is in the things that will be no matter what we do and what
we will to do, and, in a word, in what is essential. And this is what we
call an absolute necessity. Nor will it serve at all, as regards what is
absolutely necessary, to make prohibitions or commandments, to pro-
pose penalties or rewards, to blame or to praise; it will not be any the
more or any the less for all that."44 Let us compare this passage with
that already quoted from the Nicomachean Ethics (Z, 2, 113965-11),
keeping in mind that voluntary choice and project do not apply to the
past.
Aristotle says that the past makes the conditional necessity of the
event degenerate into a sort of absolute necessity. Leibniz seems to
agree with him on this point, though he himself makes the conditions
on conditional necessity more stringent. It no longer suffices to apply
it to momentary events, because now there is the additional demand
for the requisites of voluntary deliberation. Leibniz even gives as his
reason for agreeing that it is a contradiction to suppose that we have
any effect on the past; but what is possible is that which is not the
antecedent of a contradictory consequence. If something is possible we
can have an effect on it; but we cannot have an effect on the past;
therefore the past is not possible. This is clear. Leibniz concedes that
43
Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, p. 214; Jalabert, p. 226.
44
Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, p. 380; Jalabert, p. 383.
94 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
the necessity of the past signifies nothing other than the impossibility
of realizing the possible in the past. But it is just this conclusion that
contradicts Cleanthes and puts Leibniz in agreement with most of his
adversaries, among whom Aristotle must be numbered as well.
To situate these Leibnizian intentions let us return to the Master
Argument. Leibniz praises Aristotle for having distinguished between
conditional and absolute necessity. He even claims to borrow this dis-
tinction from him. But he blames Aristotle for his doubts relating to
the principle of the excluded middle. But in Chapter IX of the De
Interpretatione Aristotle combines these doubts with that distinction
in order to escape the Master Argument whose three premises, which
Diodorus borrowed from him moreover, he admits. In crediting Clean-
thes with the distinction between the two sorts of necessity, Leibniz is
interpreting it as tantamount to a denial of the first premise, i.e. of
the absolute necessity of the past. Since he himself, given his theory
of possible worlds, admits the existence in the divine understanding of
possibles that will never pass over to an empirical existence and since
he does not challenge Diodorus' second premise, we can suppose that
what he attributes to Cleanthes is a doctrine quite like his own. To
think that the past is absolutely necessary is to blot out the distinc-
tion between conditional and absolute necessity. Every event, past or
future, is determined. But what is determined is in nowise necessary
if its existence-conditions, which caused or will cause it to be chosen,
depend not solely on the logical principle of non-contradiction, but on
the principle of the best, as well. But any event, in so far as it is part of
this world, exists on the condition of what Leibniz calls the free choice
of the best and what Cleanthes called Divine Providence.
This distinction of two necessities, which for Leibniz and for Clean-
thes as interpreted by Leibniz, though not for Aristotle, suffices for
avoiding fatalism, is itself amenable to two different forms of expres-
sion. On the one hand, in asserting that the past is hypothetically
necessary, one might be saying that it is necessary that an event oc-
cur if it has occurred; whence it is not possible to conclude that it is
simply and absolutely necessary that that event should have occurred.
On the other hand, one might posit that if an event has occurred, it
was necessary, during the time of its occurrence, that it should occur;
the necessity is thus conditional in that it depends on the duration of
a past event, whence again the impossibility of concluding that it was
simply and absolutely necessary that that event should have occurred.
On either of the two different forms of expression, the first of which
is more Leibnizian, the second more Aristotelian, although Aristotle
himself does not apply it to the past,conditional necessity entails a
THE SECOND CONJECTURE / 95
what this modal surplus consists that enables distinguishing the neces-
sity of the past from the necessity of the existent in general, without
assimilating it to metaphysical necessity for all that. For Leibniz, a
complete symmetry of past and future would probably have been seen
as entailing the nonsense of a Pierre Damien saying that God could
make what was not have been. If this is nonsense, it is because the
necessity of the past is specific in just that it is impossible to realize
the possible in the past. Time must then be taken to be asymmetrical
and linear. But if this is the case what has been gained for solving the
Master Argument? The interpretation of the first premise requires no
more than the irrevocability of the past. On the other hand, Leibniz
does not seem to contest the argument's other premises. He does have
the merit of showing the real difference there is between the irrevoca-
bility of the past and the necessity of a mathematical deduction. But
that is a difference Diodorus can accommodate.
There remains the question of the historical likelihood of the Leib-
nizian reconstruction. Let us first point out that the distinction be-
tween two sorts of necessity was known to the Ancients as an Aris-
totelian one. Had Cleanthes, the Stoic, taken it over from Aristotle,
the antique sources would have noted it. Above all, however, in in-
terpreting the first premise, Leibniz no more denies its validity than
had Ockham before him. The premise asserts the necessity of the past:
Ockham had clarified the sense of the word past, Leibniz clarifies the
sense of the word necessity. These clarifications purify, they do not
contest the premise itself.
The Epictetus passage reports that Cleanthes meant to reject the
premise, not to amend it. The conjectures advanced thus far are there-
fore irrelevant to his project. In particular, we have seen Leibniz de-
fend, without justification, the linearity of time, in order to safeguard
the asymmetry of past and future. It is in this way that it remained
impossible to realize the possible in the past. But if one is to inval-
idate the first premise, isn't it just that impossibility that must be
questioned?
There remains open then one last possible conjecture that would
allow for an interpretation in terms of physics and of the properly
Stoic conception of time and would negate the Master Argument's
first premise. First the condition of possibility of that interpretation
will be examined. It will then be shown that it seems to correspond to
Cleanthes' theory.
THE THIRD CONJECTURE / 97
that had come from the Chaldeans.64 Among all the Stoic doctrines it
is this one especially 'that represented the ethereal fire as the primor-
dial principle and held the stars to be the purest manifestation of its
power'.65
Cleanthes insisted on the astronomic basis of benevolence and fate.
His doctrine of the fire principle destined him to philosophically jus-
tify the sun-cult of the 'Chaldeans', as his Hymn to Zeus shows. It is
true that there is no extant text explicitly attributing a perfect numer-
ical interpretation of palingenesis to him, thereby setting him opposite
Chrysippus on this point. But all the remaining elements of his doc-
trine tend in this direction. It was thus within the logic of the system
to forgo the linearity of time and to draw from palingenesis what Ori-
gen considered to be the only consequence possible: perfect numerical
identity.66 But if time is symmetric, realizing the possible in the past,
and thereby inducing a reversal of time, is no longer absurd. What
scandalized Aristotle no longer presents a problem. Challenging the
Master Argument's first premise then-becomes legitimate.
In short, the Stoics extended to the universe as a whole the cyclical
return that had been restricted to the Heaven in Aristotle's system.
The ekpurosis realized a kind of synthesis of Heraclitus and Aristotle
and answered to Diodorus' negation of motion.
The fatalism of Cleanthes and Antipater 67 is no longer of a logical,
but of a physical, order. The total determination of the sublunar by
the supralunar world, in conformity with the astrological dogmas, and
the total stability of the system of astronomic equations, in conformity
with the dogma of eternal return, bring freedom down to the joyous
acceptance of destiny. It is this pantheism that supports the rejection
of Diodorus' first premise. As Stobaeus says, "As for Cleanthes, he
speaks as follows:... The tension that is in the substance of the universe
ceaselessly produces always the same revolution and same arrangement.
For just as all the parts of a same individual are born of seeds at the
proper times, so too do the parts of the universe, which include the
animals as well as the plants, come into being at the proper times.
And just as certain seminal reasons of the parts, condensing into a
seed, mix and separate again when the parts are born, so do all things
64
Cumont, 1929, pp. 160-162.
65
Cumont, 1912, p. 69; on Cleanthes' intelligible fire see Cumont, 1909, p. 15 note
2.
66
Origen, Contra Celsum, V, XX; Arnim, S.V.F., II, n.626, p. 190.
67
Who, in the Middle Stoa, maintained the doctrine of the conflagration.
THE THIRD CONJECTURE / 103
come from one sole being and all condense into one, the revolution
having been accomplished, and this in conformity with the order."68
68
Stobaeus, Eel. I, 17, 3, p. 153, 7 W (Arii Did., fr.38 Diels), Arnim, S.V.F., I,
n.497, p. 111.
Freedom as an Element of Fate:
Chrysippus.
105
106 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
at the rising of the dogstar and that he will die at sea' " (De Fato,
VIII, 15).
Just what does this rather odd-seeming transformation come down
to? If it is meant to reconcile fate and divination on the one hand
and to allow for non-necessary futures on the other, it must evidently
be that Chrysippus took this conjunctive form to be weaker than the
conditional one for which he had reproached the astrologers. As shown
by the passage quoted above (VII, 14), the astrological conditional ex-
presses a necessity: 'it is necessary that if anyone was born at the
rising of the dogstar, he will not die at sea'. As the antecedent is itself
necessary, since past, positing the necessity of the consequent, which
is future, becomes inevitable. It must be then that the change from
that conditional to the conjunctive form constitutes a weakening of as-
trological necessity. Since, for Chrysippus, the doubt cannot affect the
necessity attaching to the antecedent, it must be that the conjunctive
form weakens the very connection between antecedent and consequent.
What is the reason for that weakening in the force of the consequences?
Having distinguished 'sound' implication according to Philo and
according to Diodorus,2 Sextus goes on to examine a third theory
of the conditional, probably corresponding to the Chrysippean the-
sis. "Those who introduce the notion of connection (avvdpTrjaLt;) say
that the conditional is sound when the contradictory of its consequent
is incompatible with its antecedent. According to them, the condition-
als mentioned above to illustrate the doctrines of Philo and Diodorus
are unsound, but the following is true: 'If it is day, then it is day'."3
The conditional posited by Chrysippus is stronger then than that of
Diodorus and, a fortiori, than that of Philo. It is stronger than the
Philonian material implication and stronger than the Diodorean for-
mal implication, for Chrysippus adds a proper modal clause to the
conditional. The incompatibility between the negation of the conse-
quent and the truth of the antecedent transforms the conditional into
a sort of 'strict' implication,4 that is to say, into the statement of a
law. Since Chrysippus does not, however, spell out the nature of this
incompatibility—is it logical? physical?—it is not possible, without a
preliminary inquiry, to determine formally in just what the 'strictness'
of that implication consists. It must be added too that the example
given by Sextus could be misleading. When it is said that if it is day
2
See above, 3.3, p. 50.
3
Sextus Empiricus, PH II, 111-112.
4
A strict implication in Lewis' sense is one for which the conjunction of antecedent
and negation of the consequent is not possible. (Hughes and Cresswell, 1972,
p. 217).
108 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
The conditional given is 'if Dion is dead, this man is dead'. It is not
only true 12 but 'sound' as well, for there is incompatibility of negation
of consequent and affirmation of antecedent. This conditional that is
'sound' for Chrysippus is a fortiori so for Diodorus; it constitutes a
'strict' implication. Further, 'Dion is dead' is possible, for it can be
true one day that Dion should be dead. But 'this man is dead' is not
possible. Employment of 'this man' presupposes that one can show the
object in question, but precisely one can no longer show it once Dion
is dead.
We shall examine successively 1) just what Alexander's example
involves, 2) how it fits in with the question raised as regards the Master
Argument and 3) its connection with the conjunctive expression proper
to Chrysippean laws.
1) The argument could be taken as an ad hominem one.13 In that
case, it is the sentence 'This man is dead' that is impossible, because
one could never utter or formulate it.
But it is unnecessary to have recourse to the sentence and we can
suppose that the argument is formulated in terms of propositions and
is taken into account by Chrysippus himself. 'Dion is dead' or 'This
man is dead' will be taken then as a 'lecton', that is, as the class of
all sentences of the same form, completed by the specification of the
circumstances that determine their truth-values. Among the singular
propositions, two sub-classes may be distinguished. The simple mean
propositions are expressed by sentences of which the subject is a proper
The validity of the demonstration depends at step 4. on the validity of the impli-
cation
~ L ~ p D Mq,
that is to say, on the interdefinability of the modalities.
The sound Chrysippean implication is
p D q =~ M(p- ~ q),
which is equivalent in turn to ~ M ~ (p 3 q), but not to L(p D q).
Among the expressions used, it is surely (B') then that Chrysippus contests. The
care he takes in refusing to admit the 'conditional' form of the Chaldeans shows
that he accepts the validity of (Bi). Consequently, either 1) Chrysippus refuses
the implication ~ M ~D L in all cases and is driven, from contesting ( B 1 ) , to
contest 4 as well, or 2), which seems more probable, he limits the invalidation of
the implication to certain cases only, and postulates its validity in particular in
formulas beginning with L. He would then accept 4 in mathematical arguments,
for instance.
12
M. Frede, 1974, p. 116, says of this implicative statement that 4t is true, which
we must naturally understand in a Chrysippean sense. The statement:
(p D q) D (Mp D Mq)
can certainly be falsified.
13
Kneale and Kneale, 1962, p. 127.
112 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
fate does not mean fatalism no more than physical connection means
moral constraint. The future event, that Oedipus will be born of Laius
and assassinate him, is not necessary. Its necessity would only be de-
rived from the necessity of the intercourse of Laius and Jocaste (which
is granted since it has already occurred) if it were positively necessary
that it be not the case that this intercourse has taken place and that
it will not happen that Oedipus be born of Laius and not assassinate
him. But this positive necessity requires not only that, were that con-
junction capable of being true, it would be prevented from being so by
external circumstances, but also that it be actually false. Then at least
one of the conjuncts must be false. It cannot be the past event of Laius'
intercourse with Jocaste, which is true and even necessary. Therefore
it is the future event of the non occurrence either of Oedipus' birth or
of his assassination of Laius. The negative impossibility differs from
the positive necessity and does not imply it, because the truth of the
future is not already given within the truth of the past. Formulated as
an astrological conditional, fate entails not only the impossibility that
Oedipus will not be born of Laius, but the necessity that he will be.
The Idle Argument becomes legitimate then, since the necessity of the
consequent can be detached.25
The prediction concerning Oedipus ought therefore not to have been
of the form 'It is necessary that Laius have intercourse with a woman
and beget Oedipus' but only 'it cannot possibly not happen both that
Laius have intercourse with a woman and that he not beget Oedipus'.
It is probable that if the Stoics insisted on the clauses of non-prevention
in their definitions of the modalities it is because they expressed the
laws of nature in the form: it is not possible not to have such and such
a conjunction.
Fate has to do with condestinates. The illusion of necessity is due to
the fact that one of the assertions—the birth of Oedipus—was isolated
and made to support the entire causal chain. This is how the cele-
brated example of the cylinder can be explained. "Just as in pushing
a cylinder one has given it a beginning of motion, but has not given
it the capacity to roll, so a sense-presentation will surely impress and
25
Taking Pp — 'Laius had intercourse with a woman'
and
Fq = 'Oedipus will be born of Laius',
the law of condestinates will be written: ~ M(Pp- ~ Fq). Given Pp, and thus LPp,
all that can be concluded without appeal to the interdefinability of the modalities
is:
~ M(Pp- ~ Fq)- ~ M ~ Pp. The conditional law L(Pp D Fq), on the other hand,
together with the given Pp, allows the detachment of LFq as the Idle Argument
would have it.
118 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
mark its form in the soul, but the act of assent will be in our power;
pushed from without, as we said of the cylinder, it will move by its
own force and nature. If something were produced without antecedent
cause, it would be false to say that everything happens by fate; but if
it is likely that everything that happens has an antecedent cause, what
reason could be adduced for not recognizing that everything happens
by fate provided that the distinction and difference between the causes
is well understood?" 26
It cannot be that a certain cylinder should not have a certain mo-
tion, if an external impulsion is impressed upon it. It is not for all
that that this motion bespeaks a brute necessity. For from the point of
view of providence it is simply a question of not possibly not bringing
about a certain conjunction, given the maximum perfection of the work
in conformity with the principle of the best. And from man's point of
view it is simply a question of not being able to avoid the consequences
bound to his acts, without its being for all that that the assent he gives
to moving mental representations is a brute and inevitable consequence
of the impression they make.
Leibniz made a famous commentary on this passage and its contin-
uation by AuliusGellius 27 . Chrysippus' cylinder is similar to Leibniz'
boat swept along at a greater or lesser speed in a river current. On the
one hand such a possible has its own nature and spontaneity which are
formal and not material, as is misleadingly suggested by the metaphor
of the cylinder and of the boat too; and they constitute the perfec-
tion of the individual in which is encompassed its assent28. And that
is what accounts for freedom. From the point of view of theodicy on
the other hand, if it is objected that the sheer fact that the cylinder
is by nature rough, the boat heavy or ungainly, are so many argu-
ments against providence, the reply must be that the partial evil is
in view of the general good, like the vulgar epigrams and inscriptions
in ancient comedy.29 Cicero's development of these two themes in the
De Natura Deorum is proof enough of the connection between Leibniz
and Chrysippus.30 Neither for the one nor the other do providential
26
De Fato XIX, 43; Brehier, 1962, pp. 489-490; assent is not assigned by the specific
chain of mental images (Cherniss, 1976, II, p. 591, note e).
27
Noct. Alt. L. VI, c. 2, quoted by Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, p. 321; Jalabert, p. 326.
28
Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, p. 314; Jalabert, p. 328.
29
Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, p. 313; Jalabert, p. 327. Plutarch takes up the Stoic view
of comedy (Moralia, XIII, Part II, 1065; Cherniss, 1976, II, pp. 709-713) and turns
it against Chrysippus as impious. "But that refutation doesn't amount to much,"
says Leibniz (Gerhardt, VI, p. 313; Jalabert, p. 326).
30
Especially L. II, ch. XIV and XXXIII; Hamelin, 1978, pp. 94-95.
CHRYSIPPUS' NON-STANDARD MODAL SYSTEM / 119
ity of the causal modalities will be given up. To remedy the first, the
only singular terms admitted will be descriptions that keep the same
reference in all physically possible worlds. But this comes down to
saying that if it is causally necessary that a, and further that a = 6,
then it is causally necessary that b as well, where causal necessity has
nothing to do with our subjective manner of describing individuals, but
has to do rather with their proper essence.39 This 'causal essentialism'
is quite in keeping with the Chrysippean notion of fate.40
What is still missing in such systems is the explicit reference of
the Chrysippean modalities to a double temporal index and the corre-
sponding interpretation of the Master Argument's second premise.
The definitions, 41 or rather, elucidations (of the modal terms figur-
ing in the definiens) of Chrysippus are complex. Following M. Mignucci
we shall lay down the following conventions:
A means: 'p' is true
B means: 'p' can be false
C means: external circumstances prevent p's being false.
Replacing the word 'false' by 'true' and vice versa in these stipulations
we get:
A' means: 'p' is false
B' means: 'p' can be true
C' means: external circumstances prevent p's being true.
The definitions of necessity and of not-possibly-not (which will be dis-
tinguished from that of necessity), for example, will read as follows:
p is necessary (Lp) if and only if p is true and if p can be false it
is prevented by external circumstances from being so, that is
Lp = A.(B D C).
By contrast, the negative form 'it is not possible that not p' will be
written simply:
~ M ~ P = BDC,
where the assertion that A has disappeared. It is asserted only that if
'p' can be false, external circumstances prevent its being so. But there
39
F011esdal, 1965, pp. 272-273, who thus finds Prior's example again.
40
In such a system past and future are symmetric. But adjunction of the Master
Argument's first premise, admitted by Chrysippus, re-establishes the asymmetry of
time (that tempers the notions of absolute numerical identity in the eternal return
and thus opposes Chrysippus to Cleanthes). As for the system Q, it would seem to
have a good deal of affinity with the Aristotelian logic of possibles ad unum (the
virtues).
41
Mignucci, 1978; Vuillemin, 1983.
A SYSTEM RELATED TO PRIOR'S SYSTEM Q / 123
LpsA.(Bz)C) L-psA'.(B'z)C')
contraries
//
-subcontraries-
M-peB.-C
It is readily seen from this square of opposition why an impossible,
~ Mp, is compatible with the negation of a negative necessity, ~ L ~ p,
for there is opposition of contradiction between 'it is impossible that
124 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
p' and 'it is possible that p\ but not between 'it is impossible that p'
and 'it is not necessary that not p\
The question that arises at this point is that of the relation between
the double logical square of Chrysippean modalities and the double
temporal index figuring in the Master Argument's second premise. The
preceding arguments about the interdefinability of the modalities are
not sufficient to determine their meanings. But the occurrence of the
letters B and C in these definitions are enough to show that these
meanings do not belong to pure modal logic.
When Chrysippus says that from the strong Chrysippean antece-
dent
'If Dion is dead, then this man is dead'
the conditional consequent
'If it is possible that Dion is dead, then it is possible that this man
is dead',
logically follows, the strong antecedent would mean, according to the
definition of positive necessity, that 'If Dion is dead , then this man is
dead' is true and that if it is capable of being false external circum-
stances will prevent it from being false. But these strong antecedents
make the consequent false, in the case where 'Dion is dead' is true and
'this man is dead' is destroyed. We must therefore accept only the
weaker antecedent that it is not possible that Dion be dead and this
man not be dead, a conjunction which is indeed always true. Unfortu-
nately this conjunction does not authorize the consequent.
In the strong rejected antecedent as well as in the weak authorized
conjunction, we find two synchronic sentences, while the consequent is
a conditional whose antecedent states a diachronic modality and the
consequent a synchronic modality. This suggests that there must be
a connection between the Chrysippean non standard square and the
second premise.
Let us first examine what would mean for Chrysippus himself as
well as for the whole Stoic-Megaric school the second premise of the
Master Argument as put under its complete Aristotelian form, if no
distinction were made between weak and strong modalities:42
(B)cs(t)(MNPt D {(3*i)[MtlPtl • (« < ^ < Nv N < ^ < t)} •
(MtPt
42
The complete second premise says:
(t){MNPt D (Bti)Mtlptl • (t < ti < N V N < ti < t)} • (t)(Mtpt D pt)
This formula is equivalent to:
(t){(MNPt D (3ti)[MtlPtl -(t<t!<NvN<ti< t)]) • (Mtpt D pt)}
and entails the consequence by the law: [(P 3 Q) • R] D [P D (Q • R)}).
A SYSTEM RELATED TO PRIOR'S SYSTEM Q / 125
48
Metaphysique, & 5 1048° 16-21; see 2.4, p. 22; on this objection and the following
one see below, 10.1.
128 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
50
Hamelin, 1978, p. 84.
51
"Although that definition [the one Philo gives of the possible] does retain some-
thing Megarian, not only ... in that it leaves no room for genuine contingency,
but also in that it makes no appeal to external circumstances for weighing their
possibility, it is seen nevertheless to invoke these circumstances for determining the
real. This is meeting Stoicism midway" (Hamelin, 1978, p. 84). But Philo mentions
external circumstances only to eliminate them in his definition of the possible, if]
iirirriSeioTrjTi HOVR ('by virtuality alone'), so goes the Philonian definition accord-
ing to Simplicius (In cat., 195, 31-196, 24 Kalbfl.; Doring, 1972, p. 41, fr. 137).
There we have the point of view of a logician concerned with separating his science
from physics.
Part III
133
134 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
be. But it is impossible that that which cannot not occur should not
occur. And that of which it is impossible that it not happen happens
necessarily. Therefore all futures come about necessarily.
18615. Consequently nothing will be the case indeterminately or as a
result of chance, for that which depends on chance is not of necessity.
18617. Nor is it possible to say that neither the affirmation nor the
negation is true: that an event for instance neither will take place nor
will not take place. Firstly, if the affirmation is false the negation is
not true and if the negation is false it happens that the affirmation is
not true. Secondly, if it is true to say that a thing is white and black,
both qualities must belong to it. Should they belong to it until tomor-
row, they will belong to it until tomorrow. Suppose, by contrast, that
tomorrow the event neither will nor will not occur: nothing indetermi-
nate, such as a naval-battle for instance, would then take place. For
it would be necessary that the naval-battle neither take place nor not
take place.
18626. Such, among others, are the absurdities that arise if for every
affirmation and negation, either applying to universals as universals or
applying to singular things, it is necessary that one of the opposites be
true, the other false, and if there is nothing indeterminate in events but
that everything is and happens as a result of necessity. Consequently
there would no longer be any point in deliberation nor in taking any
pains, with the idea that if we accomplish a certain action a particular
result will follow, whereas if we do not accomplish it the result will not
follow.
18634. For there is nothing to prevent one man's saying ten thousand
years beforehand that something will be the case, another that it will
not, so that it necessarily will be that of one of the two cases it was true
to predict it then. Nor does it really matter whether people did make
the affirmation or not. For it is clear that reality is what it is even if
there was not this one to formulate the affirmation, this other one the
negation. For it is not because of the affirming or the denying that the
event will or will not occur, even (19a) had the announcement been ten
thousand years beforehand rather than at any other moment. Hence, if
it has been from all time that one of the contradictory propositions said
the truth, it was necessary that that should happen and every event
has always come about then in such a way as to happen necessarily.
For it is not possible that what anyone has truly said will be the case
should not happen; and as to what has happened, it was always true
to say that it will be.
19a6. But what if these consequences are impossible? For we see that
there is also an origin of what will be both in deliberation and in action
136 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
and, that the potentiality of being and of not being resides entirely in
things that do not always exist in act, things that, since they may be
or not be, the one as well as the other, may therefore also come to be
and not come to be. There are many manifest cases of this kind. This
garment, for example, may be cut in two and yet will not be cut in
two, but will wear out first. In the same way, it may not be cut, for
it could not wear out first were it not possible for it not to be cut in
two. This holds for all other events as well which are mentioned as
having the same kind of potentiality. Clearly then not everything is
or happens of necessity but some things come about indeterminately,
and for them neither the affirmation nor the negation is more true, the
one than the other, whereas for some other things one of the two is
true more frequently, though it does come about that the other should
happen and not it.
19"23. It is necessary that what is be, when it is, and that what is
not not be, when it is not. Yet it is not of necessity that everything
that is is or that everything that is not is not. For it is one matter for
everything that is to be necessarily, when it is, and another for it to be
necessarily simply. The same holds for everything that is not.
19"27. The same argument applies to contradiction as well. Everything
necessarily is or is not, will or will not be, without saying for all that,
if we divide, that one of the two is necessary.
19a30. Let me take an example. It is of necessity that tomorrow there
will or will not be a naval-battle. Yet it is neither that the naval-
battle takes place necessarily tomorrow nor that it does not. What is
necessary is for either to take place or not take place.
19a32. Consequently, since propositions are true in so far as they
conform to the things themselves, it is clear that whenever the things
behave indeterminately, and have a potentiality for contraries, the same
necessarily goes for the contradiction as well. This is the case for things
that are not always existent or that are not always non-existent. For
it is necessary then that one of the two contradictory propositions be
true or false, but it is not this one or that one but either, and when one
is more true than the other it is nonetheless not already true or false.
It is clear then that it is not necessary for every affirmation or negation
taken from among opposite propositions that the one be true, the other
false. For what is non-existent but has the potentiality of being or not
being does not behave after the fashion of what is existent, but in the
manner just explained.
OUTLINE OF THE PASSAGE: INTRODUCTION (18°28-34) / 137
account, as St. Thomas points out.3 The word designating the future
here is usually opposed to the future participial of the verb to be like
what is in contingent matter is opposed to that which is in necessary
or impossible matter.4 Assertions resulting from an essential predi-
cation, such as 'Socrates will be a man' or 'Socrates will not be an ass',
affirm or deny a property of a subject not in so far as it is a particu-
lar singular subject but after the manner of universals,5 as is required
by science. The opposition between these singular future assertions is
therefore treated as an opposition between a universal and its contra-
dictory, where the opposite truth-values obtain presently. The inquiry
will be limited then to deciding whether it is necessary in the case
of singular statements about the future in contingent matter that one
of the opposites be true and the other false, presently.6 These state-
ments may be of two different grammatical forms. There are singular
predicative statements such as 'this will be white', and pseudo-dated
existential statements, e.g. 'there will be a naval-battle tomorrow'. Not
every future singular predication or future singular existence statement
is accidental. Socrates will be essentially reasonable and the Heavens
will necessarily have a given motion. But a particular man will be
standing or sitting by accident, and he will exist by accident. It is to
this twofold domain that the inquiry is limited
3
St. Thomas, De Interpretation, Liber Primus, Lectio XIII, 1-3 (Oesterle, De
Interpretatione, 1962, 6, pp. 102-103).
4
The text says " im. 84 toiv xat? ' ixaercaxal jiEXXovctov" in singularibus et futuris.
Ammonius (quoted from William of Moerbecke's Latin translation, In De Int., 138-
139, Corpus Latinum Commentariorum in Aristotelem Graecum, t. I, pp. 264-265)
specifies that what is to be understood by 'future' here is what is thought of as of
contingent matter. He reminds us that in the De Generatione et Corruptione (II,
11, 337fc3) Aristotle opposes 'mellon' (or 'future') and 'esomenon' (future participle
of the verb ei^t). The latter signifies what will happen in any case, as when we
say 'winter or summer will come' or 'an eclipse will take place', whereas the former
involves a future that can happen or not, as 'I'll go for a walk' or 'I'll sail'.
5
St. Thomas, Peri Hermeneias. p. 43: "secundum universalium rationes".
6
As St. Thomas points out: "Aristotle has not mentioned contingent matter
until now because those things that take place contingently pertain exclusively to
singulars, whereas those that per se are inherent or are repugnant are attributed to
singulars according to the notions of their universals". "Aristotle is therefore wholly
concerned here with this question: whether in singular enunciations about the
future in contingent matter it is necessary that one of the opposites be determinately
true and the other determinately false" (Oesterle, op.cit., p. 104).
PRINCIPLE OF NON-CONTRADICTION AND LAW OP EXCLUDED MIDDLE / 139
12
Ammonius, op.cit., 1961, pp. 251-252.
13
ei yap aXr)i?E<; etnav on Xeuxov ?) o-u ou Xeuxov eativ, dvdyxT) rival XEUXOV TJ ou
XEUXOV (IS^g-lS6!).
From the grammatical point of view there is no decisive argument for choosing
between the division (Lp V L ~ p) and the composition L(pV ~ p) of necessity. (On
this point see Mrs. Frede, 1968, pp. 16-17). One might then reject our decision as
unfounded and follow Edghill (op. cit., 19a30-32) in taking the consequent of (C)
in the composite sense. The formula (F)
*L(p\J ~ p) D (Lp V L ~ p)
is not a thesis of modal logic.
(Notice Hughes and Cresswell, 1972, p. 38, who are mistaken in saying that the
antecedent is false and the consequent true). On the composed-sense interpretation,
the denial of (F) would suffice for avoiding Megarian necessitarianism. But that
would mean supposing that Aristotle had attributed to the Megarians the thesis
(F) whose modal invalidity is patent.
14
Ammonius presents this passage as follows. "Suppose two individuals feign di-
vining with respect to a particular event, attempting to predict of an invalid for
example, one that he will recover, the other that he won't. Clearly it is necessary to
hold one of the two cases true, the other false. If the one predicting recovery there-
fore says what is true, it is necessary that the invalid recover (for it has already been
postulated that the truth of discourse is followed by the occurrence of the thing in
any case); but if the one denying it says what is true, clearly it is impossible that
the invalid recover. That is why either it is necessary that the thing happen or it is
impossible that the event take place. Therefore contingency is excluded..." (1961,
pp. 267-268).
142 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
The first choice was that of Boethius who translated both terms by juturum esse.
But then the third proposition (line 32) would be but a repetition of the first (line
30). If we want to avoid such a shocking redundancy within just a two-line interval
we must take Minio Paluello's lesson to heart, recalling the passage at IS'lS. It is
thus that William of Moerbecke, in his Latin translation, opposed fore and fieri.
In Metaphysics, K, 8, 1065° 14-17, Aristotle discusses the thesis of universal de-
terminism based on the arguments of physics borrowed from the notion of causal
regression. All chance, all contingency will be impossible if one admits in the case
of an accidental being the regression of causes all the way back to a cause which
is itself necessary. But there are two ways of conceiving of that regression, accord-
ingly as it is applied to what is or to what is becoming. "Even if the cause were
supposed no longer what is (ov) but what is becoming (fiyvotJ.ei'oi'), the conse-
quences would be the same: everything would happen necessarily; for the eclipse
will take place tomorrow if such-and-such happened, and such-and-such happens if
some other thing happens in turn, and that other thing if a third thing happens".
We could in no way agree with Bonitz, vol. II, 1849, p. 464, and Tricot, II, p.
611, in taking Aristotle in the Metaphysics passage to be opposing present or past
being to future being. That was St. Thomas' interpretation who commented (p.
540, number 2282): "Someone might object to the argument saying that the cause
of future contingents is not already posited as the present and the past but is up
to now contingent like the future. For the result is that then everything happens
necessarily as was the case before [where we reasoned about what is, not about what
is becoming]. For if a certain cause is future it must be future in some determinate
time and determinately distinct from the actual present. Suppose it to be tomorrow.
If therefore the eclipse, which is itself the cause of certain accidental futures, is a
future that will take place tomorrow, and if all that happens happens through some
cause, it must be that that eclipse itself, as a future that will take place tomorrow,
happen if this will have happened, that is to say, as a result of something pre-
existing it..." St. Thomas thinks then that after having reasoned about present
or past causes Aristotle goes on to reason about causes to come, thus extending
to the future a causality that that extension does not preserve from determinism.
But it is clear that Aristotle considers the eclipse phenomenon to be determinate.
He is not concerned with the effects that will result from this phenomenon posited
as future. He is inquiring whether for this phenomenon, itself posited as a future
effect, there exists a causal chain, an already given regression, which is precisely
the case. Moreover, the word -yi-yvoiiEvov refers to the present just as the word 6v
does. The opposition of the two cases distinguished by Aristotle has nothing to do
with the temporal index of causality, but with the question of whether causality
applies to beings or to events (as Ross well notes in his Commentary, t. II, p. 322).
And if one wonders why Aristotle introduces that opposition when he defends the
possibility of contingency both in the context of causality and in that of logic, the
example of the deterministic eclipse will have to be taken into account for finding
the answer. He was clearly aware that any solution of the difficulties that would
limit itself to reserving contingency to events, even future ones, abandoning beings
148 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
anticipation or removal of causes, we shall take something away from the time there
is between the present moment and the future eclipse. Therefore, since this is a
finite time, and since everything finite is exhausted when something is taken away
from it, everything that will occur will be due to a cause existing now". This is the
reasoning used by Lukasiewicz (op.cit., 1967, p. 29). Its principle is the following:
"...every fact G occurring at instant t has its cause in some fact F occurring at
instant s earlier than t, and at every instant later than s and earlier than t there
occur facts which are both effects of fact F and causes of fact G" (ibid, p.28).
27
1065° 21-26. To the argument of necessity Aristotle replies that for contingent
beings there is a limit to the search for causes (Ross, 1924, vol. I, 363). This
is precisely the point of view defended by Lukasiewicz, which he does moreover
by recourse to the analysis of infinity and continuity. Causal chains have inferior
limits beyond which it is pure imagination to want to go back (op.cit., pp. 30-33).
For Aristotle the limit to the regression of causes is due to the fact that "some
condition will arise, if it does arise, not by a process but instantaneously" (Ross,
ibid.). The Stoics in particular blamed Aristotle for thus having introduced an
a.i/aiTio<; Kii/r)<ru; that would liken him to Epicurus. Mrs. Frede (pp. 115-117)
attributes this objection to a misunderstanding which was quite natural given the
obscurity of the terms Aristotle uses. The only difference between 'essential' and
'accidental' causality is that the former involves a unique and immanent teleology
whereas the latter involves several distinct teleologies. The accident is therefore
necessary once reinserted in its proper teleology (someone hid a treasure in the
field) and is properly accidental only when referred to an extraneous teleology (a
man plowing the field finds the treasure). Aristotle's doctrine is therefore not
unlike that of Cournot when he defines chance as the meeting of two independent
causal series. That is a classic and plausible interpretation. The Stoics in fact will
insist on the universal connection of the causal chain, the fatum. In this sense, the
limit in the regression of causes as conceived by Lukasiewicz would be Epicurean,
not Aristotelian, in spite of the mention made of instantaneous and ungenerated
conditions. The instantaneous character of the accidental event would be due to the
instantaneity of the meeting of the two independent series, each of which by itself
would be indefinitely generated. There is still, besides, a fundamental difference
between Aristotle and Cournot. For Cournot chance results from the meeting of
two series determined only by efficient causality, whereas for Aristotle it results
from the meeting of two teleological series.
THE DIFFERENCE BETWEEN ARISTOTLE AND DlODORUS / 151
nitely, throughout all this time it is necessary for that act to be,30 and
consequently the potentiality in question is reduced to an impossibil-
ity. Mustn't we conclude then with Diodorus that the possible is what
is or will be?31 The repeated oppositions concerning modality, acci-
dent, non-being, motion and even language,32 between the ontology
30
De Caelo, I, 28161, 281t15-25, 282 a 22-25, 283=24-29. See Cherniss, 1962, p. 416,
on these passages.
31
At De Caelo, I, 283°27, Aristotle writes that "the destructible is at some time
destroyed".
J. Hintikka, 1973, pp. 93-113, systematically assimilates the Aristotelian and the
Diodorean conceptions of modality. The Metaphysics passage (0, 4, 1047*3-14)
that he alleges in favor of his thesis enjoins us only not to consider as semantically
possible that which is in principle prevented from passing to actuality, whether by
an already given material or efficient cause or by a logical principle. It in no way
says that a possible will have to be, but simply that a possible that certainly will
not be is not an authentic possible.
32
According to Aristotle "potency and actuality extend beyond the cases that in-
volve a reference only to motion" (Metaphysics, Q, 1, 1046"l-2), and they therefore
go beyond the range of the corresponding notions according to Diodorus. Time can
fall within the scope of an Aristotelian modality. Moreover, infinity, the void, and
matter are eternally in potency and never pass to actuality. When Diodorus criti-
cizes the possibility of motion regarded as a passage (Fr. 128 in Doring, 1972, p. 37:
"...so something living dies neither in the time in which it lives nor in the time in
which it does not live, therefore it never dies") he is in fact denying generation.
He is to be counted therefore among those who, through awkwardness, imitate
the Ancients and according to whom "no being is generated or destroyed, because
whatever is generated must necessarily be so either from being or from non-being,
two equally impossible solutions; indeed being cannot be generated for it existed
already, and nothing can be generated from non-being for there must be something
to underlie it" (Physics, I, 8, 191Q27-32). But how does Aristotle reply to those
who simply deny motion, like the ancient Megarians, or to those like Diodorus who
reduce it to a cinematographic succession of discontinuous states? He invokes the
distinction between essence and accident (Physics, I, 8, 191612-17; Metaphysics, A,
10691'14-34). Accidental non-being, that is to say, privation, gives rise to genera-
tion. But all material beings, as such, suffer privation in virtue of their contrariety,
and the missing contrary has a sort of ghostly existence that Aristotle calls poten-
tiality and that, because of its incompleteness, produces an uneasiness calling for
change. As regards quality for example, potentiality is the ghostly presence of the
contrary (white) in something having a given quality (black). Of course when the
potentiality passes to actuality, if ever it does, it will be a development in present or
future time just as much for Aristotle as for Diodorus. But for Aristotle it is there
at the very core of the thing before becoming actuality. In the same way, motion
for Aristotle is the fulfillment of what is in potentiality in so far as it is in poten-
tiality. The act of motion, which would be expressed grammatically by the present
progressive tense (this is moving), could in no way therefore be confused with a
succession of immobilities, that is to say, with the positions occupied successively
by the mobile in the course of discontinuous time. The 'now', says Aristotle, is a
limit, not a part of time (Physics, IV, 10, 218a6) and motion cannot be reduced
to a correlation between the points occupied by the mobile and the 'nows' dividing
time.
THE DIFFERENCE BETWEEN ARISTOTLE AND DlODORUS / 153
not is, that which is is not, that which is not is not. Applying
(3) it is evident that the two extreme forms are true, whereas the
two middle ones are false (1011625-27).
(5) Therefore, to say that what is is, or that what is is not, is to say
what is true or what is false and there is no third (1011627-28).
To say that S is P is true if S is P and false if non-5 is P, and
to say that non-51 is P is true if non-5 is P and false if 5 is P,
and there is no third possibility.
(6) On the other hand, to say that the intermediate between 5 and
non-5 either is or is not P, is not to say what is true or what is
false (1011628-29).
(7) Therefore, the negation of the excluded middle, taken as disjunc-
tion of the subject (intermediate between what is and what is
not), is neither true nor false.
(8) To say that 5 is P is true if 5 is P, and false if 5 is not-P; and
to say that 5 is not-P is true if 5 is not-P, and false if 5 is P, in
virtue of (3)(1012a4-5).
(9) Therefore, to say that 5 is P or that 5 is not-P is to say what is
true or what is false, and there is no third possibility (1012a2-4).
(10) On the other hand, to say that 5 is an intermediate between P
and not-P is not to say what is true or what is false.
(11) Therefore, the negation of the excluded middle taken as disjunc-
tion of the predicate (to be intermediate between what is and
what is not) is neither true nor false.
(12) The negation of the excluded middle, therefore, whether taken
as disjunction of the subject (first argument) or as disjunction of
the predicate (third argument), is neither true nor false.
This argument uses the definition of truth through its most evident
instance (4) or through its consequences (5) and (8). It does not con-
tain it explicitly and we had to import it from another passage of the
Metaphysics (3). The text where Tarski thinks he sees the Aristotelian
definition of truth is in fact not one. Just what relation then does
the Aristotelian definition have to the Tarski criterion? According to
Aristotle, "truth and falsity, insofar as things are concerned, depend
on their combination or separation, so that he who thinks that what
is separated in fact is separated, or that what is combined in fact is
combined, thinks truly, while he who thinks what is-contrary to the
nature of the things is in error."45 But that definition differs from
Tarski's criterion, not only by the subject to which true and false are
45
Metaphysics, 0, 10, 1051t2-5.
160 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
some that will not verify p at ti, although the relative frequency of p
at t\ is different from 0.
Looked at in this way, the intuition developed in the De Inter-
pretatione is not logically contradictory. It does nevertheless require,
that, within the domain of the possible as regards reality and which
is therefore already different from the pure logically or mathematically
possible, a distinction be made between essence and accident. Only
the accident is subject to probability. To be already true or false, for
an accident, is to have already fallen within the domain of reality, that
is to say, to have a probability equal to 1 or to 0. Not to have a deter-
minate truth-value is to have a probability falling between those two
extremes. Then all the modal expressions used in Chapter IX trans-
late into probabilist expressions and the paradoxes pointed out by the
logicians vanish.
A theoretical difficulty, however, dismisses this interpretation, at
least if we use it in its direct and literal sense. When Aristotle doubts
that bivalence is universally valid, his doubt is cast on individual con-
tingent factors. The premises (A), (B) and (NH) of the Master ar-
gument are considered as true. What is questionable in (C) is not
the notion of a possible deprived of realization but the assertion of
its actual truth before the non-realization has occured. On the other
hand, the probabilistic interpretation requires that probabilities be in-
terpreted as frequencies, since any hint of subjective probabilities is
barred in Aristotle's dogmatic system. Then there are not individual
events, but frequencies that are able to verify or to falsify probabilistic
sentences.
However, introducing frequencies into the Master Argument's in-
terpretation seems to recommend Diodorus' rather than Aristotle's
solution.68 Moreover, when physicists today make reference to Aris-
totelian potentialities, they indeed allude to second order probabilities
depending on probability amplitudes, all concepts that lead us far away
from the letter of the Master Argument. 69
68
See later, p. 249.
69
See later, 10.5, pp. 259-263.
Epicurus and Intuitionism.
169
170 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
man, unable to admit that conclusion, was forced to say that it was
neither true nor false. After that, there is no need to refute him". 4
Leibniz' judgment leaves the difference between Aristotle and Epi-
curus in the dark. Aristotle, along with the dialecticians, explicitly
admits the truth of "either Hermarchus will be alive tomorrow or he
will not"; he even establishes its necessity. What he denies is the
distribution of truth—and therefore of necessity too—over each of the
disjunction's components. Epicurus rejects the truth, and therefore the
necessity, of the disjunction itself.5 What Epicurus denies is therefore
not the determinate character of the truth-values of the disjunction's
components, but the truth of that very disjunction. His criticism is
directed not to the principle of bivalence but to the principle of the
excluded middle. Naturally, a challenge to this latter is a challenge to
the former, for then the excluded middle is neither true nor false.6
Historians of philosophy have paid little attention to Epicurus' de-
nial of the principle of the excluded middle, either for lack of interest
in logical questions or for the suspicion they bore towards Ciceronian
testimony. Logicians have given two different interpretations of that
denial. The only one that can be retained since it is compatible with
the texts will lead to considering Epicurus' doctrine as a form of in-
tuitionism. We shall have therefore to examine the nature of the Epi-
curean criteria. From this examination we shall draw consequences
regarding certain hypotheses as well as the principle of the excluded
middle, which will permit us to assign the probable attitude of Epi-
cureanism towards the Master Argument. Thereafter we shall look at
other intuitionist representations of modality in Descartes and Kant.
4
Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, p. 211; Jalabert, p. 222. Leibniz based his remark on Ci-
cero's Academica reporting something Carneades said, perhaps ironically, in praise
of Epicurus (Bk. 2, XXX(97); Brehier, 1969, pp. 231-232).
5
See note 1.
6
On the contrary, denying the validity of the bivalence does not entail denying the
validity of the principle of the excluded middle, since the first denial only bears on
future contingents and does not question logical truths. Cicero makes mention of
Epicureans who, ashamed to have to declare that there are propositions that are
neither true nor false, "declare more impudently still that alternations of contra-
dictories are true, but that neither the one nor the other of their terms is true"
(De Fato, XVI. 37; Brehier, 1962, p. 487). This Ciceronian passage evokes that
of Quine on the fantastic character of Aristotle's position. The difficulty there is
in distinguishing logically between the principle of bivalence ('p' V '~ p') and the
principle of the excluded middle ('pV ~ p') explains how the Epicureans, natively
contemptuous of logic, could have taken over the Aristotelian position which per-
haps recommended itself to their eyes by virtue of the Stagirite's reputation as a
logician.
FIRST LOGICAL INTERPRETATION / 171
7
See above, 6.7, pp. 153-155.
8
Appendix to "Many-valued Systems of Propositional Logic" in Polish Logic,
edited by Storrs McCall, 1967, p. 64.
9
See above, p. 154, Note.
10
Lukasiewicz in Storrs McCall, 1967, pp. 40-66. With the three-values chosen as
1, j , 0 , the following must be verified: 1) ~ p = 1 — p, 2 ) p D < 7 = l i f p < g and
p D < 7 = l— p + 17 if p > g; see also Prior, 1962, pp. 240-250. Disjunction is defined:
p V q = (p D q) D q.
^Lukasiewicz, op.cit., p. 55. (Mp = £ > ^ ~ p 3 q).
The matrix is:
p ~p ~p D 9
1 0 1
1 1
2 2
0 1 0
whence MO = 0, M j = 1 and Ml = 1.
whence
LO S~ M ~ 0 =~ Ml =~ 1 = 0,
L\ = 0, LI = 1; M ~ 0 - 1, M ~ | = 1, M ~ 1 = 0;
~ MO = 1, ~ M| = 0, ~ Ml = 0.
The theorem of two-valued prepositional calculus (~ p D p) D p is falsified here for
172 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
It is seen that there is reciprocal implication between the last two expressions.
14
Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, pp. 211-212; Jalabert, pp. 222-223.
15
See above, 5.3, p. 113.
SECOND LOGICAL INTERPRETATION / 173
suffices to change the matrix for negation. It will take its arguments
from the three truth-values but, as is the case with the modal operators,
it will have as values only the true and the false: namely, the true for the
false and the false for the other two argument-values.16. Negation then
has the same matrix as did the impossible in the previous system.17
17
See note 11.
18
P '1 ~ (P • g) ~ PV ~ q ~ (~ pV ~ q)
1 1 1 0 0 1
1 1 1 0 0 1
2 2
1 0 0 1 1 0
i 1 1
rf
1
2
I
2
0
0
0
0
1
1
2
0 0 1 1 0
0 1 0 1 1 0
0
1 0 1 1 0
2
0 0 0 1 1 0
Consequently:
1— (p • q) =~ pV ~ ,
but not
* ~ (~pV~g) D (p-g).
19
The axiom in question is h (~ p 3 q) 3 {[(q D p) D q] 3 q} which is verified by
the three-truth-valued matrices.
20
Prior, 1969, p. 253.
174 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
35
Letter to Herodotus (47), Furley Translation, p. 127.
36
Furley. p. 127.
ARE THE EPICUREAN 'CRITERIA' COMPATIBLE WITH INTUITIONISM? / 179
difference between the truth it attributes its hypotheses and the ab-
sence of positive truth proper to hypotheses according to Popper. On
the one hand, any perceptive anticipation is in itself simply a problem
awaiting confirmation or falsification by direct and 'near' experience.
As such it is therefore without truth-value, since it is only experience
that will confer that upon it. An hypothesis, on the other hand, is ver-
ified or falsified by the phenomena following from it. There is no truth
or falsity apart from these procedures of confirmation. Moreover, the
verification of an hypothesis being limited to non-falsification is asym-
metric to falsification, and strictly speaking, given the invalidity of the
excluded middle, it is not absolutely positive nor does it in any way
authorize the conclusion to truth in the dogmatic sense of adequation
to the object.
The Epicurean theory of law gives a remarkable illustration of the
precepts of the Canonic. For in the procedures of verification and fal-
sification of laws, more complex than those operative on the level of
sensible opinion since they can deal only with the far-off consequences
of the laws, the method of anticipation has to do no longer with simu-
lacra passively received but with effects "whose cause we ourselves have
posited" ,39 There will be two distinct cases. Either confirmation will
be inherited from the past as with a body of laws left by the ancestors.
In this case the law brings its confirmation (hence, non-falsification)
with it and can fulfill its essential function of establishing security, just
as confirmation and non-falsification establish security in the order of
knowledge.40 Or again, there may be a proposed law of which the
confirmation or non-confirmation is 'in suspense'. Goldschmidt has
likened this to the Attic procedure of 'revision of laws' and the action
taken against the author of a detrimental law.41 In this last case the
law is like a hypothesis about the future. If there is often confirmation
and hence justification of a rule by its present conformity to the com-
mon interest, or non-confirmation and rejection of its legality because
its consequences do not conform to the interest of the community, the
immediate confirmation assimilating the juridical criterion to the cri-
terion of opinion about 'near' sensible things, it also happens that law
changes as a result of constitutional upheavals. What was just ceases
seems to lessen this first difference.) In the other direction, as Goldschmidt aptly
points out (1977, p. 217), Epicurean sensation differs from Humean impression
by the "fundamentum in re accorded it in Epicurean realism by the theory of
simulacra".
39
Goldschmidt, 1977, p. 217, pp. 221-222.
40
Id., ibid., pp. 218-219.
41
Id., ibid., pp. 196-197, 222-223 ; Goldschmidt, 1981, p. 87.
182 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
The connection with the denial of the principle of the excluded middle
becomes apparent once we consider the weight of representations or
motives in voluntary decision making. Both adversaries and partisans
of the freedom of indifference agree in denying that a motive can be
at once sufficient and insufficient for entailing decision. But it is not
for all that that the partisans of will admit that a motive is either
sufficient or insufficient for entailing decision. For it is the indifference
of freedom that bestows upon the motive the power of determination in
which the representation in itself, no matter what its weight, is lacking;
and that is why it isn't true that such a motive in itself either is or is
not sufficient for entailing decision.54
the future as one might wish. If we take into consideration the infinity
of time, we will not be able then, according to the Canonic, either to
affirm or deny the third premise. Moreover, the overall accommodation
made in Epicurean thought for the free play of what is the aleatory
would hardly allow discarding the third premise, whose truth is an
experiential given for free will. As for the second premise taken as a
thesis of pure modal logic, it is employed by Epicurus in the Letter to
Herodotus (57), for example. He starts from the thesis (5fjXov) "if there
is an infinity of parts, however small they may be, having whatever size
they do, the body composed of them will itself be infinite in size".60
The consequence is impossible: "how then could a size like that be
limited?" Therefore the antecedent is impossible as well.61 We have
reason to presume then that Epicurus escapes the Master Argument's
necessitarian consequence by indirectly challenging the dogmatic scope
of the third premise, and that to this end, he denied the validity of the
excluded middle, given the overall intuitionistic style and the exigencies
of his canonic.
When serious attention is payed to the fundamental innovations
Epicurus made in Democritean atomism, it is difficult to take Epicure-
anism as a kind of model of dogmatic empiricism as Kant does in the
Antithetic of the Critique of Pure Reason. The characteristics of the
Kantian antitheses: infinity of the world in space and time, inexistence
of a simple substance, denial of freedom and total subordination of the
world to the laws of nature, denial of the existence of an absolutely
necessary being are proper to Democritus, though it is difficult to rec-
oncile atomism with the second.62 Epicurus tempers all but the last
of these theses. To the eternity of the atoms he adds the theme of the
plurality of worlds that come to be and pass away and have therefore
beginning and end.63 If the soul is a perishable composite, it has, for a
certain time at least, a sort of formal permanence that fits in well with
its independence, parallel to that of the atoms. Finally, the swerve and
freedom break the chain of natural causes. In short, with the excep-
60 "|?or it is clear that the unlimited number of particles have a determinate size
and, whatever the size of these components, the magnitude [of the body] would be
unlimited as well." (Bollack, Bollack, Wisemann, 1971, p. 113).
61
There is no contradiction between the existence of an infinity of atoms and the
fact that an infinite number of atoms cannot enter into the makeup of a limited
body. For as the Letter to Herodotus (40) says, "the whole is unlimited in extension
and in the number of bodies"; and it goes on to add (45b), "the number of worlds,
some like and some unlike ours, is equally infinite".
62
See the difference Kant makes between monadism and atomism, Critique of Pure
Reason (B478/A460).
63
Lucretius, De Rerum Natura, II, 1047-1089.
INTUITIONIST CONCEPTIONS OF REALITY: DESCARTES AND KANT / 187
tion of the existence of the necessary being,64 one would put Epicurus
rather on the side of the Kantian theses than the antitheses, that is to
say, precisely on the side of practical interest as over and against the
speculative interest of reason.65
Nevertheless, while placing Platonism (the thesis) decidedly among
the dogmatic systems, Kant hesitates about Epicureanism. In an im-
portant note he says: "There is still doubt, however, whether Epicurus
ever propounded these principles as objective affirmations. If they were
perhaps nothing more than maxims for the speculative exercise of rea-
son, he would show a more genuinely philosophical spirit in that than
any other of the sages of antiquity. That, in the explanation of phe-
nomena we must proceed as if the field of inquiry was not bounded
by limits nor a beginning of the world; that the material of the world
must be accepted by experience, if we are to hope to learn from it; that
we must determine no production of events, if not by the immutable
laws of nature; and finally, that we should have no recourse to a cause
distinct from the world—those are even today very good, though little
followed, principles for extending speculative philosophy and for dis-
covering the principles of morals, without an appeal to outside help.
Nor for that reason can anyone desirous of ignoring these principles,
as long as mere speculation is involved, be accused of wanting to deny
them".66 Had Kant taken into account the Epicurean innovations in
the domain of physics with the swerve as well as in that of the canonic
with his rejection of the excluded middle and of morals with the as-
sertion of free will, he would no doubt have given more weight to this
remark and would not have hesitated to see in Epicureanism a sort of
precritical philosophy.
ated eternal truths. As for the third, it seems to result directly from
the existence of our freedom. Furthermore, these truths for our un-
derstanding are not unfounded once that, given the demonstration of
God's existence, His veracity is engaged in the clear and distinct idea
we have of necessity.78 Two sorts of possibility79 and necessity are
thus distinguished. Assuredly the distinction is reminiscent of Aristo-
tle and foreshadows Leibniz.80 But Leibniz found the creation of good
and evil,81 and of the eternal truths generally, so shocking that he sus-
pected there was some 'philosophical trick'82 behind the idea: what
was traditionally attributed to the divine understanding was made out
to be an object of the divine will, endowed with freedom. The two sorts
of modalities distinguished by Descartes are altogether different from
the dogmatic opposition between the order of essence and the order of
existence or between the principle of contradiction and the principle
of the best. Descartes writes to Mersenne83 that since some men "un-
derstand the truths of mathematics but not that of the existence of
God, it is not surprising if they fail to believe that the former depend
on the latter. On the other hand, they should judge that, since God
is a cause whose power surpasses the limits of human understanding,
and since the necessity of these truths does not outstrip our knowl-
edge, these truths must then be something lesser and subject to that
incomprehensible power".
So Descartes' absolute or uncreated necessities are not those of
essences, objects of the understanding, precisely because these essences
are created. They have to do only with God's truth, which lies beyond
our understanding because of His immensity that we cannot encom-
pass. As for created necessities, though on the same scale as our un-
derstanding, there is nonetheless something about them that shields
78
Gueroult, 1953, II, p. 34.
79
Gueroult, 1953, II, p. 39. "God in His omnipotence can do everything in
principle—even what we judge to be positively impossible—as long as it is not
repugnant to His very omnipotence, that is to say, as long as it is not a question
of absolute impossibility. But having instituted as eternal truth whatever our un-
derstanding perceives of as positive impossibilities, being immutable and truthful,
God will do nothing in the universe that we judge excluded by them. If He should
happen to do so however, He will call it to our attention in an indubitable way.
Moreover, He can always do what we fail to understand the possibility of, in the
case where we haven't a sufficient reason to judge it necessarily as positively impos-
sible; there is nothing, on the other hand, that could make Him unable to realize
whatever our understanding conceives of as possible".
80
Gueroult, 1953, II, p. 39.
81
Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, p. 219; Jalabert, p. 230.
82
Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, p. 227; Jalabert, p. 239.
83
Letter of May 6; Correspondence, A.T., I, p. 150.
194 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
91
Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, p. 130; Jalabert, p. 137.
92
Descartes, Principes, Part I, art. 39.
93
Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, L.W. Beck, 1976, p. 200.
INTUITIONIST CONCEPTIONS OF REALITY: DESCARTES AND KANT / 197
when once wound up also carries out its motions of itself .98 Hence
the dogmatic illusion results in necessitarianism. But necessitarianism
runs against our moral conscience. "A man may dissemble as much as
he will in order to paint his unlawful behavior, which he remembers, as
an unintentional error, as mere oversight, which can never be entirely
avoided, and consequently as something to which he was carried along
by the stream of natural necessity, and in this way to make himself
out as innocent. But he finds that the advocate who speaks in his be-
half cannot silence the accuser in him when he is conscious that at the
time when he committed the wrong he was in his senses, i.e., he was in
possession of his freedom".99 What is revealed through the paradoxi-
cal sentiment of repentance is not the actual psychological presence of
freedom but its obligatory postulated presence at the base of our past
responsibility taken as the ratio essendi of the imputation of our acts
to a moral agent.
The dogmatic illusion then is really a moral fault, or, at best, an in-
tellectual habit got for the purpose of casting the veil of necessity over
our moral faults. To deliver us from this illusion, it is not necessary
for intuitionism to appeal directly to the experience of freedom, but it
must simply indicate the phenomenon of that freedom, self-blame,100
which alone is the object of experience in the matter. But Kant's tran-
scendental theory of freedom has a universal bearing for intuitionism
precisely because, according to it, all our intellectual errors are faults
in that reflection leads us to feel them as such. For Epicurus' impa-
tience of opinion and Descartes' prejudice and precipitation of judg-
ment confront us with facts that accuse us. Even if there is nothing
positive about error, formally it still bears witness of our imperfection
and poses a problem for us that postulates our freedom by implication.
Thus the firm resolve to take only experience into account appeals to a
faculty going beyond that experience, and it has been rightly said that
it was Epicurus who introduced the transcendental concept of freedom
into philosophy. And this very concept is the keystone of intuitionism.
Psychology and anthropology give rise to it, though it does not fall
within their jurisdiction. It is characteristic of that paradoxical exi-
gency imposed by our finite reason. It is Fichte who best described it
in saying: "To be free is nothing, to become free, everything".101
This anthropological exigency may be seen as intuitionism's ulti-
mate requisite. That is how Epicurus took it in placing the gods in
98
Critique of Practical Reason, op.cit., p. 203.
"Ibid., p. 204.
loo
lbid., p .204.
101
Quoted by Gueroult, 1930, I, p. 269.
INTUITIONIST CONCEPTIONS OF REALITY: DESCARTES AND KANT / 199
by the cause of error, i.e., the excessive broadness of opinion over sen-
sation. It will be said for example that that excess allows the living
to foresee dangers and therefore aids in conserving life. But it is seen
that theodicy engages in speculation going beyond sensations. It is
this then that represents the extreme limit of intuitionism, going fur-
ther even than the adventure through which credence was granted to
atomism.
Descartes reaches the same limit in connection with his own system
when he tries to clear God of the responsibility for error. "Preoccupied
with integrating the human experience (formal error, feeling) into the
total system of philosophy, and affective psychology and ethics into the
system of the sciences, he reintroduced into the created world, through
the principle of the best, finality, theodicy, and consequently theology,
although it was natural theology... Divine freedom's infinitude can no
longer be conceived of then as the absoluteness of a decisive power, of a
power of arbitrary pronouncement of yes and no, for God can not sub-
scribe to nothingness: He cannot deny being. There is an ascendancy
therefore, in the species, of the idea of the perfect or of the infinite
essence over pure freedom. Whether this primacy comes from the di-
vine will itself, arising by virtue of its nature as unlimited omnipotence,
or is imposed from without under the constraint of a dominant under-
standing, as for Malebranche or Leibniz, makes certainly more than
just a nuance of difference. But on either hypothesis the fact of that
primacy remains indubitable".106
That balance of freedom and perfection in God dominates the subtle
and complicated interplay of psychology and metaphysics throughout
the Cartesian theodicy.107 On the one hand, the incomprehensibility of
the divine decrees would have as limit the imperfection of the work and
therefore the formal reality of error, which psychology requires. On the
other hand, Divine Perfection demands that that error be an absence
of being and that the formal imperfection it introduces in nature cancel
out as an ingredient of a perfect whole subject to the principle of the
best.108 But if in the final analysis divine freedom submits, so to
speak, to its positive perfection like the incomprehensibility of creation
submits to the assent we owe to the visible finality of that creation in
virtue of the divine veracity, this double subordination is rather induced
from signs than produced by the pseudo-necessity of the principle of
the best. It is an object of rational faith rather than one of reason.
106
Gueroult, 1953, II, p. 215-6.
107
Gueroult, 1953, I, p. 300 sq.
los
lbid.,pp. 306-18.
INTUITIONIST CONCEPTIONS OF REALITY: DESCARTES AND KANT / 201
written to the same princess that "philosophy alone suffices for knowing
that the least thought could not enter the mind of a man, that God
should not will and should not have willed there from all eternity".112
Leibniz113 thought that even Calvin had said nothing harder than this
last assertion of God's "total" causality over our least thoughts and he
excuses Descartes only if divine will is taken in a "permissive" and not
in an absolute sense, as Descartes however explicitly maintains.
The conflict comes to a head when Leibniz corrects Descartes' ex-
ample in order to make it acceptable. He says that it would be nec-
essary "to invent a reason that obliged the prince to arrange or allow
that the two enemies should meet".114 That reason is the principle of
the best. On the contrary, for Descartes, from the fact that God did
something it follows that it was the best. In another letter to Elisabeth
he advances considerations on our freedom and on divine providence115
that are contrary by our lights but both equally well founded, and goes
on to conclude that that freedom "is not incompatible with a depen-
dency of another nature, according to which all things are subject to
God". That other nature is a truth of simple consequence following
upon the proof of the existence of God, hence altogether indirect and
already resemblant of a rational postulate, of an object of faith.
Just as the usefulness of survival value of a mutation has only an ex
post facto justification, the finality and insertion of human freedom in
the plans of providence has but an indirect and, as it were, retrospective
rationale. As Descartes admits, this is because the truths proportionate
to our cognitive faculty in so far as it moves spontaneously and of itself
in the bosom of truth are of a different nature from those met with
by that same faculty when it has to account for error and for the
remedies error calls for. Just what is this difference of nature? It is
to Kant's glory to have discerned it and made it the touchstone of his
philosophical system.
Taking up a remark of Leibniz' on the difficulties added to the ques-
tion of freedom by the physical concurrence of God and creatures with
the will,116 Kant posits the ideality of time as a necessary condition
for the solution of the problem. For if divine action were accomplished
under the condition of time, necessity would be inescapable. "There-
fore, if the ideality of time and space is not assumed, only Spinozism
112
Letter of Oct. 6, 1645, Correspondence, A.T., IV, p. 314.
113
Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, p. 207; Jalabert, p. 218.
115
Letter of Nov. 3, 1645, Correspondence, A.T., IV. p. 333.
116
Leibniz, Gerhardt, VI, p. 122; Jalabert, p. 128; Kant, Critique of Practical
Reason, p. 206.
204 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
human reason, without such validity proving that this distinction lies
in the things themselves".121
In taking the fact of error to be the result of divergence among the
faculties, intuitionism finds the remedy in critically assigning these fac-
ulties a domain of validity. But what error shows is that the possibility
of transgressing the bounds set is inevitably tied to our human nature.
Opinion outstrips sensation, understanding and judgment encroach on
one another's domain, reason inexorably disengages itself from the lim-
its of intuition. But the fact is that these proscribed excesses are not of
uniquely negative bearing. A classically demonstrated theorem poses
a problem for mathematicians just as selective value and finality do
for the intuitionist philosopher. Subordinations arise that, seen from
the outside, seem to run counter to the method. Finality, for example,
imposes itself as a principle of natural science.122 But insurmount-
able difficulties would arise if it were of the same order as mechanical
causality whose sway extends over the phenomena. For teleology is
inexplicable. Hence, in so far as applied to objects, it does not af-
ford a principle of truly determinant judgment, but only one of merely
reflective judgment, even though this last be universal.123
Kant tells us that the same can be said of the connection between
freedom, presenting us with the law as an imperative, and actual ac-
tion. If our will were holy there would be no such distinction. Thus
the requisite subordination of mechanism to finality and of particular
to universal,124 does not express a dogmatic subordination in the ob-
jects, of which we could form a determinant conception. It expresses
only a regulative principle, necessarily valid for our human faculty of
judgment. Far from governing creation like the Leibnizian principle of
the best, it is a subjective principle depending on the contingent nature
of our faculty of knowledge. The illusion common to Diodorus and his
dogmatic adversaries, and probably to all of modern modal logic, lies in
the confusion that attributes a constitutive use to principles that have
no meaning once divorced from cognizing activity and whose legitimate
and simply regulative use is to police that cognizance from the inside
without presuming to legislate with respect to things in themselves.
121
Ibid., pp. 570-1.
122
Ibid., §68.
123
Ibid., §74.
124
Ibid., §76.
8
207
208 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
room for individual spontaneity in each of these series and fate does
not wrong freedom".1 Epicurus denied both propositions asserted by
Chrysippus. Carneades took a more balanced stance, typical of his phi-
losophy in general, accepting the first of these propositions but limiting
his acceptance of the second.
Such an interpretation fails to draw out all that is in the texts. The
dispute between Chrysippus and Epicurus becomes a dispute over the
materiality of the two principles of causality and the excluded middle,2
as if these two principles were admitted as independent. But that is
not the case. For here is Chrysippus' reasoning: "If uncaused motion
exists, it will not be the case that every proposition (termed by the
logicians an axioma) is either true or false, for a thing not possessing
efficient causes will be neither true nor false; but every proposition is
either true or false; therefore uncaused motion does not exist. If this
is so, all things that take place take place by precedent causes; if this
is so, all take place by fate; it therefore follows that all things that
take place take place by fate" .3 The polysyllogism with contraposition
takes as its starting point the following Epicurean principle:
If there is motion without cause (Pi), there are exceptions to the
principle of the excluded middle (P?),
and immediately furnishes an application of the principle: the proposi-
tion saying that 'there will be a certain swerve' is neither true nor false.
The principle is true and the consequent P2 false. In order to criticize
his two adversaries then, Carneades begins by specifying the hypothet-
ical principle they both take to be true. If there is opposition between
Chrysippus and Epicurus, it is because the latter, accepting the an-
tecedent as true (the existence of motion without cause), is obliged
to admit the consequent (invalidity of the excluded middle), whereas
Chrysippus, admitting the falsity of the consequent (not-P 2 ), the ex-
cluded middle being always true, is obliged to reject the antecedent,
the invalidity of the principle of causality, (not-PI). As the univer-
sal principle of causality (not-PI) entails the universal precedence of
causes (Ps), and that precedence in turn entails fate (Pi), the truth of
1
Robin. 1944, p.127.
2
In spite of the fact that the principle is here expressed in the meta-language, it
will be spoken of throughout the paragraph as the principle of the excluded middle
and not as that of bivalence. For in the debate before us none of the speakers
establishes a difference between those two principles and the discussion at no point
touches on Aristotle's solution.
3
Cicero, De Fato, X.20-21, trans, by H. Rackham in the Loeb Classical Library,
1942, pp. 216-217.
PRINCIPLE OF THE EXCLUDED MIDDLE AND PRINCIPLE OF CAUSALITY / 209
5
~ Pi D P3.
6
De Fato, XI. 24 "...voluntary motion possesses the intrinsic property of being in
our power and of obeying us, and its obedience is not uncaused, for its nature is
itself the cause of this" (XI.25, ibid., pp. 220-221).
7
XI.26, ibid., pp. 220-222. Translation altered.
8
XII.27.
9
XII.28, ibid., pp. 222-223.
210 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
age as he intends? How can he have it"?17 All that his knowledge
can attain is the probability of a safe passage given what he believes
he presently perceives, and that probability is enough for determin-
ing action; but there is a gulf between it and truth. The outcome of
Carneades' skeptical pragmatism is the probable, as it would have been
for Aristotelian dogmatism had it classed all contingent events in a sin-
gle category. But it is because there are propositions about the future
that are neither true not false that the probable exists for Aristotle,
while for Carneades the probable results from the gulf there is between
the self-containment of truth and the act of our apprehension.
If a theory of degrees of belief were to be developed for Carneades
as one of degrees of determination has been for Aristotle, it might be
said that the Carneadean probable opens the way to 'subjective' prob-
ability while Aristotelian contingency suggests 'objective' probability.
We shall refrain from speculating about these developments however,
especially since for Carneades, for whom a statement's truth implies
no actual determination of the thing, the accent put on the subject in
no way reduces the probable to ignorance of what is determinate.
first two parts of the argument, the Orator shows that the Diodorean
distinctions, from Diodorus' point of view, not only fail to avoid but
even establish necessitarianism. The last part of the argument shows
that he knew of one philosophy that maintained that that Diodorean
necessity was only apparent or formal and that was the philosophy of
Carneades. The mainstay of the argument's first part is the consid-
eration of the change of truth-value. "... it is no more possible for
things that will be to alter than it is for things that have happened;
but...whereas in the things that have happened this immutability is
manifest, in some things that are going to happen, because there im-
mutability is not manifest, it does not appear to be there at all, and
consequently, while 'This man will die of this disease' is true in the
case of a man suffering from a deadly disease, if this same is said truly
in the case of a man in whom so violent an attack of the disease is not
manifest, none the less it will happen. It follows that no change from
true to false can occur even in the case of the future. For 'Scipio will
die' has such validity that although it is said of the future it cannot
be converted into a falsehood, for it is said about a human being, who
must inevitably die".18
It is clear that Cicero is here speaking of propositions, that is to
say of the equivalence classes of all possible statements about a certain
presently future event. Diodorus, on the contrary, limited himself to
statements or to propositions as partial equivalence classes modulo a
given lapse of time, formulated or not, according to the state of our
knowledge. Cicero maintains that in going from the latter to the former
necessitarianism in forma cannot be avoided.
But let us leave grammar and come back to reality. In other words,
let us eliminate these purely exterior variations of truth-value, in taking
the equivalence class of statements modulo a determinate date. Accord-
ing to Diodorus a proposition is possible if it is true or will be true. In
this case its truth retrogrades; it is necessary as soon as one takes for
granted, with Diodorus, the Aristotelian principle of correspondence.
For Cicero then, Diodorus does not escape the necessitarianism
for which the Megarians were reproached. He would only avoid it in
sticking to a consideration of grammatical forms alone and in refusing
to consider the corresponding propositions.
Some have compared Diodorus to Quine. Just as Quine is skep-
tical of the contemporary modal logics, so was Diodorus skeptical of
the Aristotelian modal theory "but offered nevertheless some 'harm-
l8
De Fato, DC.17; Rackham, 1942, pp. 212-213. [I have slightly revised the Rack-
ham translation of this passage. Translator's note.]
214 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
position. "Hence if, while it is consistent for the Stoics, who say that
all things happen by fate, to accept oracles of this sort and all other
things connected with divination, yet the same position cannot be held
by those who say that the things which are going to happen in the
future have been true from all eternity, observe that their case is not
the same as that of the Stoics".22 The partisans of Carneades admit
the eternal truth of propositions about future contingents. It would
seem then—and this impression is reinforced by the entire context of
the discussion between Carneades and the Stoics—that these partisans
go along with the Stoics in admitting the eternal truth of a possible that
will not be realized, but without running the risk of necessitarianism for
all that. What is dangerous about the third premise on the dogmatic
interpretation is that the truth of the negation entails the act of the
contrary event. Once that act is suspended, necessity vanishes.
We must now turn to the logical consequence of Carneades' skepti-
cism. The late scholastic philosopher, Buridan, will provide the occa-
sion for doing so.
40
Academica, II, XXXIII (105); Brehier, 1962, pp. 235-236.
222 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
45
Academica, II, XXVI (84); Brehier, 1962, p. 225.
46
Ibid., XXIV (77); Brehier, 1962, p. 222.
"Ibid., XXV (79); Brehier, 1962, p. 223.
48
/&«*., XXXI (99); Brehier, 1962, p. 232. As Hamelin remarks (1978, p. 30),
in agreement with Aristotle on the definition of truth, "Carneades denatures the
notions of truth and falsity".
9
225
226 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
in my will a greater and mightier bond than those with which ye were
bound at the time of your birth" .2
Plato, as will Aristotle, posits a sort of permanence of the modal
status of beings. A composite being is by nature perishable and will
therefore always remain so. From the fact that it was engendered it
always will be able to perish. Yet in the case at hand that force of
destruction will never be realized because the will of the demiurge will
constantly keep it in abeyance. So far from excluding the capacity of
not existing at the same moment, as conformity to the principle of
conditional necessity would require, existence is compatible with that
capacity, and in virtue of divine will it will remain so for the rest of
time. The demiurge's address to the gods implies therefore, on the part
of Plato, a revocation of the principle of conditional necessity3 that was
nearly unanimously espoused by the Ancients. This stems, for Plato,
from the gap there is between the ideas and the sensible world. In so
far as it is sensible, necessity characterizes the strictures of mechanism
and materiality and therefore expresses only the nature of the image.4
It would be foolish to conclude from the strictures on the image the
existence of corresponding strictures regarding the ideas.
The Platonic refusal of conditional necessity is therefore indepen-
dent of the particular way in which the creation of the world is inter-
2
Timaeus, 40E-41C; Jowett trans, in Hamilton, 1963, p. 1170.
3
In the Platonic questions, VIII, 1007 (Plutarch's Moralia, XIII, Part I, Cherniss,
1976, I, p. 89), Plutarch writes in the same vein "... as they came into being together
[the universe and time], together they will also be dissolved again if any dissolution
overtake them, for what is subject to generation cannot (be) apart from time just
as what is intelligible cannot apart from eternity either if the latter is always to
remain fixed and the former never to be dissolved in its process of becoming". Since
they were born together the universe and time will perish together. That is to say,
they conserve the capacity of decaying together, even if (by divine will) they are
maintained perpetually in being. The reasoning here differs from the demiurge's
address above only in that here is posited the compatibility of a constant association
of being with a no less constant association of the corresponding contrary capacity.
As Cherniss has pointed out to me, the principle of the conservation of modal status
is implied in a passage of the Laws (818 A7-E2; and Cherniss, 1962, pp. 608-9)
where Plato distinguishes two sorts of necessity: a divine necessity to which the
gods are subject and which has to do with the objects of arithmetic, geometry
and astronomy, and a human necessity having to do with what exists sensibly. A
consequence of this distinction is the invalidation of conditional necessity, for the
demiurge is not subject to "human" necessity.
4
"The nature of this world is blended of intelligence and necessity. What is good
in it comes from god, what is evil from the primordial nature as Plato says for
referring to matter as a simple substance as yet unadorned by god." (Plotinus,
First Ennead, VIII, 7, 4-7). Cf. also Plato, Timaeus, 48A.
PLATONISM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF CONDITIONAL NECESSITY / 227
preted, which from what Atticus5 says was already a matter of dispute
among the ancients. If, with Atticus himself, the literal interpreta-
tion is adopted,6 the productive power of the demiurge will be placed
above the obstacles materiality set up against it. If, with the Platonic
Statesman, creation is taken in a symbolic sense with the accent put
on an indefinite succession of such "creations",7 the deity will be seen
as indefinitely thwarting the capacity of disorder and destruction that
haunts the images by their very nature. Such a capacity, as will be
pointed out by Aristotle in the De Caelo (281615-25), will have to be
posited at the same time as the contrary actuality, for the ascendancy
of form applies to an infinite time.
That such really was the doctrine of the Platonists finds verification
in a passage of the City of God in which St. Augustine, criticizing
them, shows that starting from their principles one cannot refuse the
5
A second-century A.D. Platonist engaged in the general polemic of the day with
the Aristotelians. Cf. Taylor, 1969, p. 443.
6
On the opposition between Plato and Aristotle, fr. 4 (1977, pp. 50-4 (801a-
804b)).
7
"Then, when a long time had passed, it began to rest from this tumult and
confusion; convulsion gave place to calm, and the world went on its way, settling
down into its normal course with superintendence and sovereignty over itself and all
it contained, mindful to the best of its power of the lessons of its maker and father.
Now it discharged this task at first with much exactness, but more carelessly as time
went on, the reason of this being the corporeal strain inwrought in the primal fabric
of its structure, which, before it was brought to the order we see today, was steeped
in all manner of lawlessness. From its fashioner, indeed, the world has received only
good; all the violence and wrong it has within it or breeds in its creatures, it has as
a relic of that its ancient state. So while the captain was still there to help in rearing
the creatures within it, it brought forth little that was amiss and much that was
good; when parted from him, in the years just after the severance, it still orders all
things excellently well, but in process of time, as forgetfulness comes over it, the old
discord prevails ever more and more till, in the fullness of the days, the world runs
wild, producing little that is good with a great admixture of the contrary, and so
comes in peril of perishing with all its contents. So there comes the moment when
God, who first made an ordered world of it, beholds it in these straits; concerned
that it shall not be broken by the buffetings of the storms of disorder, and so founder
in the boundless ocean of unlikeness, he takes his place again at the tiller, turns
back all that had run to disease and dissolution in the age just past while the world
was left to its own devices, restores its order once more, and makes it safe against
death or senescence." (The Statesman, 273 A-C, trans. Taylor). Mugler, 1960,
p. 170 sq., draws a radical line of distinction between the demiurge's redressment
of the world in The Statesman symbolizing only "the structural information of the
world and the regulative power it has over the diffuse forces of necessity" and the
diachronic intervention of the World-soul of the Timaeus and panpsychism of the
Laws. But then he is obliged to construe the expressions in The Statesman making
mention of the world's memory of the demiurge's instructions, for instance, as a
simple anthropomorphism (p. 192), whereas it may have been for Plato the sign of
the presence of a soul.
228 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
the whole of existence and all the revolutions of the world within it" ,16
Suppose then that the Soul ceases to act and to exercise its power and
withdraws within itself and in eternity. Succession, time, all images
would disappear at once.17 Such is the secondary being of images, of
time, and therefore of sensible movement and of all that partakes of
quantity. There is a possible world in which the Soul would return
into its life of pure contemplation and where that secondary being
would disappear. It must therefore not be necessary. Even the sensible
things that will last forever, dependent as they are on the activity of the
Soul, are without necessity in spite of their perenniality.18 There is no
absolute sensible necessity. A fortiori there is no conditional sensible
necessity.
At the same moment t the movent has the property expressed by 'pt'- What leads
to the contradiction pointed out by Ross is conditional necessity, since if the formula
for the moved at t could be
Mtpt • ~ pt ,
there would be no need to appeal to a movent other than itself for it to produce
the action. Aristotle's argument in Physics VIII, 5 is a dilemma (Cherniss, 1962,
pp. 390-1, n.210). The continuity and therefore the divisibility of motion renders
a self-mover impossible. Either the self-mover moves itself as a whole, but then
it would both undergo and cause the same motion at the same time, and motion
would no longer be an incomplete actuality. Or self-motion would result from a
partial motion which would be reciprocal (with A moving B and B moving A, in
effect reproducing the previous confusion of action and passion) or ordered. If self-
motion is partial and ordered, a part A will move a part B without being moved
by it. But if A moves itself in moving B the same difficulty will arise again: A
would undergo the motion it causes. Therefore A must move B while remaining
immobile itself. The mainstay of the argument is the essential separation of movent
and moved, in other words, conditional necessity. For the Thomistic doctrine on
this point see Effler, 1965, pp. 180-91.
24
Saint Thomas, Summa Theologiae, Part I, quest. 80, art. 2; Gilson, 1952, p. 583.
25
De Anima, 408a34-(>30; Cherniss, 1962, p. 402 sq.
26
I'm following Cherniss quite literally here, ibid., p. 169.
THE CONSEQUENCES OF ABANDONING THE PRINCIPLES / 233
united to the intellective soul which is its 'essential form'. But there
is such a gulf between them that an 'organic bodily form' seems nec-
essary as the ultimate disposition of matter to receive the intellect.35
The multiplication of forms will result from the requisite specification
of every potentiality become positive. But the hierarchy ordering that
matter and those forms increases, rather than diminishes the distance
between them. As strong as the bond between them is, there is nothing
that could prevent God from creating matter without form. For Plato
the bonds established by the demiurge's creation took precedence over
the constraints of the sensible world. Divine power, for Scotus, takes
precedence over the bonds formed by creation. How could conditional
necessity subsist in the face of that power?
In connecting sensible motion with a mobile, Aristotle is drawing
the consequence of his modal definition of motion as imperfect act,
identical with the process of realizing form in matter. But let us, with
Plato, consider the motion of things as secondary. A thing can be
moved by other things that move, but the ultimate cause of its motion
cannot exist in any other thing.36 We must posit its model in the idea
of motion and its realization in the life of the soul. But if motion cannot
be reduced to any other given than motion itself, there is no longer a
reason for its modal analysis in terms of imperfect actuality. On the one
hand, the idea of motion is pure actuality in virtue of its immateriality.
On the other hand, the soul, which takes its model from that idea
and produces the spiritual motion and secondarily the physical one, is
free from all potentiality for it is not a subject susceptible of contrary
determinations: it is the self-mover in act. Only physical motion then
falls under the Aristotelian analysis. It alone requires the distinction
between the mover and the moved.37
Scotus has similar thoughts on the matter. He says that it seems
impossible for an angel to move if the motor and mobile are always dif-
ferent and if what is in act cannot be in potency. But the impossibility
is only an apparent one stemming from the application to spiritual
things of what is only valid for material things in general.38 We must
Par., L IV, d.ll, q.3, n.22, Vives, XXIV, pp. 125-6.
36
Cherniss, 1962, p. 453.
37
Ibid., p. 441, p. 453.
38
Op. Ox., L II, d.2, q.10, n.l, Vives, XI, p. 523; ibid., d.25, q.l, n.12, Vives, XIII,
pp. 207-8. "When it is said that mover and moved must necessarily be distinct by
their subject, what is said is true only of corporeal things: I think that even here
moreover it is not necessarily true. But I say that it is simply false for spiritual
things. Otherwise God could not create a single Angel, bare in its nature, and
which, left to its nature, could comprehend its essence, thereby being a same mover
and moved indistinctly as to the subject."
238 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
potency and subject in act are only equivocally the same, as is required
by the imputability of action.
The objection against the existence of a self-mover is therefore
removed.42 "Soul, however, as self-motion in which there is no dis-
tinction of substrate and activity can have no potency of motion in
this Aristotelian sense which involves the possibility of contrary deter-
minations but as a positive process must have a pattern in reality of
which it is the manifestation" ,43 The life of the soul is not the attribute
of a substance. We must not say that soul moves, but rather that it is
self-mover or self-motion.
Once the principle of omne agens est praesens passo is given up,
the way is clear for the freedom of the human will.44 The proposition
assigning an external cause to every volition had been condemned45
in 1277. The faith posits that "nothing other than the will is total
cause of the will in the will" ,46 The will continues therefore to exist
"Therefore it is absurd that a very noble form, such as the intellective soul, should
not have the active as well as the receptive potentialities of its accidental perfection.
And because in such forms there cannot be given an active and passive potency
distinct from the subject, as they are not organic potencies, they are therefore not
distinct by the subject and will therefore be united here without distinction as to
the subject, without however being deprived of formal distinction." (Ibid., n.13,
Vives XIII, p. 208).
42
Duns Scotus, ibid., n.14, pp. 208-9 "Likewise, it has been shown in book four
that a separated soul has the power of moving itself to another place, for to move
thus is suited to a very imperfect being, and what are distinct perfections in an
inferior nature must be unified in a more perfect nature to which the inferior one
is ordered."
43
Cherniss, 1962, pp. 441-442.
44
Op. Ox., L II, d.25, q.l, n.2, Vives XIII, pp. 197-198.
45
Gilson, 1952, pp. 377-379.
46
Op. Ox., L.II, d.25, q.l, n.22, Vives XIII, p. 221. The condemnation was of
"the proposition that the soul wills nothing unless it is moved by something else.
Whence it follows that it is false that the soul moves itself. This is wrong if we
understand moved by something else, namely the desirable or the object, to mean
that the desirable or the object is the entire reason for the movement of the will."
That the soul is necessarily moved by something else was the position of Scotus'
adversary, Godfrey of Fontaines. From this argument he distinguishes that of "an-
other Doctor" who is St. Thomas: "As concerns the proof that it is the same thing
to say that mover and moved are indistinct as to subject as to say that there is
a self-mover, it seems that another Doctor would concede that the will is moved
by an object in so far as apprehended by the intellect, and yet that the object as
apprehended by the intellect or the intellect showing said object are not distinct
from the will as to subject; and yet he would not concede that mover and moved
here are one and the same thing." Scotus refutes both opinions. "As for me, I say
not only that they are indistinct as to subject, but that one and the same thing
simply can be mover and moved." (Op. Ox., L.II, d.25, q.l, n.12, Vives XIII, p. 208;
see above Chapter 4.2, note 30, p. 81).
240 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
Epilogue
243
244 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
contingent, from posing the same problem for analysis that freedom
does, and finally, that the naturally contingent, without pretending to
impose its own particular features on freedom, may suggest analogical
ways of rendering this latter possible.
The second source of complication, extraneous to the Master Ar-
gument, is one of circumstance. The majority of philosophers today,
either because of their lack of familiarity with the sciences or because
they deny that there is any separation between scientific and ordi-
nary languages, postulate that it is sufficient to correctly analyze the
common language with which they express themselves and which has
incorporated wisdom and truth in order to dissipate the confusions, the
paradoxes, the pseudo problems and imagined solutions transmitted by
the history of philosophy.
Aristotle, already, led into the real examination of a question by
a preliminary linguistic or dialectical examination. Let us follow his
lead.
possible in the context of physics about which the Ancients reason? The
analysis of the Chrysippean modalities has shown what it was. The ab-
sence of internal contradiction is not generally sufficient for recognizing
a possible; there must be conditions of reality as well, conditions about
which the philosophers are not in agreement but which require, in any
case, that the realization of the possible should not be prevented by
obvious external hindrances. As Aristotle puts it, "a thing is capable
of doing something if there will be nothing impossible in its having the
actuality of that of which it is said to have the capacity".2 As the
condition has to do with a being that, not walking, has the capacity
of walking, or that, walking, has the capacity of not walking, the most
general impossibility we can imagine is that of a possible that would
come to be contracted and realized at the very instant at which the
contradictory state of affairs would be the case.
Let us then follow the suggestions of ordinary language. Let us
forget the requirements of reality that the Ancients attached to the
notion of the possible. Let us consider now a possible at t, but such
that from an instant t' < t on it will be clear that it will not be reduced
to a contracted possible: we will not have Mtipt>. Since the contraction
of this possible between now and t' has not even been envisaged, this
amounts to a denial of premise (B). We then posit, subject to the
validity of (A):
(A) and (~B) (3t) ~LN~pt- (t^N < ti < t D~ MtlPtl).
What is the meaning of this assertion that formally contradicts Aris-
totle? It will be seen in examining the two limiting cases that arise
when N and t are identified and when t\ = t is precisely fixed. In the
first case we reach a contradiction: pN is impossible and its negation is
not necessary. In the second case we assert, for example, that it is not
impossible, if it is 6 o'clock, that I should not take a certain train at
8:02, although at no intermediate instant am I faced with the concrete
possibility of taking it. In short, the event considered is a verbal pos-
sible, a word that makes no commitment. For Aristotle, for Diodorus,
for Chrysippus, even though there is no logical contradiction in the
concept this word expresses, even if we consider the concept possible,
it "is" not a possible as long as the impossibility of the contraction at
the stated instant is not excluded and as long as the diverse hindrances
that are liable to intervene have not been removed.
This is what we sometimes express in explicitly adding the clause
of non-hindrance to the statement of diachronic possibility. Aristotle,
2
Metaphysics, Q, 3, 1047°24-25.
246 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
who knows what saying something means, has been seen to mention
this given.3
A being has a potency insofar as this is a potency to act, not an
absolute power, but subject to certain conditions, among which will
be included the absence of external obstacles. For a possible to be
authenticated such, the hindrances to its realization must first be ruled
out. It is because it receives them instead of ruling them out that the
first objection invalidates (B) so readily.
Henri Bergson and William James, in the name of metaphysics
and psychology, and often in thinking that they were criticizing logic
and everyday language, defended an idea similar to that expressed by
the objection made against conditional necessity. It may be doubted
whether the testimony of language can be cited in an unequivocal fash-
ion on the matter. Aristotle, in any case, to whom we owe the dis-
tinction between the limits and the parts of time and who on other
occasions rested arguments on the distinction, did not look to it for a
solution to the aporia on freedom but reserved the use of it to extri-
cating us from the labyrinth of the continuum. The fact is that the
axiom of conditional necessity does not seem on its own to commit
us to an interpretation in terms of instants. All that is required by
contraction is the identity of the two indices. While and for as long as
the possible lasts, the actuality lasts. The validity of the axiom in no
way depends on the particular conception one adopts as regards the
relation between the continuum and its elements.
4
See above, 6.6, p. 149 sq.
5
See above, 6.9, pp. 159-160.
6
P.W. Lindgren, G.W. McElrath, Introduction to Probability and Statistics3,
MacMillan, London, 1969, p. 68, where the authors give mathematical precision
to the sense of the terms "approximately proportional" and "negligible". E. Borel,
Elements de la Theorie des Probabilites, Paris, Albin-Michel, 1950, p. 186-187.
248 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
increasing J\f will suffice for reducing that deviation. The annual occur-
rence of two events has the probability 0.1839 if, and only if, in a long
series of years and for like populations, it is probable that the limit of
the difference between relative frequency and probability tends toward
0. There is, therefore, no probability without a determination of the
conditions of realization of the probable event; and these conditions of
non-hindrance affect the probabilities of rare events as much as those
of frequent ones.
What then, in probabilistic terms, would correspond to the state-
ment (C) which asserts the existence of a never realized possible? It
would be a statement asserting that, no matter how long the sequence
of trials chosen relatively to a positive probability nor how great the
number of trials become, the probability that the relative frequency of
the expected event should differ from the probability of the event by
more than a small number, e, cannot be made as small as one likes.
And this statement contradicts the theorem of Jacques Bernoulli.
Thus when proper care is taken to translate the Master Argument's
premises into probabilistic terms, the law of large numbers leads an-
alytically to an acceptance of Diodorus' solution and incrimination of
premise (C). To apply probabilities to the natural sciences is to bind
these latter to frequencies. The sense in which the words "real" and
"virtual" are to be taken here still remains to be specified. For in
the probabilistic reconstruction of the Master Argument, the two con-
tradictory statements expressing it are both asymptotic. Their truth
depends on a passage to the limit for an infinite number of trials. A
probability is not defined by a frequency after the manner in which
Diodorus defined a possible by one or more realizations; and the pas-
sage of the relative frequency to the probability is itself only probable.
The realizability to which the possible is reduced is to be understood
as a virtual sequence of virtual events on a plane of abstract repre-
sentation. As happens every time a scientific concept is defined, we
have changed the sense of the term from that which it had in ordi-
nary language. The individual possible takes its place in a "reality"
going beyond experience, since it is made up of a virtual sequence of
virtual events. But the infinite future postulated by Diodorus also has
a transcendence comparable to that of this sequence.
THE SPECIAL STATUS OF PREMISE (C) / 251
Number of
quadruplet births 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
in 17 years
Observed
frequencies 7 5 4 0 1 0 0 0
Expected
values 6.25 6.25 3.13 1.04 0.26 0.07 0 0
It will be noted that except for the numbers 6 and 7 the expected values
all differ from the observed frequencies with the deviation in excess of
1, the value of the standard deviation, for the numbers 1 and 3. The
test will be based on the value of a mean square deviation:
i=7 / ,.
which gives:
(0.75)2 (1.25)2 (0.87)2 (1.04)2 (0.74)2 (0.07)2 =
6.25 6.25 3.13 1.04 0.26 0.07
Under asymptotic conditions for the number of trials,10 the statistic
would obey a distribution \ 2 with 6 degrees of freedom. If ^ 2 is too
large there will be reason to cast doubt on the hypothesis H0. The
question that arises is for which set of values x2 > M (M being con-
stant) the hypothesis HO is to be rejected, with the constant M devised
to assign the probability a of rejecting H0 when H0 is true. 11 In other
words, to fix M is to fix the probability a that one will accept of being
mistaken in rejecting a true hypothesis:
Q = 7r(reject H0\H0)
10
"The exact distribution of this statistic
=E :
,,2 _ V^ (/« --A/po;) 2
is not simple and it depends on the p0's in the null distribution (Ho)', but it was
found that this dependence disappears as the sample size becomes infinite, and that
the distribution for n = oo can be computed. It is a 'chi-square distribution with
n — 1 degrees of freedom' ". (Lindgren, McElrath, op. cit., p. 240).
n
Lindgren, McElrath, op. cit., p. 240.
254 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
Let us decide, for example, to run the risk of being mistaken with a
probability of a = 0.10. In the table for \2 with 7 - 1 = 6 degrees of
freedom, we shall then choose M such that FxiM = 0.90, which gives
M = 10.6. Since x2 = 3.92 < 10.6, the test calls for acceptance of the
hypothesis of a Poisson distribution.
Even apart from asymptotic considerations, the decision to accept
or reject a statistical hypothesis is never exempt from risk. All that
can be demanded of it is that it be informed by the measure of the
risk involved. Then too, this measure should be exact. But what is it
in fact that we see? First we calculated the Poisson Law of parame-
ter 1, in forcing the last decimal place, for 9 degrees of freedom: the
approximative total of the probabilities fell short of 1. Next we con-
sulted a table in order to specify the sense of the word probability in
such a distribution. That table was limited to 7 degrees of freedom.
Since the values not listed by the table were smaller than 1/2(0.001),
it "rounded off' the value of 7r(7) in conformity with the table's degree
of precision.12 Whatever the degree of precision required of a table,
all values going beyond that degree of precision will be disregarded.
Without such disregard, and thus without there being imposed some
limit to the degree of precision, the very formulation of a statistical
test would become impossible and the probability calculus would have
no application to experience.
This necessary approximation has attracted little attention from
the men of science, with the exception of Emile Borel. It is, so to
speak, the counterpart of the law of large numbers. As an idealiza-
tion of a theoretical order, the law of large numbers embeds a finite
sequence of trials in an infinite one. As a practical idealization, the
"law" of approximation enjoins us to disregard a part of probability
or a sufficiently small probability. The law of large numbers translates
Diodorus' definition of the possible into probabilistic terms. It will
be seen that the law bearing on approximation gives consistency to
Chrysippus' definition of the probable.
Borel writes: "The practical applications of the results [bearing on
repeated trials] are dominated by an empirical law that ... must be
regarded as absolutely certain and that might be called the unique law
of chance. That law, which is altogether simple, can be expressed as
follows: Events with an extremely weak probability are never realized,
but this statement should still be made explicit by indicating just what
12
Boursin, Caussat, op. cit., p. 324. Instead of ir(7) = 0.00007 we take 7r(7) =
0.0001, in introducing an error of 0.00003 < 1/2(0.001).
THE SPECIAL STATUS OF PREMISE (C) / 255
tile by the canon) to the final state (arrival on the detector at point
x). Furthermore, this transition can be analyzed. It is the sum of
two possible transitions: one in which the particle passes through the
intermediary state \ua > (passage through hole A), the other in which
it passes through the intermediary state \Ub > (passage through hole
B):
(/x|i> = (fx\Ua)(Ua\i) + (fx\Ub)(ub\i).
Attribution of corresponding probabilities involves, in all cases, the
elaboration of a density function making is possible to speak of the
probability of the detection of a particle at point x and of conventions
that allow of assigning numbers to the elements of the diagram of
transitions that will be apt to suitably define the probabilities sought.
Of these conventions we shall retain only what is of importance for the
discussion of the Master Argument. The expression for the transition
(fx\i) is generally a complex number, and its probability is equal to
the square of that expression, |(/i|«)| 2 , which is always a real number.
Experiment shows that every time we observe, or can observe, by
which branch of the alternative the particle has passed, the total prob-
ability is the sum of the probabilities of the two branches:
(1) *«/*!»)) - *((/x|tt«X««l')) + T((/»l«6>(« 6 |t».
22
This equality corresponds to the classical hypothesis according to
which every transition is observable and corresponds to a well defined
path. We shall see that, with the validity of the Master Argument,
it entails Diodorus' solution. Quantum particles, on the other hand,
obey a different law. The total probability is the square of the sum
of the transitions — we are speaking now of probability amplitudes — so
that here there appears a term of interference that did not figure in
expression (1):
(2) Jr((/*|i» = *({/,K){tt«|») + {/*K>(«fc|i».
This equality23 disallows observation and the observability of the in-
termediary state. It is impossible to determine by which branch of the
alternative the transition is effected. Consequently, there is not a well
defined path corresponding to a transition. We shall see that in this
22
That is to say:
23
That is to say:
K/. Wl 2 = (!(/« + «a}|2 • IK + i>| 2 ) + (K/x + «fc)| 2 • ItoWl 2 ) +
2(/x|u a )(u 0 |t){/ x K){u f c |i).
It is this last term, called the interference term, that makes the difference.
CONTINGENCY AND IGNORANCE / 259
case the Master Argument loses its cogency and physics can do without
Diodorus' solution.
Let us first consider the case of classical particles. The frequency fx
(the number of particles reaching the detector at x] is measured, and in
shuttering hole B the frequency JXA (the number of particles reaching
x after passing through hole A) is measured, as is the frequency fxB
with hole A shuttered. If M is the number of particles having passed
through one of the two holes, then fx\J\f, fxA\N and fxB\-N" measure
the corresponding relative frequencies that will have to be compared to
the respective theoretical probabilities KX,KXA,'!J'XB- There are three
weak laws of large numbers that follow from this, the first resulting
from the sum of the other two. When the particles are projectiles in
a Young apparatus, it is a simple matter to reconstruct the Master
Argument. The projectiles collected on the detector screen at x fall
into two disjoint classes, though without our being able to distinguish
those having passed through A from those having passed through B.
We are nevertheless certain, now that the event has taken place, that
each individual projectile considered has passed either through A or
through B. In the first case the probability that it passed through B is
zero, and vice versa in the second case. Thus axiom (A) is verified. We
are justified then, as regards the consequent of axiom (B), in retaining
only that disjunct that has to do with the future. But at the moment
of firing, the probability TTX attributed to a certain particle now col-
lected at x may be broken down into the two non null components TTXA
and TTXB . The weak law of large numbers applied to TTXA and -KXB
guarantees that the probabilistic version of the conjunction of axioms
(A.B.NH) holds for both of these probabilities, notwithstanding the
fact that they are contraries: each of the two "degrees" of the possible
contracts and is realized with the frequency sought as the number of
trials is increased at will.24
24
Let us shutter B and count /XA at x. The law says that
lim P(|^--7r^|> £ ) = 0.
JV—>oo J\
One might think that with the two holes A and B left open and
the two probabilities TTXA and TTXB each greater than zero the Master
Argument would cease to apply. It would be argued that since the law
of large numbers verifies the conjunction of axioms (A.B.NH) for TTXA
in probabilistic terms, the contrary event is excluded though without
its probability being null, and this is a state of things that pleads in
favor of axiom (C). But this would be to confuse two experiments that
are in fact independent. For just what does it mean to say of a particle
collected at x that at the moment of its emission it had probability
KXA of passing through A and probability TTXB of passing through B, A
and B both being open? Take one such particle. At the very latest at
the moment of passage through the holes, the possible will have had to
synchronically contract, in conformity with axiom (B), and will have
had simultaneously to be realized, in conformity with axiom (NH).
The possibility of the contrary choice is nothing but a word once the
contraction is made. Are we obliged then to recognize that before the
contraction, in the time interval separating the emission of the particle
from its passage through the hole, there was a contrary possibility and
that since that contrary possibility was destined never to be realized,
the probabilistic model is seen to verify axiom (C)? The symmetry of
the Young apparatus requires that TTXA = TTXB for x equidistant from A
and B. Isn't this an argument of weight for attributing equi-possibility
to both the excluded and the realized events?
But what is the meaning of the concession made? Have we really
the right to put off the choice—that is to say, the synchronic contrac-
tion and realization—until passage through the holes? This would be
to misunderstand the meaning of equality (1). For indeed, with all due
precaution taken as regards times of emission and the counting of par-
ticles, we can postulate that collecting the particles simultaneously at
x that have come through one or the other hole with both holes open
comes down to the same thing as collecting successively at x those
particles having come through A with B shuttered, then those having
come through B with A shuttered. As this second experimental case
decides for Diodorus' solution, the first will then do so as well. In other
words we can imagine that the particles are already partitioned at the
source into two exclusive classes much as would be the balls of two dif-
ferent colors in an urn. The emission of a particle is like a drawing in a
statistical mix. If M is the total number of particles, N.TTXA of them are
marked "destination x via A" and A(TT X B of them "destination x via
B". Reduced to its simplest expression the Master Argument, together
with Diodorus' solution, asserts only that it is impossible for one ball
CONTINGENCY AND NATURE / 261
state of superposition into a state proper. Thus axiom (B) turns out
to be truistically confirmed and even reinforced since the synchronic
contraction extends to all moments preceding that of the reduction.
Axiom (C) is verified by a possible that is not realized. But since
the term of interference precludes our observing through which hole the
particle has passed, it is impossible to say which of the two contrary
probability amplitudes has been realized, so that there ceases to be an
exclusion between axiom (C) and the conjunction of axioms (B and
NH) and, furthermore, axiom (C) is strictly speaking undecidable.
What of axiom (NH)? It is verified when there is reduction of the
wave-particle, that is to say, when the process of measurement selects
one particular value of the observable. If such a reduction takes place
at the moment the particle passes through one of the holes, the in-
terference effect is destroyed for detection. If it takes place only at
the moment of detection, the interference effect is produced. In other
words, nature chooses the statistical mix or superposition accordingly
as we observe or do not observe where the particle passes. To decree
along with classical mechanics that the state of a physical system is
composed of a set of physical magnitudes and that these magnitudes
are all simultaneously observable is to choose law (1). To choose law
(2) is to define the general state of a physical system by superposition:
such a state is not observable. An observable is associated with the
action of an operator on it and it is that action that produces a proper
state.
What dismantles the Master Argument's premises is the new dis-
tinction in the history of modal notions between a probability and a
probability amplitude. Classical physics was content with the oppo-
sition 'This particle passes through A' versus 'This particle has the
probability IT of passing through A'. This opposition has nothing to do
with ontology: it incorporates what is due to our ignorance into the
determination of natural phenomena. Instead of attributing a prop-
erty or magnitude to a physical system, we attribute it a disposition or
propensity to have that property or magnitude. Probability measures
that disposition or propensity that belongs to the system in act. A
probability amplitude is something altogether different. We can com-
pare it to an embryonic probability as the inventors of the infinitesimal
calculus compared the "moment" of motion to an embryonic motion
that an integration would bring to a state of "whole" motion. But
the comparison limps. For the probability amplitude, which is gener-
ally a complex quantity, does not figure among the elements of reality.
To obtain a probability we must multiply two conjugated probability
amplitudes. This means that, when we attribute that amplitude to
CONTINGENCY AND NATURE / 265
267
268 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
88, 89, 92, 225, 228, 235, Godfrey of Fontaines, 83, 239
238-240 Goldschmidt, V., 4, 98, 100,
126, 176, 177, 181, 182
Edghill, 137, 141 Granger, G.-G., 12, 18
Effler, R., 232, 238 Gregory of Rimini, 90
Eleatics, 55, 153 Gueroult, M., 192, 193, 198-
Elisabeth (Princess), 202, 203 200
Empedocles, 162, 199
Epictetus, vii, viii, 3, 4, 6, 8,13, Haack, S., 157, 158, 161
16, 22, 29, 43, 62, 92, 96, Hamelin, O., 118,121,128,129,
125, 133 151, 155, 223
Epicureans, 47, 133, 144, 170, Heimsoeth, H., 183, 184
171, 183, 187, 222, 223, Heinzmann, G., 161
230 Heracliteans, 98, 139
Epicurus, 7, 133, 140, 150, 155, Heraclitus, 98, 102, 139
169, 170, 172, 174-180, Hermite, Ch., 188
182-189, 192, 195, 198, Herodotus (EPICURUS' corre-
199, 201, 207-209, 212, spondant), 174-176, 178,
222, 228, 261 179, 183, 186
Euclid (of MEGARA), 67, 153 Herophilus, 55
Eusebius, 98 Heyting, A., 173
Hintikka, J., 14, 144, 152
Faust, A., 228
Hobbes, 33
Festus, 10
Hughes, C.E. (see CRESS-
Fichte, J.G., 198
WELL, M.J.)
F011esdal, D., 121
Hume, D., 109
van Fraassen, B., 160, 161
Fraenkel, H., 10 Jalabert, J. (see LEIBNIZ,
Frede, D., 141, 150 notes)
Frede, M., 63, 108, 109, 111, James, W., 246
115, 121
Frette, 31 Kant, I., 170, 186-192, 194-
von Fritz, K., 5, 95, 155 198, 203-205
Furley, D., 175, 177, 178, 185, Kelsen, H., 182
199 Kleene, S.C., 174
Kneale, W. and M., 6, 12, 44,
Galileo, 190 59, 111, 151,217
Gassendi, 192, 195, 201 Krantz, W. (see DIELS, H.)
Aulus Gellius, 12, 118 Kretzmann (see ADAMS)
Gerhardt, C.J. (See LEIBNIZ,
notes) Lambert, J.H, 157, 161, 189,
Gilson, E., 83-86,232, 235, 236, 219
239, 240 Laplace, K., 246, 261, 262
288 / NECESSITY OR CONTINGENCY: THE MASTER ARGUMENT
Robin, L., 64, 208, 211 Tricot, J., 147, 149, 157
Rodis-Lewis, G., 176, 177, 183,
184 Urquhart, A., 6
Ross, D., 139, 140, 147, 149, Valla, L., 20
150, 158, 232 Verbeke, G. (see AMMONIUS)
Russell, L.B., 51, 217 Vidal, Ch. (see BERGE, P.)
Ryle, G., 112 Vives (see DUNS SCOTUS)
Vlastos, G., 175
Sands, M. (see FEYNMANN,
Vuillemin, J., 12, 67, 115, 122,
R.)
189, 199
Sartre, J.P., 183
Scharle, T., 219 Weyl, H., 140
Schuhl, P.M., 5, 95 Windelband, W. (see HEIM-
Sedley, D., 10, 13, 51, 53, 58, SOETH, H.)
66,67, 112,115, 142, 174, Wisemann, H. (see BOLLACK,
220 J.)
Sextus Empiricus, 47, 52-55, von Wright, G.H., 5, 6, 51, 78,
62,66,107,108,114,126. 148
176, 177, 180, 183, 188 Wyclef, 33
William of Shyreswood, 217
Simplicius, 28, 57, 98, 100, 129 Zeller, E., 4-6
Socrates, 220, 236 Zenon of Citium, 98, 99, 101,
Spencer, H., 201 119, 222
Spinoza, B., 203 Zenon of Elea, 10
Stagirite (see ARISTOTLE) Zenon of Tarsus, 99
Stobaeus, 102, 103
Stoics, 6, 10, 32, 33, 44, 47,
67,98-102,117,129,150,
163, 165, 169, 197, 210,
215, 222, 223, 229, 230,
255
Storrs McCall, 171, 174
Suppes, P., 262