Hierarchy and The Sources of International Law
Hierarchy and The Sources of International Law
* Senior Lecturer, Keele University (UK). This article is a significantly extended version
of a chapter in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK ON THE SOURCES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW (Jean
d'Aspremont & Samantha Besson eds., 2017).
285
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
11. SHAW, supra note 3, at 50. Scholars do debate, of course, whether Article 38
represents an authoritative and definitive statement of sources (i.e., the meta-norm of
sources), or merely a clause of applicable law for the ICJ. Few dispute its pragmatic value
as a rallying point for the doctrine of sources, however. See JÖRG KAMMERHOFER,
UNCERTAINTY IN INTERNATIONAL LAW: A KELSENIAN PERSPECTIVE 208-10 (2011).
12. Article 38 states:
The Court, whose function it is to decide in accordance with international law
such disputes as are submitted to it, shall apply:
a. international conventions, whether general or particular,
establishing rules expressly recognized by the consenting states;
b. international custom, as evidence of a general practice accepted as
law;
c. the general principles of law recognized by civilized nations;
d. subject to the provisions of Article 59, judicial decisions and the
teachings of the most highly qualified publicists of the various
nations, as subsidiary means for the determination of rules of law.
Statute of the International Court of Justice art. 38, June 26, 1945, 59 Stat. 1055.
13. On the drafting history of Article 38, see Akehurst, supra note 6, at 274.
14. See JAN KLABBERS, INTERNATIONAL LAW 25 (2013) (“[J]udicial decisions and the
writings of the most highly qualified publicists are listed as subsidiary means only . . . it
follows from the organizing principle of sovereignty that [these subsidiary means] cannot
make law, but only apply it.”); HUGH THIRLWAY, THE SOURCES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 8
(2014) (“Neither a judge nor a scholar says ‘This is the law, because I say so’; they both lay
down what they regard as established by one of the other sources.”).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
15. Military and Paramilitary Activities in and Against Nicaragua (Nicar. v U.S.),
Judgment, 1986 I.C.J Rep. 14, ¶ 176 (June 27) (“It cannot therefore be held that Article 51
[of the United Nations Charter] is a provision which ‘subsumes and supervenes’ customary
international law . . . . [I]n the field in question . . . customary international law continues
to exist alongside treaty law.”).
16. See Fragmentation of International Law: Difficulties Arising from the
Diversification and Expansion of International Law, Rep. of the Study Grp. of the Int’l
Law Comm’n, ¶¶ 86, 88, U.N. Doc. A/CN.4/L.682 (Apr. 13, 2006) [hereinafter
Fragmentation Report]; PAUWELYN, supra note 9, at 89-109; Maarten Bos, The Hierarchy
Among the Recognized Manifestations (“Sources”) of International Law, 25 NETH. INT’L L.
REV. 334 (1978).
17. For a theory of fragmentation as struggle for institutional hegemony and
normative authoritativeness, see Martti Koskenniemi, The Fate of Public International
Law: Between Technique and Politics, 70 MOD. L. REV. 1 (2007); Martti Koskenniemi,
International Law and Hegemony: A Reconfiguration, 17 CAMBRIDGE REV. INT’L AFF. 197
(2004).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
hiérarchie entre les différences sources qu’il énumère . . . on constate qu’il y a accord sur
les idées suivantes . . . [l]a première source, incontestablement la plus importante, est
formée par les traités.”) (emphasis removed).
23. For example, PATRICK DAILLIER ET AL., DROIT INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC (8th ed.
2009), subcategorize their chapter on international law-making into “formation
conventionnelle” and “formation non conventionnelle.”
24. E.g., Fragmentation Report, supra note 16, ¶ 85 (“This informal
hierarchy . . . emerges as a ‘forensic’ or a ‘natural’ aspect of legal reasoning. Any court or
lawyer will first look at treaties, then custom and then the general principles of law for an
answer to a normative problem.”).
25. PAUWELYN, supra note 9, at 133-34; see also John K. Setear, An Iterative
Perspective on Treaties: A Synthesis of International Relations Theory and International
Law, 37 HARV. INT’L L.J. 139, 215 (1996) (highlighting that treaty provisions often include
specific mechanisms for dispute resolution).
26. Jason Beckett, Customary International Law, in INTERNATIONAL LAW FOR
INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 122, 134 (Başak Çali ed., 2010) (emphasis omitted).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
27. Disputes occasionally arise regarding the validity of a treaty or its termination,
though this is a rather rare occurrence. For a characteristic example, see Gabčíkovo–
Nagymaros Project (Hung. v. Slovk.), 1997 I.C.J. Rep. 7, ¶ 142 (Sept. 25).
28. The ICJ was notoriously criticized for its method of ascertaining customary law
in the Nicaragua case, with some legal scholars blaming the Court for its “revisionist”
approach, blurring the lines between practice and opinio juris, and “trashing” customary
international law. Similar criticisms were levelled against the ICRC when it published its
2009 restatement of customary international humanitarian law. See MARIO PROST, THE
CONCEPT OF UNITY IN PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW 100-02 (2012).
29. Hilary Charlesworth, Law-making and Sources, in THE CAMBRIDGE COMPANION
TO INTERNATIONAL LAW 187, 189-90 (James Crawford & Martti Koskenniemi eds., 2012).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
35. G.J.H. VAN HOOF, RETHINKING THE SOURCES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 117 (1983).
36. On the methodological problems posed by the identification of customary law,
see OLIVIER CORTEN, MÉTHODOLOGIE DU DROIT INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC 149-78 (2009).
37. THOMAS M. FRANCK, THE POWER OF LEGITIMACY AMONG NATIONS 59-60 (1990).
38. MARTIN DIXON, TEXTBOOK ON INTERNATIONAL LAW 55 (7th ed. 2013).
39. For a discussion of “source determinacy” as a signifier of progress in
international law, see Thomas Skouteris, The Force of a Doctrine: Art. 38 of the PCIJ
Statute and the Sources of International Law, in EVENTS: THE FORCE OF INTERNATIONAL
LAW 69 (Fleur Johns et al. eds., 2011). The notion that the primary function of the law of
treaties should be to provide certainty and security in legal relations was central to
proceedings at the 1969 Vienna Conference. Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties
pmbl., May 23, 1969, 1155 U.N.T.S. 332.
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
53. FRANCK, supra note 37, at 59-60; Thomas M. Franck, Legitimacy in the
International System, 82 AM. J. INT’L L. 705 (1988).
54. L. OPPENHEIM, INTERNATIONAL LAW: VOL. 1, PEACE 24 (1905).
55. Id.
56. LAUTERPACHT, supra note 30, at 58.
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
57. HANS KELSEN, GENERAL THEORY OF LAW AND STATE 369 (1945).
58. PAUL REUTER, INTRODUCTION TO THE LAW OF TREATIES 29 (José Mico & Peter
Haggenmacher trans., 2012).
59. JAMES CRAWFORD, CHANCE, ORDER, CHANGE: THE COURSE OF INTERNATIONAL
LAW 57 (2014).
60. Brigitte Stern, Custom at the Heart of International Law, 11 DUKE J. COMP. &
INT’L L. 89, 89 (2001).
61. The notion that the rule pacta sunt servanda is a customary rule is open to
question. Kelsen himself eventually abandoned this view, arguing instead that the rule
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
pacta sunt servanda is an axiom incapable of juridical demonstration and not itself a part
of the system of positive law. HANS KELSEN, PRINCIPLES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 190 (2nd
prtg. 2003); François Rigaux, Hans Kelsen on International Law, 9 EUR. J. INT’L L. 325,
328 (1998).
62. Gerald Fitzmaurice, Some Problems Regarding the Formal Sources of
International Law, SYMBOLAE VERZIJL 153 (1958), reprinted in MARTIN DIXON ET AL.,
CASES & MATERIALS ON INTERNATIONAL LAW 23, 23 (6th ed. 2016).
63. Id.
64. Id. For a rebuttal, see M.H. Mendelson, Are Treaties Merely a Source of
Obligation?, in PERESTROIKA AND INTERNATIONAL LAW (William E. Butler ed., 1990).
65. PARRY, supra note 19, at 34.
66. Id.
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
72. North Sea Continental Shelf Cases (Ger. v. Den.; Ger. v. Neth.), Judgment, 1969
I.C.J. Rep. 3, ¶ 63 (Feb. 20).
73. Beckett, supra note 26, at 124.
74. See, e.g., Military and Paramilitary Activities in and Against Nicaragua (Nicar.
v. U.S.), Judgment, 1986 I.C.J Rep. 14, ¶ 269 (June 27) (“[I]n international law there are
no rules, other than such rules as may be accepted by the State concerned, by treaty or
otherwise.”); Barcelona Traction, Light & Power Co., Ltd. (Belg. v. Spain), 1970 I.C.J. Rep.
3, ¶ 89 (Feb. 5) (“Here as elsewhere, a body of rules could only have developed with the
consent of those concerned.”).
75. See, e.g., JOHANN CASPAR BLUNTSCHLI, LE DROIT INTERNATIONAL CODIFIÉ 58 n.1
(1895) (“Si le droit international était exclusivement le produit de la libre volonté des états,
aucun d’eux ne serait obligé vis-à-vis des autres d’en respecter les principes, quand ces
principes n’auraient pas été sanctionnés par un traité.”).
76. E.g., Nico Krisch, The Decay of Consent: International Law in an Age of Global
Public Goods, 108 AM. J. INT’L L. 1, 1-2 (2014).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
77. Jonathan I. Charney, Universal International Law, 87 AM. J. INT’L L. 529, 529
(1993).
78. Christian Tomuschat, Obligations Arising for States Without or Against their
Will, 241 RECUEIL DES COURS 195 (1993).
79. Andrew T. Guzman, Against Consent, 52 VA. J. INT’L L. 747, 788 (2012); Laurence
R. Helfer, Nonconsensual International Lawmaking, 2008 U. ILL. L. REV. 71, 125.
80. E.g., JOEL P. TRACHTMAN, THE FUTURE OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 283 (2013).
81. C.G. WEERAMANTRY, UNIVERSALISING INTERNATIONAL LAW 222-25 (2004).
82. Id. at 223.
83. Id. at 223-24.
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
84. E.g., R.P. Anand, Attitude of the Asian-African States Toward Certain Problems
of International Law, 15 INT'L. & COMP. L.Q. 55 (1966); Prakash Sinha, Perspective of the
Newly Independent States on the Binding Quality of International Law, 14 INT’L & COMP.
L.Q. 121 (1965).
85. This critique mirrored that which was levelled earlier by the Soviet doctrine
against custom, seen as entrenching the hegemony of capitalist states. E.g., Grigorii
Ivanovich Tunkin, Co-existence and International Law, 3 RECUEIL DES COURS 3, 46-48
(1958).
86. MOHAMMED BEDJAOUI, TOWARDS A NEW INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC ORDER
133-34 (1979).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
95. On the early history of the doctrine of sovereign equality and the influence of the
philosophical ideas of Grotius, Hobbes, Locke, and others on its formation, see Arnold
McNair, Equality in International Law, 26 MICH. L. REV. 131 (1927).
96. The Antelope, 23 U.S. (10 Wheat.) 66, 122 (1825).
97. Ann Van Wynen Thomas & A.J. Thomas, Jr., Equality of States in International
Law—Fact or Fiction?, 37 VA. L. REV. 791, 791 (1951).
98. Montevideo Convention on the Rights and Duties of States art. 4, Dec. 26, 1933,
165 L.N.T.S. 19 (“States are juridically equal, enjoy the same rights, and have equal
capacity in their exercise.”); U.N. Charter art. 2(1) (“The Organization is based on the
principle of the sovereign equality of all its Members.”); G.A. Res. 2625 (XXV), at 124
(Oct. 24, 1970) (“All States enjoy sovereign equality. They have equal rights and duties
and are equal members of the international community, notwithstanding differences of an
economic, social, political or other nature.”).
99. E.g., Jurisdictional Immunities of the State (Ger. v. It.), Judgment, 2012 I.C.J.
Rep. 99, ¶ 57 (Feb. 3) (“[T]he principle of sovereign equality of States . . . [i]s one of the
fundamental principles of the international legal order.”); CASSESE, supra note 3, at 48 (“It
is safe to conclude that sovereign equality constitutes the linchpin of the whole body of
international legal standards, the fundamental premise on which all international
relations rest.”).
100. E.g., CRAWFORD, supra note 6, at 449 (“Obviously, the allocation of power and
the capacity to project it in reality are different things, which suggests that while all states
are equal, some are more equal than others.”).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
101. On formal or “forensic” equality, see McNair, supra note 95, at 136, 151 (“An
international tribunal, or a municipal tribunal when giving effect to the international
obligations of the State to which it belongs, pays the same attention to the rights of France
as it does to the rights of Costa Rica . . . [and sovereign equality] is used to denote [e]quality
before the law, equality in the assertion and vindication by law of such rights as a state
may have.”) (emphasis removed); see also Composition of the Court, 1950-51 INT’L CT.
JUSTICE Y.B. 17 (statement of President J. Basdevant) (“Before this Court, there are no
great or small states.”).
102. Military and Paramilitary Activities in and Against Nicaragua (Nicar. v. U.S.),
Judgment, 1986 I.C.J Rep. 14, ¶ 258 (June 27) (“Every State possesses a fundamental
right to choose and implement its own political, economic and social systems.”). On the
notion of “existential equality,” see GERRY SIMPSON, GREAT POWERS AND OUTLAW STATES:
UNEQUAL SOVEREIGNS IN THE INTERNATIONAL LEGAL ORDER 53-56 (2004).
103. Most of the “equality rights” are restated in the UN Friendly Relations
Declaration, G.A. Res. 2625 (XXV), supra note 98. For an early conceptualization of
sovereign equality in terms of substantive rights, see ROBERT PHILLIMORE,
COMMENTARIES UPON INTERNATIONAL LAW, VOL. 1, at 216-17 (3d. ed. 1879), who extracted
four specific “rights of equality” from the principle of sovereign equality: the right of
protecting subjects abroad, the right to recognition, the right to external marks of honor,
and the right to make treaties.
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
104. See McNair, supra note 95, at 142-47; SIMPSON, supra note 102, at 48-53.
105. Case of the S.S. Lotus (Fr. v. Turk.), Judgment, 1927 P.C.I.J. (ser. A) No. 10, at
18 (Sept. 7).
106. This is how Oppenheim, in particular, envisaged sovereign equality at the turn
of the 20th century. See OPPENHEIM, supra note 54, at 162 (“The consequence of . . . legal
equality is that, whenever a question arises which has to be settled by the consent of the
members of the Family of Nations, every State has a right to a vote, but to one vote only.
And legally the vote of the weakest and smallest State has quite as much weight as the
vote of the largest and most powerful.”).
107. On sovereign equality as autonomy, see Hans Kelsen, The Principle of
Sovereign Equality of States as a Basis for International Organization, 53 YALE L.J. 207,
209 (1944) (“[N]o State has jurisdiction over another State . . . without the latter’s
consent . . . [and] the courts of one State are not competent to question the validity of the
acts of another State . . . . Understood this way, the principle of equality is the principle of
autonomy of the States as subjects of international law.”).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
108. For a historical account of these struggles, see R.P. ANAND, SOVEREIGN
EQUALITY OF STATES IN INTERNATIONAL LAW ch. 3 (2008).
109. See B.S. Chimni, Legitimating the International Rule of Law, in THE
CAMBRIDGE COMPANION TO INTERNATIONAL LAW, supra note 29, at 290, 294 (stating that
international law generally codifies the interests of powerful states).
110. See id. at 290.
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
111. The ability to sign treaties with European powers was of course a privilege
reserved to a few recognized non-European sovereigns such as China, Japan, Korea, and
the Ottoman Empire. Most non-European territories were denied the privilege of
sovereignty and were thus managed (“civilized”) through conquest and colonial rule. The
leading text on the role of international law in regulating the encounters between Europe
and the non-European world remains ANTONY ANGHIE, IMPERIALISM, SOVEREIGNTY AND
THE MAKING OF INTERNATIONAL LAW (2004).
112. On the history of unequal treaties, see Lucius Caflisch, Unequal Treaties, 1992
GERMAN Y.B. INT’L L. 52, 52; Matthew Craven, What Happened to Unequal Treaties? The
Continuities of Informal Empire, 74 NORDIC J. INT'L L. 335 (2005); MICHAEL AUSLIN,
NEGOTIATING WITH IMPERIALISM: THE UNEQUAL TREATIES AND THE CULTURE OF JAPANESE
DIPLOMACY (2004).
113. Gerry Simpson, International Law in Diplomatic History, in THE CAMBRIDGE
COMPANION TO INTERNATIONAL LAW, supra note 29, at 25, 35-36.
114. Id.
115. Id.
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
116. MARK JARRETT, THE CONGRESS OF VIENNA AND ITS LEGACY: WAR AND GREAT
POWER DIPLOMACY AFTER NAPOLEON 369 (2013).
117. For an overview of the varying influences imposed by different countries, see
Betsy Baker, Hague Peace Conferences (1899 and 1907), OXFORD PUB. INT’L LAW ¶¶ 9-11
(Nov. 2009), http://opil.ouplaw.com/view/10.1093/law:epil/9780199231690/law-
9780199231690-e305 [http://perma.cc/B2PL-6E3U].
118. Id.; see also EDWIN D. DICKINSON, THE EQUALITY OF STATES IN INTERNATIONAL
LAW 290-91 (1920).
119. See JAMES BROWN SCOTT, THE HAGUE PEACE CONFERENCES OF 1899 AND 1907,
at 165-73 (1909) (quoting and endorsing the views of, among others, Louis Renault, the
French delegate and chairman of the drafting committee, during his time as a U.S.
delegate to the Second Peace Conference).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
120. President Woodrow Wilson, The Fourteen Points Speech (Jan. 8, 1918), in THE
WILSON READER, VOL. 4, at 172, 177 (Francis Farmer ed., 1956) (“The program of the
world’s peace . . . as we see it, is this: I. Open covenants of peace, openly arrived at, after
which there shall be no private international understandings of any kind but diplomacy
shall proceed always frankly and in the public view.”).
121. SETH P. TILLMAN, ANGLO-AMERICAN RELATIONS AT THE PARIS PEACE
CONFERENCE OF 1919, at 84-85 (1961).
122. E.J. DILLON, THE INSIDE STORY OF THE PEACE CONFERENCE 201-02 (1920).
123. ANAND, supra note 108, at 87-88.
124. Id. at 88.
125. Id.; Gerry Simpson, The Great Powers, Sovereign Equality and the Making of
the United Nations Charter, 2000 AUSTL. Y.B. INT’L L. 133, 136.
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
126. See José E. Alvarez, A BIT on Custom, 42 N.Y.U. J. INT’L L. & POL. 17, 26, 38-39
(2009) (acknowledging the unequal nature of many BIT negotiations but nevertheless
stressing the validity of these agreements under the existing law of treaties). For a
resolutely apologetic defense of model BITs as facilitating negotiations and reducing the
drafting and negotiation costs of investment treaties, see STEPHAN W. SCHILL, THE
MULTILATERALIZATION OF INTERNATIONAL INVESTMENT LAW 91 (2009).
127. The adoption en force of the Copenhagen agreement was famously criticized by
the Venezuelan delegate who during the Conference’s closing session deliberately cut her
hand and drew blood, denouncing a “coup d’état against the United Nations.” Andrew
Gilligan, Copenhagen Summit Ends in Blood, Sweat and Recrimination, TELEGRAPH
(Dec. 20, 2009, 7:30 AM), http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/earth/copenhagen-climate-
change-confe/6845892/Copenhagen-summit-ends-in-blood-sweat-and-recrimination.html
[http://perma.cc/9Q3E-HBSZ].
128. Soft power is defined by Joseph Nye as “intangible power resources such as
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
culture, ideology, and institutions” which a state can use to set the political agenda and
determine the framework of debate in a way that shapes others’ preferences. Joseph S.
Nye, Jr., Soft Power, 80 FOREIGN POL. 153, 166-67 (1990).
129. BOYLE & CHINKIN, supra note 4, at 30-31.
130. For example, the principle of common but differentiated responsibilities has
recently been the object of sustained criticism from Western governments and scholars,
claiming that efficiency requires setting aside ethical principles in favor of swift, practical,
and politically acceptable action. E.g., ERIC A. POSNER & DAVID WEISBACH, CLIMATE
CHANGE JUSTICE 169-70 (2012). For a critical analysis, see Mario Prost & Alejandra Torres
Camprubí, Against Fairness? International Environmental Law, Disciplinary Bias, and
Pareto Justice, 25 LEIDEN J. INT’L L. 379 (2012); Benoît Mayer, Climate Change and
International Law in the Grim Days, 24 EUR. J. INT’L L. 947 (2013).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
149 (1957).
136. BYERS, supra note 134, at 8.
137. Lauterpacht, for instance, points to the overwhelming influence of the United
States and the UK, as the leading maritime powers of the day, on the emergence of
customary rules concerning the status of marine and submarine areas, noting that their
practice was treated as “authoritative almost as a matter of course from the outset.” See
HERSCH LAUTERPACHT, INTERNATIONAL LAW: VOLUME 3, PART 2-6: THE LAW OF PEACE,
PARTS II-VI, at 163 (1977).
138. For a recent restatement, see Michael Wood (Special Rapporteur), Second
Report on Identification of Customary International Law, ¶¶ 52-54, UN. Doc. A/CN.4/673
(May 22, 2014) (“[F]or a rule of general customary international law to emerge or be
identified, the practice need not be unanimous (universal); but, it must be ‘extensive’ or,
in other words, sufficiently widespread . . . . [T]he participation in the practice must also
be broadly representative.”).
139. As a recent example, the ICJ’s Nuclear Weapons advisory opinion states that
the opinio juris of the few states possessing nuclear weapons outweighs that of the large
majority of states that support their prohibition. Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear
Weapons, Advisory Opinion, 1996 I.C.J. Rep. 226, ¶¶ 64-73 (July 8). Judge Shi criticized
the Court’s approach and methodology, expressing reservations about the nuclear
deterrence policy. Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, Declaration of Judge
Shi, 1996 I.C.J. Rep. 277, 277-78.
140. On the pre-eminence of Western lawyers in the formulation of CIL (based on
the practice of a limited number of Western powers), see ONUMA YASUAKI, A
TRANSCIVILIZATIONAL PERSPECTIVE ON INTERNATIONAL LAW 135, 258-60 (2010). On the
dominance of the ICJ bar by international lawyers from developed states, see Shashank
P. Kumar & Cecily Rose, A Study of Lawyers Appearing Before the International Court of
Justice, 1999-2012, 25 EUR. J. INT’L L. 893 (2014).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
145. The four female members of the ILC are Concepción Escobar Hernández, Marie
G. Jacobsson, Xue Hanqin, and Paula Escarameia. Present and Former Members of the
International Law Commission (1949-present), INT’L LAW COMM’N (July 15, 2015), http://
legal.un.org/ilc/guide/annex2.shtml [http://perma.cc/Z4CV-4V28]. The only female Special
Rapporteurs to be appointed by the UN are Marie G. Jacobsson and Concepción Escobar
Hernández. Special Rapporteurs of the International Law Commission (1949-2014), INT’L
LAW COMM’N (July 15, 2015), http://legal.un.org/ilc/guide/annex3.shtml [http://perma.cc/
54TP-7DB2].
146. The four female justices are Xue Hanqin, Julia Sebutinde, Dame Rosalyn
Higgins, and Joan E. Donoghue. All Members, INT’L COURT OF JUSTICE, http://www.icj-cij.
org/court/index.php?p1=1&p2=2&p3=2 [http://perma.cc/82F8-3NR5] (last visited Dec. 15,
2016).
147. See generally Nienke Grossman, Sex on the Bench: Do Women Judges Matter to
the Legitimacy of International Courts?, 12 CHI. J. INT’L L. 647 (2012) (outlining a feminist
critique of international courts and tribunals from a democratic theory perspective).
148. Charlesworth, supra note 142, at 447-48.
149. Rosa Ehrenreich Brooks, Feminism and International Law: An Opportunity for
Transformation, 14 YALE J.L. & FEMINISM 345, 347 (2002).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
C. Legalized Hierarchies
The structure of international law-making, as the above
makes clear, is one dominated by oligarchy and patriarchy. There
is, it turns out, a significant discrepancy between the pragmatics
of sources and the foundational principle of legislative equality.
When confronted with this problem, international lawyers have
traditionally deployed a variety of strategies to reconcile material
hierarchies of influence and international law’s formal
commitment to sovereign equality. A classical posture of
international lawyers in this regard is one that politely
acknowledges the existence of legislative hierarchies but confines
them to the political domain, outside the law, as a mere fact of
international life. This narrative is deceiving, as it creates a false
dichotomy between de facto and de jure hierarchies which
neglects the manner in which hierarchies of influence are actually
internalized by the international legal order, including by its
system of sources.
International law (by which I mean actual, positive law; not
just diplomatic practice), to start with, has historically been very
152. See, e.g., HUGO GROTIUS, THE RIGHTS OF WAR AND PEACE INCLUDING THE LAW
OF NATURE AND OF NATIONS 392-93 (A.C. Campbell trans., 1901) (asserting that injustices
of war do not challenge a treaty’s validity but rather its interpretation); SAMUEL
PUFENDORF, OF THE LAW OF NATURE AND NATIONS 849 (Basil Kennett trans., 4th ed. 1729)
(arguing that compacts made with an enemy are required to be observed, save for treaties
that continue a state of war); DANIEL GARDNER, INSTITUTES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 573
(1860) (“Treaties made under forcible coercion are valid by the law of nations, though in
all codes of municipal law the rule is otherwise as to contracts of individuals. This is a rule
of necessity, as all wars would be endless if a valid treaty could not be made, and terms of
pacification ratified in a binding form.”); OPPENHEIM, supra note 54, at 525
(“[C]ircumstances of urgent distress, such as either defeat in war or the menace of a strong
State to a weak State, are . . . not regarded as excluding the freedom of action of a party
consenting to the terms of a treaty . . . a State which was forced by circumstances to
conclude a treaty . . . has no right afterwards to shake off the obligations of such treaty on
the ground that its freedom of action was interfered with at the time.”).
153. For a historical account of the emerging norm prohibiting coercion in treaty-
making, see Stuart S. Malawer, Imposed Treaties and International Law, 7 CAL. W. INT’L
L.J. 5, 7-8 (1977).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
force.”154
Critically though, the new rule of international law providing
for the invalidity of imposed treaties is only concerned with the
most egregious forms of coercion involving the use or threat of
military violence. During the negotiations of the Vienna
Convention, an amendment was submitted by Afro-Asian, Latin
American, and Communist states proposing that economic and
political pressures be mentioned explicitly as falling within the
concept of coercion, noting that the strangulation of a country’s
economy had become a weapon of choice of Western powers and
could be equally as coercive as the threat or use of armed force.155
However, the amendment was vigorously opposed and ultimately
defeated by the vast majority of Western states, who argued that
the standard of economic pressure lacked objective content and
that accepting economic duress as a ground of invalidity would
prejudice the stability of treaty relations.156 That view was also
supported by the ILC Rapporteurs, most notably by Waldock, who
firmly resisted the demands of postcolonial states on the ground
that extending the meaning of coercion to other forms of pressure
would leave the door to the evasion of treaty obligations wide
open.157 As a compromise between the two groups of states, a
Declaration was attached to the Vienna Convention solemnly
condemning the threat or use of pressure “in any form, whether
military, political, or economic” in the conclusion of treaties.158
However, the Declaration is drafted in broad political-declaratory
language and does not actually form part of the Vienna
Convention. It lacks legal force and, as a result, the position today
remains that coercion of states by way of economic or political
constraint, though undesirable and prejudicial to good relations
154. Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, supra note 39, art. 52.
155. U.N. Conference on the Law of Treaties, First and Second Sessions, Official
Records: Documents of the Conference, ¶¶ 449, 454, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.39/11/Add.2 (1971)
(denoting the positions of Afghanistan, India, Bolivia, Iraq, Ecuador, Syria, Cuba, Algeria,
Zambia, Ghana, Guinea, Russia, and Kenya).
156. Id. ¶ 455 (denoting the positions of the Netherlands, Australia, Portugal,
Sweden, Canada, United Kingdom, United States, and Japan).
157. Humphrey Waldock (Special Rapporteur), Second Report on the Law of
Treaties, U.N. Doc. A/CN.4/156/1963/Add.1-3 (Mar. 20, 1963).
158. Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, supra note 39, annex, Declaration
on the Prohibition of Military, Political or Economic Coercion in the Conclusion of Treaties.
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
167. North Sea Continental Shelf Cases (Ger. v. Den.; Ger. v. Neth.), Judgment,
1969 I.C.J. Rep. 3, ¶ 72 (Feb. 20) (“[E]ven without the passage of any considerable period
of time, a very widespread and representative participation in the convention might suffice
of itself, provided it included that of States whose interests were specially affected.”).
168. See INT’L LAW ASSOC., FINAL REPORT OF THE COMMITTEE: STATEMENT OF
PRINCIPLES APPLICABLE TO THE FORMATION OF GENERAL CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL
LAW 26, princ. 14 & cmt. (e) (2000) [hereinafter ILA REPORT].
169. Id.
170. North Sea Continental Shelf Cases, Dissenting Opinion of Judge Tanaka, 1969
I.C.J. Rep. 172, 176 (“We cannot evaluate the ratification of the Convention by a large
maritime country or the State practice represented by its concluding an agreement . . . as
having exactly the same importance as similar acts by a land-locked country which
possesses no particular interest in the delimitation of the continental shelf.”).
171. See Yukari Takamura, Climate Change and Small Island Claims in the Pacific,
in CLIMATE CHANGE: INTERNATIONAL LAW AND GLOBAL GOVERNANCE, VOL. 1 657, 669-70
(Oliver C. Ruppel et al. eds., 2013).
172. ILA REPORT, supra note 168 (noting that, although seemingly undemocratic,
the importance accorded to major powers is “in the nature of things” and “in touch with
political reality,” given the “scope of their interests”); see also Benedict Kingsbury,
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM
Sovereignty and Inequality, 9 EUR. J. INT’L L. 599, 609 (arguing that the doctrine “operates
mainly (but prudently, not exclusively) for the benefit of powerful states”).
173. Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, Written Statement of the
Government of the United States of America 9 (June 20, 1995), http://www.icj-cij.org/
docket/files/95/8700.pdf [http://perma.cc/Z22U-473D] (“With respect to the use of nuclear
weapons, customary law could not be created over the objection of the nuclear-weapon
States, which are the States whose interests are most specially affected”); see also Legality
of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, Advisory Opinion, 1996 I.C.J. Rep. 226, ¶ 73
(July 8) (“[T]he desire of a very large section of the international community to [prohibit]
the use of nuclear weapons [and the] emergence . . . of a customary rule specifically
prohibiting the use of nuclear weapons . . . is hampered by . . . the still strong adherence
to the doctrine of deterrence.”); Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons,
Dissenting Opinion of Vice-President Schwebel, 1996 I.C.J. Rep. 311, 312 (“This nuclear
practice is not a practice of a lone and secondary persistent objector. This is not a practice
of a pariah Government crying out in the wilderness of otherwise adverse international
opinion. This is the practice of five of the world’s major Powers, of the permanent members
of the Security Council . . . that together represent the bulk of the world’s military and
economic and financial and technological power.”).
174. Texaco Overseas Petrol. Co. v. Libya, 17 I.L.M. 1, ¶¶ 86-87 (1978) (“[T]he legal
value of the resolutions which are relevant to the present case can be determined on the
basis of circumstances under which they were adopted . . . the Tribunal notes that only
Resolution 1803 (XVII) of 14 December 1962 was supported by a majority of Member
States representing all of the various groups. By contrast, the other Resolutions mentioned
above, and in particular those referred to in the Libyan Memorandum, were supported by
a majority of States but not by any of the developed countries with market economies
which carry on the largest part of international trade.”).
Prost - FINAL.docx (Do Not Delete) 6/7/17 3:28 PM