The Philosophy of Unschooling
The Philosophy of Unschooling
KE Y THINKERS IN EDUCATION
Adam Dickerson
John Holt
The Philosophy of
Unschooling
123
SpringerBriefs in Education
Series Editor
Paul Gibbs, Middlesex University, London, UK
This briefs series publishes compact (50 to 125 pages) refereed monographs under
the editorial supervision of the Advisory Editor, Professor Paul Gibbs, Middlesex
University, London, UK. Each volume in the series provides a concise introduction
to the life and work of a key thinker in education and allows readers to get
acquainted with their major contributions to educational theory and/or practice in a
fast and easy way. Both solicited and unsolicited manuscripts are considered for
publication in the SpringerBriefs on Key Thinkers in Education series. Book
proposals for this series may be submitted to the Publishing Editor: Marianna
Pascale E-mail: Marianna.Pascale@springer.com
John Holt
The Philosophy of Unschooling
123
Adam Dickerson
Gundaroo, NSW, Australia
This Springer imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
Me schal worþe at your wille, and þat me wel lykez,
Sometimes, if it is looked at in the right way, the most trivial of remarks can reveal
a whole ethos. It was the remark in the school newsletter that struck me this way. It
was written as such communications typically are—brightly cheerful, with a faint
undertone of menacing authoritarianism. It informed me that every day I should be
reading to my children, in order to improve their literacy skills (“Be sure the
experience is enjoyable, playful, and encourages children’s active involvement;
literacy should be engaging for your children, not a chore”).
To borrow a phrase from George Orwell, that remark “reminds me, as Samuel
Butler said of a cracked church bell he heard somewhere, of the smell of a bug”
(Orwell 1970, p. 175). The person whose thought has helped me to articulate to
myself just why this remark stinks, and precisely what the source of that stink is, is
John Holt (1923–85). Holt was a critic of compulsory schooling and one of the
‘fathers’ of the modern homeschooling movement. But it was not those aspects of
his work—significant though they are—that helped me to understand just what rang
so discordantly in that remark in my children’s school newsletter.
The problem, Holt suggests, lies in that little phrase ‘in order to’; in the thought
that in education, one engages in various activities in order to produce learning. To
use the currently fashionable jargon, students in our ‘learning institutions’ engage in
‘learning activities’ in order to produce ‘learning outcomes’. The learner’s current
activity is thus conceived of as an instrument for the production of some future state
or capacity (knowledge, skill, etc.). The learner’s activity is, that is to say, viewed
as an efficient means to an end—its value lying not in the activity itself, but in the
future outcome it is intended to bring about. Debates about education work over-
whelmingly within this instrumentalist framework, concerning themselves with
vii
viii Preface
questions of the right means (e.g. pedagogical methods) and questions of the right
ends (e.g. curricular content).
This essay is written in the conviction that Holt’s work contains a philosophically
rich and important critique of our culture’s instrumentalist conception of the relation
between activity and learning. This is not something that has been well understood
about Holt’s thought. But that, perhaps, is not surprising. After all, as philosopher
Charles Travis remarks, “Sometimes an idea is so deeply engraved in the philosophic
spirit of a time that it is difficult even to see it as a target, or as threatened, in cases
where it is” (Travis 2000, p. xi). If anything is deeply engraved in the spirit of our
time, it is instrumentalism: the thought that ends can be separated from means, and
that human action must be considered as the pursuit of some desired future end that
the action is calculated to produce. Indeed, as Marx pointed out long ago, at the heart
of capitalism itself is the treatment of human activity as primarily instrumental.
Except for the lucky few, we do not work because our work is worth doing for its
own sake; we work because it is a necessary means to earning our living.
Holt’s target is the idea that learning—at least if we wish to be ‘effective’ and
‘efficient’ in procuring it—is best thought of as something to be aimed at, intentionally
and intelligently. Or, to express this target in the terms used above, it is the idea that the
best route to learning is education—where by that term is meant the undertaking of
certain activities in order to produce certain kinds of learning. In this book, I argue that
Holt offers us a coherent philosophical critique of this apparently commonsensical
thought. Stated summarily, the main points of his critique are as follows:
1. The best—most valuable, most significant—kind of learning is necessarily a
by-product of activities (such as practices of inquiry) done for their own sake—
we might say, out of a wholehearted love for the activities themselves.
2. That is, the best learning emerges (if all goes well) from autotelic activity, rather
than from activity engaged in from instrumental motives (i.e. in which the
activity is undertaken by the agent primarily as an efficient means to some
desired external end).
3. Hence, the best learning cannot be aimed at intentionally; any attempt to do so is
self-defeating.
4. The best learning involves not just growth in skills, knowledge and the like, but,
overarching these, the development of certain character traits—the virtues of the
activity in question. So, for example the virtues of inquiry include such character
traits as curiosity, wonder, patience, imagination, determination and intellectual
courage.
5. Conversely, to engage in activities in a way that is dominated by instrumental
motives tends to be destructive of the agent’s character. That is, such activity
tends to be productive of the vices of the activity in question. In the case of
inquiry, these vices include such character traits as passivity, incuriosity,
rigidity, self-distrust and intellectual cowardice.
6. Furthermore, pursuing activities from instrumentalist motives tends to be
destructive of the agent’s pleasure (joy, satisfaction) in that activity.
Preface ix
If Holt is right, then the result of this argument is that education—at least, insofar as
it is conceived of in instrumental terms—is not a good thing in the way we tend to
think it is; that what it can achieve is limited in certain deep, conceptual ways; and
that (to borrow a remark of Everett Reimer’s) very important kinds of learning
occur in spite of education, rather than because of it.
This essay could be termed an ‘analytical reconstruction’ of the argument
sketched above, and thereby of Holt’s philosophical views about the relationships
between the concepts of agency, activity, motivation and learning. In taking this
abstract focus, this essay necessarily leaves out of consideration many other
valuable aspects of his work. Holt’s books are full of empathic, richly detailed
observations of children learning (or failing to learn); they also contain much wise
discussion of the ‘right relations’ between adults and children, and practical advice
for those involved in ‘unschooling’. I hardly touch on this material. Nor do I deal
with his bravely pioneering work on children’s rights, or his broader discussions
of the political economy of schooling.
So much for what I have not done. What I have done in this essay is to take Holt
very seriously as a philosopher, who has things to say to us that we ought to listen
to, whether we are ultimately persuaded by his arguments or not. We ought to listen
to Holt precisely because his views go against the grain of our culture. They put into
question the conceptual frameworks that tend to structure our thoughts about
learning and education, and, in doing this, they help make visible the ruling prej-
udices of the time. That is, I think, just what philosophy ought to do—especially
when, as seems so obviously the case to anyone with eyes to see, “the time is sick
and out of joint”.
References
Orwell, G. (1970). Letter to Brenda Salkeld, 7 March 1935. In S. Orwell & I. Angus (Eds.), An
age like this, 1920−1940. The collected essays, journalism and letters, (pp. 174–5). London:
Penguin.
Travis, C. (2000). Unshadowed thought: Representation in thought and language, Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Contents
xi
xii Contents
4 What Is to Be Done? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 79
4.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 79
4.2 Shifting Strategies . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 81
4.3 Homeschooling . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 85
4.4 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 87
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 91
Chapter 1
Only the Experts Shall Speak or Be
Heard
A life worth living and work worth doing—that is what I want for children (and all people),
not just, or not even, something called ‘a better education’. (Holt 1990a, p. 266)1
1.1 Introduction
John Holt (1923–85) was, during the 1960s and 1970s, the most famous radical critic
of the US education system. His first book, How Children Fail (published in 1964)
was a runaway best-seller. It has been continuously in print since first publication,
it has sold well over a million copies, and has been translated into at least fourteen
languages. In it, Holt argued that,
To a very great degree, school is a place where children learn to be stupid. A dismal thought,
but hard to escape. Infants are not stupid. Children of one, two, or even three throw the whole
of themselves into everything they do. They embrace life, and devour it; it is why they learn
so fast and are such good company. Listlessness, boredom, apathy—these all come later.
Children come to school curious; within a few years most of that curiosity is dead, or at least
silent. (Holt 1982, p. 263)
How Children Fail was the first of Holt’s many books that criticised compulsory,
coercive schooling. Indeed, Holt eventually came to reject the very idea of education
itself, describing it as “learning cut off from active life” (Holt 1976, p. 3). Instead,
Holt argued, “children want to learn about the world, are good at it, and can be trusted
to do it with very little adult coercion or interference” (Holt 1981, p. 44). Hence,
the idea of making children’s lives revolve around ‘educational institutions’ is a bad
one. As he wrote in the revised edition of How Children Fail (published in 1982),
except in very rare circumstances the idea of special learning places where nothing but
learning happens no longer seems to me to make any sense at all. The proper place and best
place for children to learn whatever they need or want to know is the place where until very
recently almost all children learned it—the world itself, in the mainstream of adult life. (Holt
1982, p. 296)
For reasons I explore in this book, Holt argues that the best (most valuable, most
significant) kind of learning takes place when that learning is, as it were, a by-
product of ‘active life’. Precisely what this comes to will be analysed in the chapters
to follow, but it clearly means at least this: that such learning does not come about
from activities undertaken primarily in order to produce certain learning outcomes.
Rather, the ‘best learning’ comes from activities undertaken primarily because they
strike the agent (the ‘do-er’ of the activities) as significant, valuable, or worthwhile
in their own right.
Holt termed this approach to learning, unschooling. Since then it has also been
called ‘natural learning’ and ‘life learning’. However, as Holt himself implies in the
passage just quoted, there is an important sense in which referring to this as a special
‘approach to learning’ is misleading. This is because learning in this way—learning
as a by-product of taking part in the ‘mainstream’ of ‘active life’—is as old as
humanity. The purpose of giving it a name, and calling it unschooling, is to reclaim
some of the territory of learning from the imperial tendencies of the ‘schooling’
paradigm. That is, there is a strong tendency for discussions about learning to be
framed in terms of ‘learning activities’ undertaken in order to produce ‘learning
outcomes’, the whole business being conducted in ‘learning institutions’ staffed by
‘professional educators’—as if it were simply commonsensical and obvious that
this is how learning must occur (at least, if it is to be achieved ‘effectively’ and
‘efficiently’).
Examples of this conceptual imperialism are easy to find; here I submit just one
(taken more or less at random from the books before me). Consider this remark
from the opening to Stewart Ranson’s very influential work on ‘lifelong learning’,
Towards the Learning Society (published in 1994). It begins with this large claim:
“In periods of social transition, education becomes central to our future well-being”.
The justification for this claim is provided in the following sentence, which is as
follows:
Only if learning is placed at the centre of our experience can individuals continue to develop
their capacities, institutions be enabled to respond openly and imaginatively to periods of
change, and the difference between communities become a source of reflective understand-
ing. (Ranson 1994, p. ix)
In other words, Ranson’s argument is that because this is a period in which learning
is particularly important, education must be ‘central to our future well-being’. Here,
in the move from one sentence to the next, we witness the act of ‘education’ (with
its apparatus of institutions, policies, professional instructors, certification, and the
rest) swallowing the entire semantic field of ‘learning’. The thought that—as Holt
suggests—some very important kinds of learning might best occur outside of the
purview of educational professionals and educational institutions does not cross
Ranson’s mind.
1.1 Introduction 3
These views about how learning best takes place outside educational institutions,
along with his tireless activism, made Holt a key figure in the history of the mod-
ern homeschooling movement. Towards the end of his book, Instead of Education
(published in 1976), Holt wrote that,
What most children need is a way of escape [from schools]. One of the things people could
do who feel as I do about schools might be to help them find or make such ways. We once
had a so-called Underground Railway (strictly illegal) to help slaves escape from slavery.
Why not now a new Underground Railway, to help children escape from schools? … [W]e
have to blaze a new trail if only so that others may follow. The Children’s Underground
Railroad, like all movements of social protest and change, must begin small; it will grow
larger as more children ride it. (Holt 1976, p. 218)2
After the publication of this book, Holt was contacted by early pioneers of home-
schooling (which was, at this time, illegal in most US states). In response, Holt began
to agitate on their behalf. Using the royalties from his works, he founded the magazine
Growing Without Schooling (published from 1977 to 2001), which facilitated net-
working for homeschoolers, and contained legal advice, discussion and educational
resources. In the first issue of this magazine, Holt wrote that,
In starting this newsletter, we are putting into practice a nickel and dime theory about social
change, which is that important and lasting social change always comes slowly, and only
when people change their lives, not just their political beliefs or parties. (Holt 1999, p. 3)
In addition, Holt assisted with court cases and travelled around the US speaking
on behalf of homeschoolers. In 1978, after some important legal victories by the
homeschooling movement, Time ran a lengthy and sympathetic article on the topic,
and Holt appeared on the popular ‘Phil Donahue Show’ to argue his case. This led to
a tremendous increase in public awareness of homeschooling in the US, and marks
its shift into the mainstream of ideas about educational alternatives (cf. Gaither
2008, pp. 122–8). The last book Holt published during his lifetime, Teach Your
Own (1981), was a comprehensive discussion of homeschooling. Holt’s influence on
the homeschooling movement—particularly on its non-evangelical wing—remains
significant (Stevens 2001). What is more, in marked contrast to many of the radicals
of the 1960s and 70s, almost all of his books are still in print, decades after they were
first published.
As even this very brief summary indicates, Holt’s ideas about learning and edu-
cation have had a substantial impact on the world; but despite this, those ideas have
attracted very little scholarly attention. In the literature written and read by ‘educa-
tional theorists’ and ‘philosophers of education’ and suchlike, he is barely present.
If one turns, for example, to standard contemporary surveys of educational thought,
‘companions’ to the philosophy of education, ‘dictionaries’ of educational thought
and the like, it is rare to find Holt listed even once in the index—and careful, patient
discussion and assessment of his ideas is almost entirely absent from the enormous
educational literature.3 When Holt is mentioned at all, it is usually either with a pass-
ing sneer, or merely in reference to his historical influence on the homeschooling
movement.
What are we to make of this silence, this absence? It is worth reminding ourselves
that silencing, or rendering absent, is a standard part of scholarly practice. Scholars
choose in their day-to-day work what to write about, cite, discuss, lecture on, include
on student reading-lists. Through such acts they are simultaneously choosing what
not to mention. In so doing, judgments are being made, implicitly or explicitly,
about which views have the appropriate sort of value (as being ‘respectable’, ‘schol-
arly’, ‘serious’, ‘legitimate’, ‘credible’, etc.), and which do not. From the silence
surrounding Holt’s work, it is clear that his views have collectively been judged to
be ‘unacceptable’. That is, while it may be acceptable for a scholar to mention Holt
as being of minor historical interest in terms of his influence on the homeschooling
movement, it seems clear that his views are not seen as acceptable contributions to
contemporary debates about learning and education. There are, I suggest, two reasons
why this is so. The first reason is that, in criticising the very idea of education, Holt
is attacking some of the most cherished beliefs of our age. However, more important
than this is the second reason, which is that Holt’s works are deliberately written in
a form that rejects the implicit politics of the entire scholarly enterprise.
One reason for Holt’s neglect by scholars is surely a very simple and obvious one:
that his central claim looks, on the face of it, to be preposterous. At the very least, it
certainly flies in the face of deep-seated cultural beliefs. Holt, after all, argues that
education—in the sense of undertaking activities, the primary purpose of which is
to produce learning—is, in some important ways, a bad thing. But there is an almost
universal consensus that education is a human good in an obvious and unqualified
way, in need of neither justification nor argument. School attendance is, for exam-
ple, taken as a measure of ‘human development’ by the UNDP, and thereby classed
alongside other such obvious human goods as access to nutritious food, clean water,
medical care, basic human security, and the like. Education is even enshrined as a
human right, with Article 26 of the Universal Declaration stating that, “Everyone
has the right to education”. Governments around the world are obsessed with edu-
cation—they spend a substantial part of the national budget on their educational
systems, which is viewed as a necessary investment for achieving national prosper-
ity in a highly-competitive, ‘globalised’ world. The “belief in education for growth”
is, as Alison Wolf writes, “the great secular faith of our age. … Questioning the
3 The only monograph on Holt’s work is Meighan (2007). Although this is a clear and helpful
introduction, it does not move much beyond paraphrase.
1.2 Against Education 5
automatic value of any rise in the education budget, it seems, places one somewhere
between an animal-hater and an imbecile” (Wolf 2002, pp. x–xi).
Education is also—or so it is widely held—a sort of social cure-all. It can create
autonomous citizens and courageously critical thinkers out of the dependent, the
childish, and the easily-led; it can empower women and girls to fight patriarchal
oppression; education in tolerance will cure racism; education in civics will restore
our faded democracies; education in sustainability will avert the ecological crisis,
and so on and so forth. Thus secular saints such as Nelson Mandela can announce to
almost universal acclaim that, “Education is the most powerful weapon which you
can use to change the world”. In the face of this, what sort of monster of reaction
would dare criticise the idea of education?
Perhaps most importantly, education is apparently also the solution to poverty and
inequality. In an updated version of the Victorian admonition to ‘pull yourself up
by your own bootstraps’, the poor are told on all sides that what they need is more
education—rather than, say, policies of genuine redistribution (as those benighted
left-wingers of old had thought). It is certainly true that schooling has become a
tremendously powerful social sorting mechanism (and class marker), with certified
educational achievement, particularly from higher education, increasingly being a
condition of access to decent work (a resource that grows evermore scarce). This
social sorting is then justified by claims that more highly educated workers are more
productive, and therefore are entitled to the higher incomes they tend to receive. The
market, in other words, produces a just division of resources, with the most highly
credentialed receiving the most. This is a meritocracy, we are told, in which (in the
words of Thomas Frank), “You get what you deserve, and what you deserve is defined
by how you did in school” (Frank 2016, p. 69).
There is thus a near universal consensus, transcending political differences, about
the value and importance of education. In the face of this, it is unsurprising that
Holt’s critique has been met with silence from scholars (especially from those who
work within university schools of education). Admittedly, the claims about an edu-
cational ‘meritocracy’ are, these days, starting to look a little—how should I put
this?—shopworn. The escalating arms-race of educational credentialism is becom-
ing harder to defend as an even remotely sensible use of social resources (cf. Labaree
1997, 2010; Caplan 2018). The ‘deplorables’, long stigmatised by the lack of the
credentials possessed by their betters, are starting to make themselves heard, to the
growing discomfiture of an increasingly discredited technocratic elite. But, nonethe-
less, the fundamental faith in education as an obvious human good remains largely
undimmed.
However, this by itself is not enough to explain the scholarly silence around Holt’s
work. After all, many radical challenges to cultural orthodoxies receive a hearing in
scholarship. Hence, I suggest that there is a further reason for why Holt’s works are
largely excluded from consideration. This lies in what I will call the mode of telling
of Holt’s works. This is worth discussing at more length, as it raises a number of
important issues concerning the nature of Holt’s project (and hence, the project of
6 1 Only the Experts Shall Speak or Be Heard
this book)—the nature of the claims that he makes, and the sorts of considerations
that will count for and against them. That is, to use a bit of philosopher’s jargon, it
concerns the epistemological nature of what Holt is doing.
Holt would have been neither surprised nor, I suspect, displeased by scholars’ neglect
of his work. He self-consciously wrote as an outsider to the establishment of ‘edu-
cational experts’ and had no interest in becoming an insider. Indeed, he cordially
loathed the side of modernity that gives us the ‘rational authority’ of the certified
expert, along with its associated practices of technocracy, managerialism, bureau-
cratisation, and ‘meritocracy’. As he wrote in a response to Jerome Bruner in 1966:
I know of no more mischievous idea, nor one more strongly deserving opposition, than this
notion that, even on matters of common human experience, only the experts shall speak or
be heard. (Holt 1966)
This is a strong and consistent theme in Holt’s work. For example, twelve years later
we find him writing in a letter to Ivan Illich that,
the things which are more abstract and remote are valued much more highly, carry more
credit with them, than things which people can learn from everyday life. I say this is a highly
political decision and has highly political consequences. It diminishes the power, capacity,
and self-respect of ordinary people. (Holt 1990b, p. 217)
The ways in which Holt’s works are written reflect—or, better, enact—these deeply-
held beliefs. After all, as Martha Nussbaum remarks, a mode of telling, “makes … a
statement about what is important and what is not, about what faculties of the reader
are important for knowing and what are not” (Nussbaum 1990, p. 7). To put this
another way, a mode of telling contains a politics of knowledge. Throughout Holt’s
works we thus find a mode of telling that is directly and deliberately opposed to the
‘scholarly’ or ‘academic’ mode.
The typical traits of the scholarly mode of telling can be swiftly itemised, as
they are familiar to anyone who reads academic works. The scholarly mode tends
to be dispassionate and impersonal in tone. It usually makes essential use of a spe-
cialised vocabulary, specific to the ‘field’ or ‘discipline’. It tends to emphasise gen-
eral, abstract statements over more particular, concrete ones. The implied author, or
authorial persona, typically displays no signs of hesitation, puzzlement, or uncer-
tainty, but lays matters out with a magisterial air. I use the term ‘magisterial’ quite
deliberately. That we are dealing here with a politics of knowledge, and hence with
questions of power, is clear from the tone. Where the scholarly tone is not that of the
legislator or the judge, it is that of the prosecutor or the defending counsel: addressing
the reader as a hostile sceptic, who needs to be convinced via argument—arguments
conceived of as impersonal forces, rather than as an interaction between people.
Power, of course, has institutional frameworks around it, and texts thus locate them-
selves in such frameworks through the manner of their publication (the scholarly
1.3 Against Expertise 7
journal, the university press, etc.), their look (down to the typography and cover
design), and, perhaps most importantly, the way they place themselves within a web
of other specialised texts via an apparatus of references and notes. In short, the schol-
arly mode claims a particular power, namely, the rational authority of the certified
expert—an authority to which non-experts must defer on pain of irrationality—and
addresses itself to other certified experts in its field.
The implicit picture of knowledge at work here is obvious enough. It is a mode
of telling which suggests that experts in a given field possess a particular sort of
knowledge that is scarce and valuable. This knowledge is scarce because it is sig-
nificantly different from people’s ‘ordinary’ or ‘common-sense’ understanding of
things—that is, the sort of knowledge reached in familiar ways, through the exer-
cise of familiar faculties, by ‘ordinary people’. (For example, expert knowledge may
require competence in certain kinds of complex theory, and/or involve the application
of special methodologies in its production.) Because of its qualitative distinctness
from ‘ordinary’ understanding, this expert knowledge is typically expressible only
in a specialised, technical vocabulary, and comprehensible only to those who have
successfully passed through a certain difficult process of scholarly training (a process
which typically focuses on the ability to manipulate abstractions).
Hence, people can be publicly certified as being in possession of this scarce and
valuable knowledge (e.g., by having a Ph.D. in the field), and this entitles them to be
recognised as ‘experts’ who are then heard as speaking with particular authority about
that aspect of the world. That is to say, the experts’ words will tend to have a certain
social power, while other voices (of those lacking the appropriate certification and
recognition) will not possess that social power. So, for example, expert contributions
in a given field are more likely to sway institutional decisions and policies, while the
contributions of non-experts will tend to be silenced: ignored, ridiculed, treated as
‘non-serious’, and the like. In some cases, experts are even granted a legal monopoly
of expertise over a certain field (enforced via professional associations, licensing
laws, and the like). This deference to the experts in a given field is treated as purely
rational—after all, if they have a monopoly of knowledge about the field, then it
follows that only fools or charlatans would disagree with the experts. It also follows
from this, that with regard to the field in question experts need only pay attention to
contributions from fellow experts, and not to those made by ‘ordinary people’. When
speaking to non-experts, the ‘appeal to authority’ is the basic manoeuvre (i.e., ‘you
cannot understand the justification for this, so you have to take my credentials as a
proxy for the strength of my argument and the quality of my evidence’).
In contrast to this scholarly mode of telling, Holt’s is a rhetoric that scrupulously
avoids addressing us from a position of such expert authority. The implied author
of his texts does not address us with a claim to possess a specialised knowledge,
significantly different from our ‘ordinary’ or ‘common-sense’ understanding, and
from a grasp of which we (the non-experts) are consequently excluded. The implied
author is instead someone who invites us to stand beside him as a fellow inquirer;
one whose manner suggests he is pointing out things that we can all see, if we only
have the courage to be honest with ourselves, and exercise our ordinary capacities
for attentive observation, reflective empathy, and thoughtful understanding.
8 1 Only the Experts Shall Speak or Be Heard
Here we are a long way from a passage written in the typical scholarly mode. Holt’s
text is not discussing general, abstract truths about learning and failures to learn, but is
telling us of a particular ‘I’ confronting two particular children (‘Nell’ and ‘Martha’)
at a particular time (‘today’). Note also the use of the interrogative form—these are,
at this temporal point in the narrative, real questions, not rhetorical ones. We, the
readers, are present with Holt and with his puzzlement, and the result is a text that
often feels genuinely exploratory rather than declarative; a text in which time flows,
rather than being written in the ‘specious present’ of the scholarly treatise; a text in
which we accompany a mind engaged in the activity of inquiry, rather than listening
to someone ‘reporting back’ after the inquiry has been completed.
This use of the narrative form, with its focus on the particular and concrete over
the general and abstract, is characteristic of all of Holt’s works, from his first book
How Children Fail to his last, the posthumously published Learning All the Time
(published in 1989). The opening line of that final book is, “Once I visited a family
whose youngest child, then about five, I had not seen in several years” (Holt 1989,
p. 2). Even in the case of Holt’s most self-consciously theoretical and political work,
Freedom and Beyond, we find that, again and again, the central concepts and distinc-
tions are introduced by way of narrative episodes, and the discussion proceeds with
narratives at key junctures. As the writer George Dennison observed, in his obitu-
ary for Holt, “He never derives theory from theory, but stays as close as possible to
experience itself” (Dennison 1985, p. 8).
At this point it might be suggested that if Holt’s writings are largely in narra-
tive form, then this in itself constitutes a good reason for scholars to ignore them.
After all—such an objection might run—this means that Holt’s work consists, fun-
damentally, of nothing more than a collection of personal anecdotes (as argued, e.g.,
by Lister 1975, p. 11). Such anecdotes might make for entertaining reading, but
they cannot possibly be a substitute for the sort of rigorous and systematic empiri-
cal evidence on which a theory of learning must be erected. As the popular phrase
contemptuously puts it, “data is not the plural of anecdote”. Hence, any broad (‘the-
oretical’) claims that Holt does make on the basis of such anecdotes, cannot aspire
to anything beyond the level of cracker-barrel wisdom.
1.3 Against Expertise 9
In other words, to think that the non-scholarly mode of telling used by Holt is a good
reason for ignoring his works, is precisely to beg one of the key questions at issue.
10 1 Only the Experts Shall Speak or Be Heard
For it is to assume that learning is an area of human life in which the knowledge
worth having must be a specialised, abstract knowledge. Of course, there are areas of
human life where this assumption makes good sense. For example, if one considers,
say, theoretical chemistry, or micro-particle physics, non-experts are highly unlikely
to have anything useful to contribute. As Bernard Williams writes,
The orderly management of scientific inquiry implies that the vast majority of suggestions
which an uninformed person might mistake for a contribution to science will, quite properly,
not be taken seriously and will not find their way to discussion or publication. Very rarely
the cranky view turns out to be right, and then the scientists who ignored it are attacked for
dogmatism and prejudice. But, they can rightly reply, there was no way of telling in advance
that this particular cranky idea was to be taken seriously; the only alternative to their practice
of prejudice would be to take seriously all such suggestions, and science would grind to a
halt. (Williams 2002, p. 217)
From the perspective that views discussions of learning as the province of specialised
‘scientific inquiry’, Holt’s views look like those of a crank (as Williams puts it), and
can thus rightfully be ignored.
However, consider what becomes of this assumption if we instead hold the view, as
Holt suggests we should, that learning is ‘a matter of common experience’—like, say,
friendship or being a parent. With regard to such matters, the notion of ‘certifiable
expertise’ finds no purchase. After all, it would be a preposterous piece of scientistic
hubris to claim that one could speak more authoritatively about such matters, on the
basis of knowing some abstract ‘theory’ learned at a university. (As if there could
be ‘progress’ in our knowledge about friendship or parenting, so that we moderns,
if our practice is informed by the ‘right theory’, are now ‘better’ at being friends or
parents than people in the past were!) It would be equally preposterous to think that
any claims made about what friendship demands of one, or of how one should rightly
relate to one’s children, were admissible only if founded on ‘systematic empirical
evidence’ (perhaps derived from a sociological survey meeting appropriate statistical
measures of validity and reliability). Of course, this is not to say that if something is
‘a matter of common experience’ then all ideas about it will be equally good. Some
reflections on the matter may be rich, wise, and profound; others stupid or superficial.
But the test of the quality of those ideas will have nothing to do with whether they
are conveyed in the typical scholarly mode, by an appropriately certified ‘expert’,
rather than in Holt’s own favoured narrative form.
So, is Holt correct in his claim that learning is a ‘matter of common experience’?
It seems doubtful that there exists a simple criterion by which such matters can be
neatly demarcated from matters in which certifiable expertise makes sense. This book
as a whole is an exploration of Holt’s ideas, and will have to speak for itself as an
argument for the value of his work. However, it is worth very briefly sketching two
considerations in favour of his viewpoint.
First, one thing shared by those ‘matters of common experience’ mentioned above
is that they are, in various respects, ethically inflected. That is to say, ideas of friend-
ship and parenting deeply involve ideas about the good and the bad, the right and the
wrong. As will be discussed in detail in the chapters to follow, Holt argues that the
concept of learning is similarly ethically inflected in its content. It has, as we shall see,
1.3 Against Expertise 11
close connections to such concepts as ‘the worthwhile’, ‘the valuable’, ‘the signifi-
cant’, ‘the worthy-of-being-desired’, as well as significant links with various virtues,
and with love. Hence, Holt’s works are, in an important sense, works in ethics—
deeply concerned with issues of what he would term ‘right relations’ (between adult
and child; between learner and the world; between the self and its own activity).
One of the noteworthy features of ethical concepts is that the notion of expertise
makes no sense in relation to them (cf. Gaita 2004, pp. 100–9). It makes good
sense to delegate questions about, say, how to design a power-plant, a bridge, or
a jet engine, to those who are certified experts in such matters. But there are no
‘ethical experts’ to whom I can appropriately delegate my ethical decision-making,
or who can legitimately claim a monopoly of serious (non-cranky) discussion of
such matters. Of course this does not mean that there cannot be investigations of
various kinds into ethical matters; but it does mean that such investigations will not
look much like the ‘scientific inquiry’ discussed by Bernard Williams in the passage
quoted above.
This leads me to the second reason for doubting the idea that discussion of learning
should be restricted to appropriately certified experts. In order to legitimately claim a
monopoly of ‘serious’ discussions about learning, such experts would need to possess
a specialised knowledge or expertise about learning. This specialised knowledge
would need to meet the following criteria:
(i) It could not be knowledge already possessed (implicitly or explicitly) by ‘ordi-
nary’ people (for then the experts’ claim to possess a monopoly of that knowl-
edge would fall to the ground).
(ii) This knowledge would have to cover, if not all cases of human learning, at least
a very wide variety of them. It would, in other words, have to take the form of
a general theory of learning.
(iii) This knowledge would, at the same time as being very general, also have to
be empirically applicable. So, for example, those possessing this knowledge
would be able to design ‘learning experiences’ that were superior in delivering
‘learning outcomes’ compared to those designed by people who lacked this
knowledge.
Knowledge meeting all these criteria would be a genuine ‘learning science’, with
teaching being the ‘applied science’.
Various educational theorists concerned to bolster the (always shaky) professional
status of teaching have taken this picture very seriously indeed. John Darling, for
example, writing of UK government attempts to wrest control of the school curricu-
lum from the hands of the teaching profession, complains that, “Where a professional
group has manifestly acquired a sophisticated critical understanding about X, it is
hard to deny its right to exercise authoritative influence over how X is conducted”
(Darling 1994, p. 110). But one must ask, have teachers and educational theorists
manifestly acquired a sophisticated critical understanding of learning? Darling’s
anxiety that this acquisition is less than manifest betrays itself in the proliferation of
meaningless value-claiming terms—and with good reason. As Holt himself would
argue, being a good teacher is not a matter of possessing certified expertise in some
12 1 Only the Experts Shall Speak or Be Heard
The theories stand in the way of our understanding. I think Holt would have been
deeply sympathetic to this remark, with its echo of Wittgenstein. Holt fought hard
for his first book to be entitled ‘How children fail’ against his publisher’s preference
that it be called ‘Why children fail’ (Holt 1990c, p. 123). Asking ‘Why?’ in this
context is the wrong question. It is to ignore the details of what lies before us—as
if we already knew what it is for children to succeed or fail at learning—and jump
1.3 Against Expertise 13
straight to causal theorising. Asking ‘How?’, on the other hand, is to focus first on the
careful observation and scrupulous description of the phenomena—precisely what
Winch suggests we need when it comes to understanding the nature of learning. As
Holt writes in his second book, How Children Learn, “My aim in writing [this book]
is not primarily to persuade educators and psychologists to swap new doctrines for
old, but to persuade them to look at children, patiently, repeatedly, respectfully …”
(Holt 1983, p. 271).
A number of the issues I have touched on above will be returned to, and elaborated
upon, in the chapters to follow, but let us, for the time being, draw this discussion
to a close. I have suggested that a key reason for the scholarly silence around Holt’s
works—despite their very real impact on the world—is their mode of telling. That is,
his works are written in deliberate opposition to the scholarly mode and its epistemo-
logical, ethical, and political presuppositions. At this point two obvious objections
raise their heads. The first is that this book, in which I analyse Holt’s ideas, is written
in the scholarly mode—so is that not inconsistent, or at least in tension, with what
I have just said about the nature of Holt’s works? There is a certain truth to this
objection; and I would be the first to concede that in a ‘translation’ like this there is a
loss. However, I hope that there will also be gains—in helping to make Holt’s works
visible to people to whom, at present, they are invisible. In the words of Stanley
Cavell, “Criticism is always an affront, and its only justification lies in its usefulness,
in making its object available to just response” (Cavell 1976, p. 46). Readers can
judge for themselves whether they think this book was useful in that way.
This leads me to the second objection, which is that, in ‘translating’ Holt in this
way, am I not making him out to be a purveyor of precisely one of those ‘general
theories of learning’ that I criticised above? This objection is misguided. The ana-
lytical account that is given in the following chapters is a work in philosophy—not,
for example, in empirical psychology. Philosophy, as I understand it, is not a tech-
nical, ‘scientific’ discipline that leads to ‘results’ and ‘findings’; it is (in the words
of Talbot Brewer) “a focussed effort to examine one’s own concerns, bring them to
articulacy, and see whether they can stand up to reflective scrutiny” (Brewer 2009,
p. 10). For this reason, philosophy is the possession of all people willing to engage
in it, not the specialised province of credentialed experts in universities. Hence, the
discussion of Holt’s ideas developed in the chapters to come has no grand empirical
theory of learning to offer, and does not rely on causal claims supposedly established
through specialised experimental methods. Rather, it appeals only to reasoning and
to conceptual resources that lie ready to hand. In this way it is, I hope, open to all
comers.
1.4 Conclusion
As remarked, I have written this book to recuperate, clarify, and explore Holt’s views
about the nature of learning and education. In order to do this, the book undertakes
what could be termed an ‘analytical reconstruction’ of the argument that lies at the
14 1 Only the Experts Shall Speak or Be Heard
ground-floor of Holt’s thinking. As discussed above, like Holt the discussion will
treat learning as a ‘matter of common understanding’, in that what is needed in order
to understand its nature is not causal theorising, but rather an approach that examines
and assesses the conceptual resources already present (even if only inarticulately)
in our own understanding. That is to say, what is needed is a philosophical analysis
of Holt’s account of learning, and of the accompanying family of concepts such
as desire, motivation, activity, virtue, and pleasure. That analysis is what this book
attempts to provide.
In approaching matters this way, the book thus treats Holt’s views of learning and
education as essentially static, rather than dynamic. This is not just a simplification
made for the sake of making exposition easier. Holt had a long career of writing
and activism, and of course a number of his views shifted in significant ways over
that period. However, all of his writing is ultimately animated by one and the same
underlying account of learning. Holt certainly expressed this view with greater clarity
and articulacy over time, but, nonetheless, it remains, in its fundamentals, the same
from How Children Fail until his final work. Hence, my explication does not follow
the historical development of Holt’s thought, but draws on his works in whatever
order best suits the needs of my analysis.
By viewing his core ideas as static in this way, this book does not attempt to
relate Holt’s views to their changing historical context, and the tactical demands of
the various debates and polemics into which they were inserted. Such an approach
would require, at the very least, placing his writings in relation to the rise and fall of the
‘counter-culture’ and the New Left in the USA over the 1960s and 1970s. This in turn
would mean reading Holt in the company of important works by other radical critics
of education of the period, such as Goodman (1971), Illich (1971, 1981), Dennison
(1969), Herndon (1965, 1971), Reimer (1971), Postman and Weingartner (1971), and
Kohl (1971). It would also involve examining systematically how his ideas relate to
earlier bodies of thought such as that of Deweyan progressivism, anarchism, and
the American tradition of ‘self-reliance’. A little of this work has been done (see
the discussions of Holt in Miller 2002, Chap. 3; Olson 2011, pp. 27–32; Bickman
2003, pp. 142–5) but it is not the approach that this book will take. My aim here is
to provide a clear articulation of Holt’s underlying thought, rather than a detailed
tracing of lines of historical influence.
Viewed analytically, Holt’s body of work can be seen as composed of three com-
ponents, as follows.
[1] There is a positive or constructive account of what the best (most valuable, most
significant) sort of learning is, and the conditions conducive to such learning.
[2] Based on this positive account, there is a critique of instrumentalist practice in
education, arguing that the structural features of that practice are such that it is,
intrinsically, in tension with, or hostile to, the sort of ‘best learning’ analysed
in [1].
[3] Various practical strategies are discussed for mitigating the problems with edu-
cation analysed in [2], and for achieving the sort of ‘best learning’ analysed in
[1].
1.4 Conclusion 15
In many of Holt’s works, the practical strategies (the third component) is where
the main focus lies. This is unsurprising, given that he wrote not for the sake of
theorising, but primarily as a form of activism—to change people’s lives. This is also
where the key shifts in his thought occurred over time, as he moved from advocating
school reform and learner-centred pedagogy, to a radical rejection of compulsory
education and advocacy of homeschooling. However, the main focus of this book
will be on articulating, analysing, and clarifying Holt’s positive account of learning
(the first component), and his critique of education (the second component). These
will be treated together, as much of Holt’s positive account is expressed by way of
his critique (that is, it is often in the reasons he uses to justify his critique that we
find his positive account).
The plan of the rest of this book is as follows. In the following chapter (Chap. 2) I
give an outline of Holt’s positive account of learning, and how it functions to support
his critique of education. Next (Chap. 3), I fill in this picture by way of considering
some objections that are likely to be raised against it. Finally, (Chap. 4) I briefly
consider Holt’s suggested practical strategies in the light of the analysis developed
in the previous chapters.
References
Armstrong, T. (2013). Cracker barrel writing. In P. Farenga & C. Ricci (Eds.), The legacy of John
Holt (pp. 41–6). Medford, MA: Holt GWS.
Bickman, M. (2003). Minding American education: Reclaiming the tradition of active learning.
New York: Teachers College Press.
Brewer, T. (2009). The retrieval of ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Caplan, B. (2018). The case against education: Why the education system is a waste of time and
money. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Carr, D. (2004). Rival conceptions of practice in education and teaching. In J. Dunne & P. Hogan
(Eds.), Education and practice: Upholding the integrity of teaching and learning (pp. 102–15).
Oxford: Blackwell.
Cavell, S. (1976). Must we mean what we say? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Darling, J. (1994). Child-centred education and its critics. London: Paul Chapman.
Dennison, G. (1969). The lives of children: The story of the First Street School. New York: Random
House.
Dennison, G. (1985). Statement. Growing Without Schooling, 48, 8. Available at
https://issuu.com/patfarenga/docs/gws-48. Accessed April 2019.
Frank, T. (2016). Listen, liberal: Or, whatever happened to the party of the people? New York:
Metropolitan Books.
Gaita, R. (2004). Good and evil: An absolute conception (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.
Gaither, M. (2008). Homeschool: An American history. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Goodman, P. (1971). Compulsory miseducation. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Herndon, J. (1965). The way it spozed to be. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Herndon, J. (1971). How to survive in your native land. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Holt, J. (1964). How children fail. New York: Pitman.
Holt, J. (1966). On education: An exchange between Jerome Bruner and John Holt. The New York
Review of Books, 12 May.
Holt, J. (1970). What do I do Monday? New York: E. P. Dutton and Co.
16 1 Only the Experts Shall Speak or Be Heard
It is love, not tricks and techniques of thought, that lies at the heart of all true learning.
(Holt 1983, p. 303)
2.1 Introduction
This chapter is the heart of the book. It analyses the conceptual structure that under-
pins Holt’s account of learning and his critique of education. One way to view this
analysis is as the solution to an interpretative problem. After all, the exceptional
clarity and plainness of Holt’s prose can hide the fact that his central claims about
learning and education are, prima facie, rather puzzling. To bring out this inter-
pretative problem, I begin by considering the contrast Holt draws in the following
passage. This is quoted from the opening chapter of Instead of Education; Holt sees
fit to repeat it verbatim five years later in Teach Your Own, so it can be considered
as being, as it were, a canonical text.
This is a book in favor of doing—self-directed, purposeful, meaningful life and work— and
against ‘education’—learning cut off from active life and done under pressure of bribe or
threat, greed and fear. (Holt 1976, p. 3)
Replacing the polemical terms ‘bribe’ and ‘threat’ with more colourless language,
Holt is thus defining education as activities, deliberately designed to produce learn-
ing, which the agent is primarily motivated to undertake by incentives and/or disin-
centives that are external to the activity. That is, the activity is not undertaken by the
agent because it strikes her as valuable, significant, or worth doing in its own right,
but because it is a means of avoiding some disincentive (‘threat’) and/or achieving
some incentive (‘bribe’). In contrast, what Holt calls doing consists of activities that
the agent undertakes precisely because they do strike the agent as worth doing in
their own right; in this way, such activities are genuinely self-directed.
It is worth emphasising how Holt’s definition of ‘education’ focuses on the moti-
vational or evaluative outlook of the learner (the ‘agent’ referred to above). Contrast
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019 17
A. Dickerson, John Holt, SpringerBriefs on Key Thinkers
in Education, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18726-2_2
18 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
this focus, for example, with that implied in R. S. Peter’s well-known remark that
the concept of education “implies that something worth while is being or has been
intentionally transmitted in a morally acceptable manner” (Peters 1966, p. 25). The
notion of intentional transmission takes for granted what could be termed a ‘top-
down’ perspective on education. It is the perspective of the teacher, the curriculum
designer, the educational policy maker; for it is they who intend to transmit learning
via educational activities. Holt’s definition, on the other hand, focuses our attention
on how the activities appear from the perspective of the agent—the child, the learner,
the student—who is undertaking those activities.
This thus begins to explain the importance of the concept of the learner’s freedom
for Holt’s account. Freedom is, as it were, a test for discovering the kind of motivation
that is moving the agent to undertake the activity. It is a way of posing this question:
would the agent continue to undertake a particular activity if she were free—that is to
say, in the absence of external incentives and disincentives (‘bribes’ and ‘threats’)?
If so, then the activity in itself is sufficient to motivate the agent; that is, the activity
strikes the agent as valuable or significant enough to be worth doing in its own right.
We can say, then, that education is effectively defined by Holt as the undertaking
of ‘learning activities’ that would not be undertaken by the agent if she were free
from the influence of external incentives and disincentives. What are we to make
of this, qua definition? It is clear that it is not intended ‘analytically’—that is, to
provide necessary and sufficient conditions for capturing all uses of the English word
‘education’. After all, this word can be used in a very broad way, where it is virtually
synonymous with ‘learning’. It can also be used much more narrowly, to refer to
particular activities that occur in institutions officially designated as ‘educational’,
under the guidance of those officially recognised as professional educators (as in ‘I
received my education at Eton and Oxford’).
In giving his polemical definition of education, Holt is not, of course, attempting
to capture the ‘logical essence’ of the concept in some ‘value-free’ way; rather, he
is using it to draw our attention to a pervasive empirical feature of the actual prac-
tice of many of our educational institutions. This pervasive—and, I would suggest,
obvious—feature is simply this: typically, the ‘learning activities’ that go on under
the auspices of these institutions are not such that the agent (child, learner, student)
would be motivated to undertake those activities, in the absence of external incentives
and/or disincentives. That is, typically, the activities in themselves would not strike
the agent as sufficiently valuable or significant enough to be worth doing.
Those who find this claim about our educational institutions to be an unfair car-
icature, should consider the following. Think of all the ‘learning activities’ that go
on, year after year, at all levels of the education system—the books read, the class
discussions had, the essays and papers written, the worksheets filled out, the exams
taken. Then ask yourself, how much of this activity would be undertaken by students
in the absence of external incentives and disincentives (‘bribe’ and ‘threat’, as Holt
puts it)? That is, if there were no marks, gold stars, places on the Honour role, high
school certificates or university degrees to be gained by undertaking the activity;
if there was no potential of the humiliation of a failing grade, a teacher’s anger, a
parent’s disappointment, if one did not undertake the activity. The answer, I suggest,
2.1 Introduction 19
is obvious. In the absence of external incentives and disincentives, very, very little
of that activity would be undertaken: the exams would not be sat; the essays would
largely remain unwritten; almost all the worksheets would be left blank.
We now need to examine just what Holt thinks is wrong with this situation. After
all, an easy retort to having this pervasive feature of our educational institutions
pointed out would simply be: So what? For, it might be said, people—and children
in particular—often need external incentives and disincentives to encourage them to
do what is in their long-term interest. Holt’s account of what is wrong with education
(by which is meant, that pervasive feature of actual educational practice) is where
matters become both more interesting and more puzzling.
For a start, it is important to emphasise that his objection to education is not simply
the fact that it denies the learner self-direction (freedom, autonomy). That is, Holt is
not giving a libertarian critique of education. This can be seen, for example, in the
following important summary statement:
The main reason for giving young people self-direction, autonomy, and choice in their
learning is … quite simply because that is how people learn best. Everyone. All the time.
(Holt 1972, p. 4)
Note the structure of Holt’s reasoning in this passage. Holt’s argument does not
terminate with an appeal to the supposedly self-evident value of ‘self-direction,
autonomy, and choice’, as it would if he were arguing on libertarian grounds. Rather,
he states that such freedom is important because it is a condition that people require
in order to ‘learn best’.
Holt’s critique is thus the paradoxical-sounding claim that education is bad for
learning. To spell this out a little more precisely, his claim is as follows. The use
of external incentives and disincentives to motivate agents to undertake ‘learning
activities’ is a bad thing. It is a bad thing because acting from this sort of motivation
is hostile to, or in tension with, acquiring the best (most significant; most valuable)
kind of learning. (Just what that learning is, and what is ‘best’ about it, is of course
one of the central topics of this chapter; but, for the time being, I will leave its nature
unspecified.) Indeed, Holt goes further than this. Not only is education hostile to the
acquisition of the best sort of learning, it in fact tends to be damaging to the agent
qua inquirer. As Holt famously writes in How Children Fail, “To a very large degree,
school is a place where children learn to be stupid” (Holt 1982, p. 263). (And just
why Holt argues this will be another of this chapter’s topics.)
To return to the initial contrast with which this discussion began, the way to
acquire the best sort of learning is, Holt argues, not education but doing. That is, the
best learning is acquired through what, as we have seen, he variously describes as
“self-directed, purposeful, meaningful life and work”, “active life”, and “work worth
doing”. These are activities which are undertaken because they strike the agent as
significant, valuable, or worthwhile in themselves (or, in their own right). Here, the
phrase ‘in themselves’ means partly that those activities are undertaken independently
of external incentives or disincentives—that is, they would be undertaken even if the
agent were ‘free’. However, it also means that these activities are not undertaken in
order to produce learning—that is, they are not undertaken as ‘learning activities’.
20 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
1 Thegeneral idea of ‘states that are essentially by-products’ of activity, I take from the superb
analysis in Elster (1983), Chap. 2.
2.1 Introduction 21
conceptual links between activity, agency, and learning. In the later sections of the
chapter, I then return to the texts with this analytical model in hand, to show how it
can illuminate his claims.
These are deeply Aristotelian thoughts. For both Aristotle and Holt, the human good
does not involve acquiring a bundle of capacities (skills, knowledge), but from actual-
ising those potentialities in activities—in particular, in activities that are worth doing
in themselves. Hence, as Holt puts, any ‘life worth living’ will, crucially, involve
‘work worth doing’, where this means (as the passage quoted above emphasises),
worth doing for its own sake, and not simply because it is a means of acquiring
such external goods as money, power, or status. In more Aristotelian terms, the good
(eudaimon) life is made up of autotelic activity, rather than instrumental activity.
In thinking through the implications of this view of the human good for learning
and education, Holt is responding to the deep connections between concepts like
motivation, agency, and activity. In the Nichomachean Ethics, Aristotle gives us a
rich account of precisely those connections, and that work thus provides important
resources for making sense of Holt’s views.
I will begin by focussing on the nature of activities; a term that has so far been
left unanalysed. A rough-and-ready distinction can be drawn between two kinds of
human activity. On the one hand there are activities in which there are not multiple
dimensions of excellence in that activity. These are, for example, simple activities
that are fully rule-governed or ‘algorithmic’ by nature, and which are therefore either
done correctly or incorrectly. Consider such activities as counting whole numbers;
making simple arithmetical calculations; giving memorised answers to standardised
questions; spelling words correctly. Or, to take another sort of example, they are
22 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
For these reasons, whilst simple activities may be done mechanically, without
thought, but perfectly competently for all that, practices require—for excellence—a
sustained quality of attention and focus from the agent.
This description of practices may sound formidably abstract, so let me illustrate
what is meant by way of Holt’s own favourite example of a practice: that of learning
to play a musical instrument. Assuming all goes well, as I engage in this practice
my capacities to make music with that instrument improve and expand. A crucial
aspect of this expansion is that, as my capacities evolve, the standards I can apply
to my own music-making become richer and more sophisticated—things become
hearable to me in my own music, which before I had been deaf to. Where once I was
concerned with such gross issues as hitting the correct notes and having a regular
beat, I find myself now able to judge subtler issues of interpretation—Have I attacked
this opening note with appropriate verve? Am I right to play this passage in a stately
manner, or does the piece require just a touch of swing to the rhythm? The only way
to search for the ‘right’ interpretation of a musical passage (that is, an interpretation
that excels in at least some of the many dimensions of musical excellence) is to play
2.2 Aristotelian Excursus, Part I: Activities 23
that passage—to engage in the practice—and it is only through engaging with the
practice that my capacities in that practice can be deepened and extended. In sum, my
grasp of the internal goods of making music on the instrument in question is achieved,
dialectically, through the activity of playing itself, and through progressively striving
for excellence in that playing.
There are many examples of practices; they are, to use Holt’s phrase, what any
‘work worth doing and life worth living’ will involve. I will not attempt an exhaustive
list, but at a minimum they include: all the varied practices of music-making, of
dance, and of art; the skilled crafts and trades—working with wood, metal, textiles,
and so on; the varied practices of design and architecture; work in medicine and in
law; sports and athletics.2 Crucial to my discussion here is that there are also many
varied practices of inquiry. There are general forms of this—as it were, the everyday
varieties of inquiry we use to find out information, seek explanations, strive for
understanding, and so on. And then there are the various highly specialised forms of
such inquiry, which we know as disciplines such as chemistry, physics, mathematics,
history, philosophy, sociology, and so on and so forth.
I am not claiming that there is a crisp and context-invariant distinction between
practices and non-practices (and it is not essential for the purposes of this discussion
that there be such a distinction). However, practices are distinguished by their posses-
sion of many-dimensioned standards of excellence, and this fact provides us with a
rough-and-ready linguistic test for identifying them. We can ask: Can a wide variety
of adverbs of excellence be applied to a performance of an activity, or would such
application be, in some way, ridiculous, senseless, or absurd? That is, when it comes
to the excellent performance of some practice, we can talk about how it was done
rigorously, carefully, imaginatively, creatively, with integrity, diligently, and so on
and so forth (with practices often having, in addition, their own extensive specialised
vocabularies for standards of excellence). However, with respect to non-practices,
applying such adverbs typically results in absurdity—consider, if you will, the idea
of praising some given episode of tooth-brushing or shoe-lace tying with a similar
range of adverbs.
Now, this linguistic test in turn points to the fact that the excellent performance of
practices is intimately tied to an agent’s character in a way that the performance
of simple activities is not. In order to engage in a practice and reach successfully
for its standards of excellence (on a regular basis) one requires certain character
traits. Or, to put this another way, an agent who can regularly produce excellent
2 The practice of motorcycle repair deserves an honorable mention here, as it has inspired at least two
works of exceptional quality (Pirsig 2004; Crawford 2010), whose themes overlap in various ways
with the argument developed here. Two other magnificent books exploring the nature of practices
are Sennett (2008) and Sudnow (2001).
24 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
The virtues of a practice are, in part, like a capacity to grasp, or hold steadily in
view, the internal goods of a practice (or, equivalently, the internal standards of
excellence of that practice). However, the metaphor of vision here is, in some respects,
misleading, for it implies that one could ‘see’ the internal goods of the practice and
yet choose not to pursue them. However, having the virtues of the practice entails
grasping those internal goods as goods—that is, not as ends that ‘somebody’ could
have, but as ends that I (the agent) actually have. Furthermore, because those internal
goods are only grasped through actually engaging in the practice and aiming at
excellence in it (that, after all, is what makes them internal goods), the capacity to
‘see’ the goods is thereby a capacity to engage in the practice in pursuit of them.
The virtues of a given practice thus require, as necessary concomitants, whatever
various physical capacities, skills, and knowledge that striving for excellence in that
particular practice requires. So, for example, in order to strive for excellence in
playing the cello, the agent requires certain capacities for making complex physical
movements with arms and fingers, certain auditory capacities, a functioning memory,
and so on and so forth; she also requires various skills in reading music, in tuning
the instrument, in keeping time, and so on and so forth. However, although such
capacities, skills, and knowledge are necessary for striving for excellence in the
practice, simply having a ‘bundle’ of them is not sufficient. It is the possession of
the virtues of the practice—or, equivalently, the agent’s grasp of the internal goods
of that practice—that gives order, unity and point to the exercise of all these varied
capacities, skills, and knowledge. Or, to put this another way, the virtues allow us
to see the ends, and then deploy the required skills and knowledge appropriately in
order to serve those ends. That is, it is the agent’s active grasp of the standards of
excellence of the practice that allow her to determine precisely how and when such
capacities, skills, knowledge need to be drawn on or mobilised. Without the virtues
playing this executive, unifying, role, all these capacities, skills, and knowledge are
blind.
It is Aristotle, in the Nichomachean Ethics, who provides what is still the best guide
to the conceptual connections that link practices, their internal goods, and the virtues.
In that great work, Aristotle’s focus is not (as mine is here) on particular practices
2.3 Aristotelian Excursus, Part II: Virtues 25
(such as music, skilled craft, forms of inquiry, etc.), but on what he sees as the practice
that overarches and unifies all of them: the practice of living a good (eudaimon) life
for a human being. The virtues (or, in Aristotle’s Greek, arête) required for excellence
in that overarching practice are the ethical virtues, or what we might call the virtues
simpliciter, such as courage, temperance, justice and practical wisdom. However,
what concerns me here is not these overarching ethical virtues, but the more small-
scale virtues of particular practices. The question of how these small-scale virtues
relate to the over-arching virtues (for example, how intellectual courage relates to
courage simpliciter) is an important topic, but beyond the scope of this discussion.
Although the word ‘virtue’ has the right historical lineage—and is the word used
in the philosophical literature on this topic—in everyday English it has unfortunately
now a somewhat priggish air about it. However, there is nothing priggish about the
particular qualities of character that it encompasses. My focus here—given that this
is a discussion about learning and education—is particularly on the virtues of inquiry,
or what have been termed the epistemic or intellectual virtues.3 I have no pretences to
offer a systematic typology (nor is it clear what the value of that would be), but these
epistemic virtues include such character traits as the following: curiosity, inquisitive-
ness, reflectiveness, wonder; attentiveness, carefulness, perceptiveness, attention to
detail, rigour; fairness, consistency, objectivity, impartiality, fair-mindedness, open-
mindedness; honesty, integrity, humility, self-awareness; creativity, imaginativeness,
adaptability; determination, patience, courage, resilience, diligence, tenacity (cf. the
table given in Baehr 2011, p. 21). Of course, precisely what these virtues come to
varies from practice to practice—so that possessing them with regard to one practice
of inquiry is no guarantee of possessing them with regard to a different practice. For
example, an agent may be highly imaginative in constructing mathematical proofs,
but this does not mean that she is therefore imaginative in, say, constructing historical
narratives.
So far we have discussed only the virtues of a practice, but opposed to these are
also the vices of a practice. Put simply, whilst the character traits needed to pursue
excellence in a given practice are the virtues required by that practice, the states of
character that prevent, or stand in the way of, excellent practice, are the vices of that
practice. To put this another way, if the virtues are the capacity, as it were, to keep in
view the internal goods of a practice, then the vices are a kind of blindness to those
goods. The virtues are thus those character traits in virtue of which the agent is able to
resist various temptations that militate against excellence in a practice, and the vices
are those character traits in virtue of which the agent is susceptible to those temp-
tations. So, for example, if I possess the virtues of diligence and attention to detail
(in a particular practice) this means, in part, that I am able to resist temptations to be
lazy, slapdash, inattentive, or sloppy in performing that practice; to fail to resist such
temptations on a regular basis is, precisely, for me to possess the vices of carelessness,
laziness, sloppiness, and so forth. Other intellectual vices include such character traits
as incuriosity, imperceptiveness, inattention, unfairness, inconsistency, dishonesty,
3 The
best discussion of intellectual virtues in the literature is Baehr (2011); see also Roberts and
Wood (2007); Hookway (2003).
26 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
It is possible to mount an argument that the virtues and vices of practices also have
this sort of logical structure. For example, paying just the right amount of attention
to detail is a virtue, whilst paying too little attention to detail is the vice of sloppiness,
and paying too much attention to detail is the vice of obsessionality or perfectionism.
Aristotle’s thesis of the ‘mean’ plays no role in the argument developed here, but it
does help to draw attention to a crucially important point: that the virtues of practice
involve an indefinitely flexible openness or sensitivity to context. That is, excellence
in a practice cannot be reduced to a matter of following explicit rules in an algorithmic
fashion. For example, there is no set of precise rules that could be stated such that,
following those rules, one would produce an excellent example of a blues song, or a
cello concerto, or a piece of abstract art. Thinking of the example from the previous
paragraph, how much attention to detail is ‘just the right amount’—avoiding either
sloppiness (too little) or obsessionality (too much)? Clearly enough, the only general
answer that can be given to this is: it depends (on the context). This is another way
of putting the point that one cannot learn excellence in a practice by learning rules
in abstracto, but only by engaging in the practice itself, in a way that aims at the
internal goods of that practice (even if such goods are, as they always are at first, only
dimly or inchoately grasped). Where ‘rules’ are stated, they can be at most ‘rules of
thumb’ rather than being constitutive of the standards of excellence in the practice.
Such rules of thumb are useful in some cases for orienting a beginner towards the
internal goods, but learning such rules cannot be a substitute for a vision of those
goods.
It is for this reason that Aristotle tells us that the ethical virtues demand practical
wisdom (phronēsis) in their possessor. He famously defines a virtue as,
a state concerned with choice, lying in a mean relative to us, this being determined by reason
and in the way in which the person of practical wisdom would determine it. (1106b36-1107a2;
my emphasis)
What is important to note here is how Aristotle does not define ethical choice by
appeal to any explicit, stateable, universal rules, but by appeal to how a person
of practical wisdom would choose in the particular case. As he writes elsewhere
in the Nichomachean Ethics, “the agents themselves must in each case consider
2.3 Aristotelian Excursus, Part II: Virtues 27
what is appropriate to the occasion” (1104a7–8), for “the decision depends upon the
particular facts and on perception” (1126b4–5). After all,
any one can get angry—that is easy—or give or spend money; but to do this to the right
person, to the right extent, at the right time, with the right aim, and in the right way, that is
not for every one. (1109a26–8)
Practical wisdom is precisely the capacity to respond in the right way to the par-
ticulars of a situation—to know what ‘just the right amount’ is in a given context.
Hence, as G. H. Von Wright remarks,
virtues have an essential and peculiar connexion with particulars. … [T]he path of virtue
is never laid out in advance. It is for the man of virtue to determine where it goes in the
particular case. (Von Wright 1963, p. 145)
We develop the virtues of a practice by engaging in that practice and striving for
excellence in it. If things go well for us, that is; for there are no guarantees here.
Perhaps we find we simply cannot sustain the sort of focus that excellence in the
practice demands, or are unable to develop the particular skills needed to progress
further in it. But, with this important caveat noted, the general schema is as follows:
We begin with a crude and inchoate view of the internal goods of the practice, and
engage in the practice in the light of that view—striving towards the internal standards
of excellence of the practice as we see them. If things go well for us, through such
striving our view of the internal goods becomes a little clearer, a little more detailed,
and hence a little more demanding. And, in doing this, we are engaging in the practice
in the way demanded by its virtues, and are thereby developing those virtues—we
are, that is, developing the character traits demanded by excellence in that particular
practice.
As a way of beginning to draw this account back towards Holt, it is important
to emphasise one particular aspect of this account of the virtues of practice. The
virtues (and, for that matter, the vices) are related to the agent’s will. As was pointed
out above, the virtues are not the grasp of the internal goods of a practice in some
28 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
Hence, as Aristotle writes, with regard to a skill “he who errs willingly is preferable,
but in … the virtues he is the reverse” (1140b23-5). That is, if I make a deliberate
error in applying a skill, this does not reflect on the level of my skill in the way that
my making a genuine (non-deliberate) error would. But in the case of virtues, if I
deliberately flout what a virtue requires, then this casts doubt on whether I in fact
possess the virtue at all (cf. Foot 2002, pp. 7–8).
To illustrate this point, consider the following example. Suppose that a research
scientist omits certain data from a data set, which omission enables her to draw a
conclusion (e.g., that a particular herbicide does not cause cancer) that she knows
will be looked on favourably by an industry where she has hopes of being employed
profitably as a consultant. If, upon this omission being pointed out, she retorts that
she omitted that data deliberately rather than accidentally, this may well protect her
claim to be skilled in data analysis, but it severely undermines any claims she has
to possess intellectual virtues such as integrity, honesty, objectivity, impartiality, and
rigour. To reiterate, this is because such virtues are not skills (capacities to do certain
things successfully), but involve the agent actually wanting to strive for certain goods.
As we shall see, this point about the virtues is the insight at the heart of Holt’s
thought: to grasp what excellence in a practice demands of one is never a ‘merely
cognitive’ achievement. That is, it is not as if the agent could know this, but find this
knowledge motivationally inert. Rather, as discussed above, the grasp of the internal
goods of a practice is simultaneously cognitive and motivational or evaluative. (Or,
more accurately, it demonstrates the conceptual crudity of the idea that there is an
easy distinction to be had between the ‘cognitive’ and the ‘conative’ or motivational.)
To put this another way, excellence in an activity requires a passionate attention to
the practice—a love for what one is doing. In exactly the same way (and as Aristotle
2.3 Aristotelian Excursus, Part II: Virtues 29
discusses at length in the Nichomachean Ethics), one cannot know in some ‘merely
cognitive’ way what being a good friend requires of one (‘I know what I should do,
but I can’t really be bothered to do it’)—this knowledge must also be passionate.
This, as we shall see, is the profound truth of Holt’s remark that, “It is not subject
matter that makes some learning more valuable than others, but the spirit in which
the work is done” (Holt 1982, p. 293). For ‘the spirit in which the work is done’
is not like icing on a cake—something super-added, which does not change what it
overlays—rather, that ‘spirit’ plays a constitutive role in determining the nature of
the work done.
Let me draw some of the threads of this discussion together. I have argued that any
engagement in a practice—such as a form of inquiry—is deeply connected to agency,
in that such engagement always involves the working of various character traits of
the agent (whether virtues or vices). And to possess a particular virtue or vice is, in
turn, to have a certain sort of will. In the case of a virtue, it is to be motivated by
certain internal goods, or internal standards of excellence, of the practice in question.
Furthermore, because of the dialectical nature of practices, any striving for excellence
in a given practice is also simultaneously a transformation of that agent’s motivational
structure—for the striving results in a progressive revelation of the nature of those
internal goods to the agent. In this fashion, striving for excellence in a practice
involves a self-transformation—of what the agent values and desires. As MacIntyre
writes,
Individuals discover in the ends of any such practice goods common to all who engage in
it, goods internal to and specific to that particular type of practice, which they can make
their own only by allowing their participation in the activity to effect a transformation in the
desires which they initially brought with them to the activity. (MacIntyre 1994, p. 280)
It is, for example, through striving for excellence in mathematics that the agent trans-
forms herself into a mathematician; it is through striving for excellence in music
that the agent transforms herself into a musician. The key point is that such a self-
transformation is not simply an acquisition of certain capacities, skills and knowl-
edge, but involves, more fundamentally, a reshaping of the agent’s character.
Implied by all this is a fundamental point: if an agent strives for excellence
in a practice, then this entails that the agent is engaging in that practice non-
instrumentally. To engage in an activity instrumentally, is to engage in that activity
because it strikes the agent as an efficient and acceptable means to an end or goal that
she desires to achieve—where this end or goal is separate from the activity. Hence,
in the case of instrumental action, if the agent were to come to believe that another
activity was a more efficient means to that end, then she would do that instead.
Opposed to doing something for instrumental reasons is to engage in an activity
non-instrumentally, or autotelically. This is to engage in the activity for its own sake.
30 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
that the action proceeds from. (For an act to count as murder, for example, requires
that the agent have the intention to murder.) So, suppose, for example, that I engage
in something that looks superficially like historical inquiry (in that I read in archives,
gather quotations from other historians, etc.). However, suppose further that in doing
this I am in fact motivated, not by a desire to craft a compelling narrative that is
well-grounded in the available historical evidence (an internal good of the practice
of history), but purely and entirely by a desire to produce a sensational book that
will sell as many copies as possible (an external good). In such a case, there is an
important sense in which I am not really engaged in historical inquiry at all—but
in a simulacrum of such inquiry. I am, as it were, ‘going through the motions’ of
engaging in historical inquiry, but that is all.
At this point there is a potential objection that needs to be dealt with: this is the
suggestion that, contrary to the claims made above, inquiry is undertaken instru-
mentally. After all—the objection runs—the point of engaging in inquiry is to find
something out (e.g., the truth of some proposition); and this resulting knowledge is
not itself inquiry, but an external goal of inquiry. This objection, although tempting, is
misguided, because practises of inquiry have a deeper end than merely accumulating
states of knowledge. Their goal is an active understanding of the world—a doing,
rather than a state or capacity (that is, with the word ‘understanding’ functioning
here a gerundive rather than a noun). As Holt puts this point, under the sub-heading
“Knowledge is Action,”
we would do very well to understand that what we have mistakenly come to think of as
‘bodies of knowledge’ or ‘fields of learning’ or ‘academic disciplines’ or ‘school subjects’
are not nouns but verbs … things that people do. (Holt 1976, p. 16)
So, the ultimate goal of practices of inquiry is the activity of inquiry itself. For
example, the ultimate end of mathematical inquiry is not for the agent to build a
collection of states of knowledge (of mathematical truths) and capacities (e.g., the
capacity to be able to make use of various proof techniques). These, after all, are mere
potentialities. Rather, the end of this practice is the ‘running actualisation’ of those
states and capacities in actual episodes of mathematical understanding—such as
solving a mathematical problem, constructing a proof, or working through another’s
proof. In the same fashion, to take another example, the end of learning music is
not to amass a collection of musical knowledge, but to engage in actual episodes of
music-making and musical understanding.
This point that practices must, to some extent, be engaged in autotelically, or for
their own sakes, illustrates an important point about the nature of motivation. We
have seen that there is a crucial difference between undertaking an activity because
it is a practice and one is motivated by its internal goods, and undertaking an activity
32 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
With these Aristotelian insights into the connections between agency and activity to
hand, I now return to begin making sense of those puzzling claims of Holt with which
I began this chapter. We saw there that at the heart of Holt’s account of learning,
and his critique of education, is the claim that there is a kind of learning which
is particularly valuable or important. This ‘best learning’, Holt argues, cannot be
produced by undertaking ‘learning activities’, motivated through external incentives
and disincentives. Rather, this ‘best learning’ is essentially a by-product of activities
undertaken by the agent because those activities strike the agent as worth doing in
themselves.
As the language just used should already suggest, we can clarify what Holt is
talking about here by use of the Aristotelian distinction, introduced above, between
engaging in an activity autotelically, and engaging in it instrumentally. What marks
out the activities that make up education, in Holt’s sense of the word, is that they are
engaged in instrumentally by the agent. That is, the agent views the activity not as
worth doing for its own sake, but as an efficient means to an end. The official, external
reason for undertaking the activity is to produce certain ‘learning outcomes’, but of
course for many learners—especially those in compulsory schooling—the activity
is undertaken because of other sorts of incentives and disincentives (the ‘threats’ and
‘bribes’ of which Holt speaks). In either case, the goals or ends of the activity are
external to the activity, and the activity is an instrument or means for pursuing those
ends. In contrast, I suggest, the ‘best learning’ results from engaging in a practice
autotelically—which is to say, in pursuit of what was termed above the internal goods
of that practice.
In order to fill this picture out, I begin by examining the sort of learning that results
from engaging in practices autotelically, and the sense in which that learning is a by-
product of the agent’s activity. As discussed above, practices have the characteristic
of being dialectical. This means that, through engaging in the practice, then, if things
2.5 The Best Learning 33
go well for the agent, her understanding of the standards of excellence that are internal
to that practice are deepened and enriched. Or, to put this another way, it is through
engaging in the practice that its internal goods progressively reveal themselves to the
agent. Consider the following example of this dialectic from Brewer:
Imagine a singer who is a masterful interpreter of blues songs and who is searching, just
now, for the right phrasing and intonation for a key line in a blues number. … She has no
way of discerning what counts as the interpretation she wants except by trying to sharpen her
grasp of this goodness she indistinctly perceives, and she may be unable to do this except by
attempting to approximate it in song, trusting that she will recognise it when she hears herself
sing it. She might sing the line many times over before achieving the interpretation towards
which she is drawn. She would then have discovered, or uncovered, what was drawing her
all along. (Brewer 2009, p. 47)
There is an important sense in which the singer, in this example, does not know
precisely what she is aiming at; that is, she does not begin with a clearly articulated
goal, and then devises an efficient route to reach that goal. Rather, the doing of the
practice is, as Brewer remarks, also a discovering or uncovering of her goal—of
what, precisely, the standards of excellence demand in this particular case. To take
another example, it is the same in the practice of writing (e.g., philosophy): one
learns just what it is one wants to say through the activity of writing—that is, through
the difficult work of beginning with a thought that is, at first, grasped only partially,
opaquely and inarticulately, and then struggling to bring that thought to clear and
precise expression.
It is worth contrasting this sort of dialectical learning with the instrumentalist
conception of learning embedded in the very idea of a ‘learning outcome’ (currently
dominant in much educational thinking). A learning outcome is something that can
be precisely specified in advance of the ‘learning activity’ being undertaken—it
is the future state at which the learning activity aims. To put this another way, a
learning activity is intentionally designed to be a means for efficiently bringing about
a specified learning outcome in the agent. Paul Hirst, in an early and influential
formulation of this sort of approach, argues that this is the only effective way of
approaching learning. The alternative to treating learning as the efficient pursuit of a
fully specified future outcome is, he writes, for learning simply to be “random” (Hirst
1975, p. 170). As he puts it, “Any learning which is not the learning of some particular
X is as vague as the notion of going somewhere but nowhere in particular” (Hirst 1975,
pp. 171–2; my emphasis). But this is simply not true. As we have seen, learning the
internal standards of excellence of a practice does not fit this instrumentalist picture.
It is not that the agent engaged in a struggle for excellence in a practice knows exactly
where she is going, and then works out an efficient route to get to that location. Rather,
as in the example of the blues singer, the finding out where she is going is identical
to the activity of getting there. The blues singer does not begin with a grasp of a
clearly articulated future state of affairs, at which her efforts then aim (if she did
have that grasp, then her search would be over). In the absence of that grasp, is she
therefore, as Hirst would have us say, floundering vaguely about, ‘going nowhere in
34 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
particular’? Of course not, and Hirst can only write this because he has nourished
his thinking with a one-sided diet of examples.4
In dialectical learning, like that of Brewer’s blues singer, it needs to be emphasised
that, whilst the agent is aiming at achieving excellence in a particular case, if all
goes well she thereby learns things that enable her to reach for higher standards
of excellence that reach beyond that particular case. That is, discovering what the
internal standards of excellence of a practice demand in a particular case, is also
a discovery of what they demand more generally; the discovery that is made in
the particular case further illuminates, for the agent, the practice as a whole. Let me
explain this important point further. As discussed, the only way to strive for excellence
in a practice, is to actually engage in the practice itself. And this means striving for
excellence in a particular episode of undertaking the activity—in the example above,
it means this singing, here and now. Yet this struggle for excellence here and now is
how the agent comes to a deeper grasp of the internal goods of the practice—goods
that reach right across the practice, and do not pertain simply to this particular case.
That is, it is only through struggling for excellence in particular cases that the agent
transforms herself into someone who understands what excellence demands across
the practice.
As discussed above, the agent’s growing understanding of the internal goods of a
practice just is the agent’s development of the virtues of the practice. So, how does
our imagined agent become an excellent singer of the blues? Only by striving for
excellence with this piece on this occasion, and that piece on that occasion, and so
on. Yet it is through all these particular episodes of striving that the agent transforms
herself (if all goes well) into someone who comes to possess the general virtues
of that musical practice, and can thus reach higher levels of excellence across the
practice (not just in those particular cases). In sum, it is through doing the practice
for its own sake, that the internal goods of the practice are progressively grasped by,
revealed to, the agent; and this, in turn, just is for the agent to further develop the
virtues of the practice.
Compare this to the remark from Aristotle quoted above, that “we become just
by doing just acts, temperate by doing temperate acts, brave by doing brave acts”
(1103a35–1103b2). By this, as Burnyeat remarks, “Aristotle is not simply giving us
a bland reminder that virtue takes practice. Rather, practice has cognitive powers,
in that it is the way we learn what is noble or just” (Burnyeat 1980, p. 73; my
emphasis). That is, it is only through particular strivings for excellence (trying to do
the right thing in this situation, and that situation, etc.) that we learn ‘what is noble
or just’. This is because ‘what is noble or just’ cannot be embodied in the form of a
collection of universal rules. If it could be summed up in a collection of rules, then
we could learn ‘what is noble or just’ simply by learning those rules in abstracto,
without engaging in the actual practice. But, as we have seen, to do ‘what is noble
or just’ requires responding to the particulars of each case, “to the right extent, at
4 “A main cause of philosophical disease—a one-sided diet: one nourishes one’s thinking with only
the right time, with the right aim, and in the right way” (as Aristotle puts it). Hence,
this learning must of necessity be embodied in the agent’s developing virtues.
What we have here, then, is learning—the development of the virtues of the
practice in question—that is essentially a by-product of engaging in that practice
autotelically, or for its own sake. This is to say, this learning cannot be aimed at
directly or intentionally; to do so is self-defeating. This is because the virtues of the
practice are acquired only by engaging in the practice in pursuit of its internal goods.
Given that those internal goods can only be embodied in particular stretches of the
practice (that is, after all, the sense in which they are ‘internal’), to engage in the
practice in pursuit of them, is to engage in the practice for its own sake.
Consider again the imagined blues singer discussed above. To strive for excellence
in this particular undertaking of the practice, is for the agent to have as her primary
aim: Getting this song right. She is not, for example, engaging in the practice with the
primary aim of: Becoming a great blues singer. (Indeed, engaging in the practice with
that kind of aim as primary is a route to acquiring the musical vices that stem from
narcissism: self-indulgence, flashiness, cheapness, and the like.) Nor, for that matter,
is she engaging in the practice with a view to improving certain technical skills. To
do this would be to treat the song as an exercise—as simply a means to an end—and
not as worth ‘getting right’ for its own sake. That is, it would entail that the primary
focus of her desires is not performing this particular song with excellence, here
and now, but rather the future state of having certain improved technical capacities.
Hence, the quality of the learning that the agent derives from this activity comes from
the fact that this activity is not engaged in to produce learning. Instead, the quality
comes from the fact that the practice is illuminated by the agent’s desires to get this
song right. If the agent’s primary motivation were instead the acquisition of certain
character traits, or simply to improve certain skills, then ipso facto this would imply
that ‘getting this right’ would lack the appropriate level of significance and value for
that agent—and thus the learning would not occur.
To put this another way, the learning that is a progressive deepening of one’s
grasp of the internal goods of a practice, can come about only through engaging in
the practice with a certain quality of attention (to what one is doing)—an intensity
of attention that we can call love. To have this love for what one is doing, is for
one’s evaluative outlook to make the internal goods of the practice the primary focus
of significance or value during one’s doing of that activity—so that in engaging
in the practice, one is attending and responding to the demands of those internal
goods. This is for those internal goods to be, from the perspective of the agent,
the pre-eminent reasons why she is engaged in the practice at that moment in time.
In contrast, insofar as the agent views the activity mainly as an efficient means
to an end—even if that end is to learn certain things—then that agent lacks the
motivational structure required to achieve that deepened grasp of the internal goods
of the practice. Hence, the acquisition of the virtues of a practice are essentially a
by-product of engagement in that practice, for such learning can occur only if the
practice is engaged in autotelically (for its own sake), rather than instrumentally.
The logic of this argument is precisely the same as Aristotle’s point about the
conceptual impossibility of acquiring the ethical virtues via instrumental action.
36 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
Suppose I undertake actions that, to external observers, appear brave; however, from
the first-person perspective, I am undertaking these actions because they appear to
me as efficient means to the end of producing a certain impression on observers—that
they think of me as brave, and hence accord me a certain status. To undertake actions
instrumentally like this (in pursuit of the public appearance of bravery) will not
result in me developing the virtue of bravery. For a constitutive part of having that
virtue is that I desire to do brave acts simply because they are the right (or excellent)
thing to do in this particular set of circumstances. That is, part of having the virtue
of bravery is to have an evaluative outlook in which brave acts are worth doing for
their own sake (and thus independently of whatever impression they may or may not
make on observers).
We now have an answer to our question of what Holt is talking about when he
talks of the best, most valuable, important, or ‘true’ learning. This ‘best learning’ is
the agent’s development of the virtues of a practice. This is what is required for the
agent to engage in a given practice to a higher level of excellence. Of course such
development entails a growth in the usual objects of learning—in the various skills,
technical capacities, and knowledge required for such higher levels of excellence.
However, it also entails that the agent has a growing grasp of the internal goods, or
internal standards of excellence, of that practice, and what they demand in particular
circumstances. And, as we have seen, this is just another way of saying that such
learning involves the development of the agent’s character. This learning is essentially
a by-product of the agent’s engagement in a practice for its own sake (autotelically); it
cannot be produced by engaging in the practice simply as an efficient means to some
external end (instrumentally). This is because possessing the virtues of a practice
entails that the agent possesses an evaluative outlook which focuses on the internal
goods of the practice as the primary reason for engaging in the practice. This, in
turn, means that the agent brings a particular quality of attention to her engagement
in the practice: she engages in the practice with love. Hence (to repeat Holt’s words,
quoted above), “It is not subject matter that makes some learning more valuable than
others, but the spirit in which the work is done” (Holt 1983, p. 293).
This conclusion also explains Holt’s repeated claim that we can achieve this ‘best
learning’ only by doing: “We learn to do something by doing it. There is no other
way” (Holt 1976, p. 13). Holt’s claim runs precisely parallel to Aristotle’s remark
that we can become brave only by doing brave acts. As discussed above, the internal
standards of excellence of a practice cannot be formulated as rules. If they could
be, then these rules could be learned in abstracto, without actual engagement in
the practice. However, as argued, to strive towards excellence in a practice requires
learning to respond appropriately to the particulars of the context—that is, through
developing the virtues of the practice. And this learning can only be achieved by
engaging in the practice itself.
I am now in a position to provide a clearer account of Holt’s critique of education.
Stated in summary form, it is this: in education, practices tend to be engaged in by
agents out of instrumental motivations; education thereby tends to be hostile to the
development of the virtues of practices. We have already remarked that instrumen-
talism is pervasive in educational institutions: most learners undertake the ‘learning
2.5 The Best Learning 37
activities’ within such institutions, not because they find those activities intrinsically
valuable, but because of the motivation provided by external incentives and disin-
centives. In turn, this instrumentalism means, for the reasons explored above, that
educational activities tend to be hostile to the agent’s development of the virtues of
practices. Viewing an activity as worth doing for instrumental reasons, is to value
that activity primarily as an efficient means to producing a certain end—where that
end is something external to the doing of the practice. From this evaluative outlook,
what will be worth doing is whatever will appear to the agent as most efficiently
achieving that external end—rather than what will best meet, in the particular case,
the practice’s own standards of excellence. To put this another way, the more the
practice is approached instrumentally, the less the agent’s evaluative outlook illu-
minates the internal goods of the practice. Hence, the less the agent will be able to
develop a deepening grasp of those internal goods; or, equivalently, the less the agent
will be able to develop the virtues of the practice.
This imagined objection thus divides the practice of music-making into two parts: the
‘playing’, which is done for its own sake, and a part consisting of various exercises,
which are done as efficient means to particular ends. This in turn suggests, contrary
to the argument developed above, that one can, at least in part, develop the virtues
of musicianship via instrumental means.
Holt responds to this objection at some length in a number of works, and a brief
exploration of his response will show how the analytic framework developed in this
chapter makes good sense of what he is saying. In Instead of Education, Holt writes
of,
the strange idea that there exist two different processes: (1) learning to play the cello; and
(2) playing the cello. … Of course, this is nonsense. There are not two processes, but one.
We learn to do something by doing it. There is no other way. (Holt 1976, p. 13)
In his posthumously published work, Learning All the Time, he writes that,
38 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
A father once told me that his daughter likes to play the violin, but hates to practice. Why
talk about ‘practice’? Why not just talk about playing the violin? … What do I do with my
cello? I play. I don’t spend part of my time getting ready to play it, and the rest of the time
playing it. Some of the time I play scales or things like that; some of the time I play pieces
that I am going to play with other people; some of the time I read new music; some of the
time I improvise. But all the time I am playing the cello. … For me there is no such thing as
‘practice’. (Holt 1989, p. 111)
And in an extended discussion of this same topic in Freedom and Beyond, he writes
that,
for someone who really loves playing an instrument, scales are part of that playing. … I
don’t divide my practice into pleasant and unpleasant parts, and then use ‘will-power’ to
make myself do the unpleasant ones so that I may later have the fun of doing the pleasant.
It is all one. (Holt 1972, p. 113)
Splitting ‘practice’ (as in, scales and other exercises) off from ‘playing’—or, more
generally, separating learning from doing—tends to makes the former activity
unpleasant, or burdensome, for the agent. This is because to treat an activity as
learning is to treat it instrumentally—as an efficient means to produce some ‘learn-
ing outcome’—rather than autotelically. And this is for the agent to undertake that
activity with an evaluative outlook that is focused on the activity’s expected future
outcome rather the present doing. This in turn tends to damage the agent’s approach
to the whole of music-making.
Holt’s response to this, as the quotes above show, is that the agent needs to avoid
such splitting, and instead keep steadily in view the unity of the practice of music-
making—as a unified doing. Hence, he writes that, when he found himself desiring
to sleep in on a cold morning and avoid his cello playing,
my response to this [desire] was not to draw on something called willpower, to insult or
threaten myself, but to take a longer look at my life to extend my vision, to think about
the whole of my experience, to reconnect present and future … If, as sometimes happened
or happens, I do stay in bed … it is not because will-power is weak but because I have
temporarily become disconnected, so to speak, from the wholeness of my life. (Holt 1972,
p. 113)
into a unity: they are all parts of an ongoing articulating of an historical understand-
ing, where this articulating is at the same time a discovering or uncovering of just
what the internal goods of historical inquiry demand of this understanding. Thus—to
return to Holt’s example of music-making—to maintain the quality of attention and
love that striving for excellence in the practice demands, the agent should not view
the playing of scales and exercises instrumentally, as efficient means to some future
end. Rather, the agent should view them as components of a unified practice of
music-making, the whole of which is animated by the agent’s on-going attempt to
reach for, and further articulate, the internal goods of that practice. As the great jazz
trumpeter Wynton Marsalis remarks, “Treat everything you play on your instrument
as an important piece of music, even if you are just warming up” (Marsalis 1995,
p. 130; cf. Green 1986).
The thought that education—the instrumentalising of activity, in separating
‘learning’ from ‘doing’—fragments the unity of human practices, is a theme to
which Holt regularly returns. Such talk of fragmentation or ‘splitting’ is another
way of putting the point that such instrumental activity is hostile to the development
of the virtues of the practice. To recall what was discussed above, excellence in
a practice involves the deployment of knowledge, skills and capacities of various
kinds. However, the executive centre, so to speak, of this deployment is the virtues
of that practice. For it is the agent’s possession of the virtues of the practice—or,
equivalently, the agent’s grasp of the internal goods of the practice—that allow her
to deploy the knowledge, skills, and capacities in just the way called for by the
particulars of the situation. To put this another way, it is the possession of the virtues
of the practice that give a unity to all the variety of knowledge, skills and capacities
required by the practice—through which their deployment coheres in a meaningful
way, as a unified pursuit of the internal goods of the practice.
In contrast, while instrumental activity can, of course, result in the learning of
various rules, techniques, skills, knowledge, and so on, what cannot be learned this
way is the unity of a practice. For, as we have seen, this unity comes from the agent’s
developing grasp of the internal goods of the practice—and this, in turn, comes only
through pursuing the practice for its own sake. Treated instrumentally, a practice
is fragmented into a mere collection or bundle of skills and pieces of knowledge.
This is a mere ‘bundle’, rather than a genuine unity, in that it lacks the overall
coherence given to their deployment by the agent’s grasp of the internal goods of
the practice. Without such a grasp, the agent may, for example, know that such-and-
such is the case, and she may know how to do such-and-such, but she cannot reliably
deploy those capacities in the ways demanded by the practice’s internal standards of
excellence. In contrast, learning these under the aegis of the practice’s virtues makes
a unified, coherent whole out of these skills, knowledge and capacities. That is, the
‘best learning’ involves the agent not just learning certain skills, knowledge, and
capacities, but—most importantly—also developing a growing sense of what it is to
deploy them (to quote Aristotle’s words again), “to the right extent, at the right time,
with the right aim, and in the right way”.
40 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
Holt’s first book, How Children Fail, is a detailed narrative exploration of what
happens when children learn instrumentally, and hence in a fragmented way—in
the absence of any real grasp of the internal goods of a practice. Through the use
of ethnographic-like techniques of close observation, and the detailed recording of
children’s conversations, Holt is able to move away from the all-too-familiar teacher’s
perspective on a class, and let us come closer to seeing educational activities from
the students’ perspective. What we see from this agent’s perspective are children
who lack, to a striking degree, any real grasp of the internal goods of the practices of
inquiry that they are nominally engaged in. These are, as Holt notes, ‘good’ students
at a ‘good’ school—and as such, the children have some relevant knowledge, and
possess various skills and techniques in inquiry. However, what they lack is the
capacity to deploy the knowledge and skills they possess, in the way that the internal
standards of the practice demand in the particular context. They cannot, that is, deploy
what knowledge and skills they do possess “to the right extent, at the right time, with
the right aim, and in the right way”.
To put this another way, what we see again and again in Holt’s narratives, are
children who are entirely missing the overall point or meaning of the inquiry that
is nominally underway. They make use of rules and techniques in a manner that is
mechanical, and done without any sense of when such uses are appropriate (that is,
when they assist in reaching for the internal goals of the inquiry). Rules of thumb
—useful in some contexts—are used without appropriate judgment, and treated as
invariant and constitutive. That is, they are used with no grasp of the internal goods
that the rules are an attempt to express. In some cases there are children who are
able to “crank out right answers”, but “without the faintest idea of what they were
doing” (Holt 1982, p. 176). Overall, through the narratives of How Children Fail,
we see that what should be a unitary, coherent, developing inquiry is, from these
children’s perspective, seen as a series of separate, disconnected activities—strung
together without rhyme or reason. It is thus unsurprising that, as Holt shows in detail,
the children perform these activities in the manner of people performing the rites of
a long dead religion, with no grasp of what they are really doing, or why.
At the limit, as external (instrumental) motivations come to overwhelm the chil-
dren’s evaluative outlook on their own activity, we see from Holt’s account just what
we would expect: that the children are not really engaged in practices of inquiry
at all. Rather, the instrumental motivation results in them engaging in something
that just has the appearance of inquiry. The main external motivation that Holt
points to is fear—fear of the consequences of giving a wrong answer, such as the
resulting public humiliation (e.g., mockery from one’s peers), or of disappointing
the teacher’s expectations, or of disappointing the children’s own expectations of
themselves. When a child’s evaluative outlook is dominated by an external end like
fear, the result is a choice of strategies which bear no relation at all to the inter-
nal goods of the practice of inquiry in which the child is nominally engaged. As
Holt documents, fear results in such strategies as ‘fence-sitting’ or ‘hedging one’s
2.7 How Children Fail 41
bets’ (i.e., avoiding commitment to an answer); attempting to ‘read’ the teacher for
the answer; attempts to manipulate the teacher into providing the answer. From an
instrumental perspective, these strategies make perfectly good sense: they appear as
efficient means to the end of ‘avoiding a wrong answer’. But for an agent engaged
in an inquiry for its own sake (i.e., because it appears interesting, worth while,
valuable, etc.) these strategies would make no sense at all. In other words, what
Holt shows us is that, although the children may, to a superficial external observa-
tion, be engaged in what looks like mathematics or some other form of inquiry, by
paying close attention to what they say and do, it becomes obvious that they are
in fact not doing this at all—they are, instead, engaged in a simulacrum of such
inquiries. As discussed above, a practice cannot be pursued instrumentally (i.e., in
a way dominated by external ends), because a practice is constituted by its inter-
nal goods. Yet external ends—external incentives and disincentives; ‘bribes’ and
‘threats’—are precisely how motivation is typically provided in school. Hence, as
Holt writes,
these children see school almost entirely of the day-to-day and hour-to-hour tasks that we
impose on them. … For children, the central business of the school is not learning … it
is getting these daily tasks done, or at least out of the way, with a minimum of effort and
unpleasantness. (Holt 1982, pp. 37–8)
After all, he suggests, from the students’ perspective it certainly looks like “what most
teachers want and reward are not knowledge and understanding but the appearance
of them” (Holt 1982, p. 255).
At this point, it is worth pausing briefly to clarify the epistemological status of the
narratives in How Children Fail. As noted in the previous chapter, Holt deliberately
avoids what I termed there the ‘scholarly mode of telling’, and tends to argue his
case via a web of narratives. As remarked, this form of writing leaves him open to
the charge of being a retailer of ‘mere anecdotes’, and thereby failing to establish his
position with sufficient empirical rigour. However, as can seen from the discussion
above, this objection misunderstands what Holt is doing. The objection assumes
that Holt is making empirical claims, and then providing ‘anecdotes’ as second-rate
evidence for those claims—rather than, say, data derived from systematic surveys.
But Holt is pointing out (among other things) that children whose evaluative
outlook is dominated by an external end like fear, do not engage in genuine inquiry.
As I have argued here, this is not an empirical claim but a conceptual one—it
concerns the logical connections between the concepts of a practice of inquiry,
agency, and autotelic versus instrumental activity. Holt’s narratives are an attempt
to make these conceptual connections—which I have discussed in this chapter in an
abstract fashion—living and concrete for the reader. To put this another way, Holt’s
narratives function, to use a Wittgensteinian phrase, not as patchy, second-rate
empirical evidence, but as reminders of conceptual connections to which we have
not given due weight in our thoughts and practices. The doings of Nell, Emily,
Martha, Nancy, Sam, Nat, and the rest, that Holt discusses in How Children Fail are
real, but they need not have been; in an important sense, Holt is giving us parables
that aim to illuminate the nature of learning.
42 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
I have argued that Holt’s notion of the ‘best learning’ is the agent’s development
of the virtues of a practice, through striving for excellence in that practice. Such
activity entails that the agent engage with the practice in pursuit of its internal goods,
or standards of excellence; hence, it entails that the agent undertake the practice
autotelically, or for its own sake. This means that the ‘best learning’ is essentially
a by-product of activity undertaken because it strikes the agent as significant,
valuable, or worth doing in its own right. Such activity is, in Holt’s phrase, genuine
“doing—self-directed, purposeful, meaningful life and work”; or, as I have put it, it
is engaging in human practices with passionate attention.
Another way that Holt expresses this thought is with his repeated slogans that
‘living is learning’ and that ‘learning is an expansion of the self’. In What Do I Do
Monday, for example, he writes that,
we can best understand learning as growth, an expanding of ourselves into the world around
us. We can also see that there is no difference between living and learning, that living is
learning, that it is impossible, and misleading, and harmful to think of them as separate.
(Holt 1970, p. 23)
Living is learning, because it is through ‘work worth doing’ that the best kind of
learning takes place—the learning that is a deepening and articulating of the inter-
nal goods of practices, rather than the fragmented grasping of skills and pieces of
knowledge, lacking a coherent unity and point. The best learning, in other words, is
one and the same as the best doing—autotelic activity—which is, for both Aristotle
and Holt, a key component of the good life for a human being.
In turn, such learning is an expansion of the self—that is, of agency. This is
because the learning that is the acquisition of the virtues of practice is not simply a
learning of skills, knowledge and capacities (although it does entail such learning).
Rather, it is a transformation, or reshaping, of the agent’s character—of what is
desired, wanted, found valuable, significant. For as one comes to comprehend the
internal goods of a practice, so one’s desires for those goods become deeper and more
articulate. In other words, through engagement in a practice, one does not simply
develop capacities to be able to do more; it is also the case that what one wants,
desires, values, and intends becomes richer and more extensive. In this way, one’s
agency is now expressed through that practice in a way it was not before.
Consider, for example, what happens as an agent develops as a musician. She finds
that the instrument (which before had seemed like an obstacle to action; something
alien to the self) slowly becomes a part of herself, through which she can express her
desires and what she values and finds significant. Or consider an agent developing as
a mathematician: she can now possess desires that are articulable only in mathematics
(the desire to achieve a certain elegance in a particular proof, for example) and the
mathematical techniques she has mastered become available modes of expression
for articulating such desires. In each case, through the striving for excellence in a
practice, an aspect of the world—musical forms; mathematical structures—becomes
2.8 Drawing Together the Threads 43
available to the learner, as a domain in which her agency is expressed. It seems natural
to call this, as Holt does, an ‘expansion of the self into the world’.
To learning as a by-product of genuine ‘doing’, Holt opposes ‘education’. As he
uses this term, it involves undertaking activities which are intended as a means of
producing certain learning outcomes. That is, educational activities are not intended
to be worth doing for their own sakes, but for the sake of the valued future outcome that
they are intended to accomplish. In a word, education (in Holt’s sense) is instrumental
activity. It is thus “learning cut off from active life”—learning that has been separated
from activity that is significant to an agent for its own sake.
Holt’s consistent emphasis on the importance of the learner’s freedom and auton-
omy follows as an obvious corollary of this view. To produce ‘best learning’ requires
the agent to undertake activity autotelically; that is, because the activity strikes
the agent as worth doing for its own sake. If a learner is only engaging in an
activity because she is coerced or manipulated into doing so—through ‘bribe’ or
‘threat’—then this necessarily renders the agent’s activity instrumental rather than
autotelic. After all, to coerce or manipulate somebody is to motivate that agent
through the use of external goods—so that an activity shows up for that agent as
worth doing because it is an efficient means of obtaining a valued thing (e.g., a prof-
fered reward), or avoiding a bad thing (e.g., a threatened punishment). But autotelic
activity is for the agent to be primarily motivated by the internal goods of a prac-
tice—and that means that the agent would undertake that activity in the absence
of any external motivation. Hence, the absence of freedom for a learner—that is,
a coercive or manipulative educational environment (such as found in compulsory
schooling)—is intrinsically hostile to autotelic activity, and therefore hostile to the
acquisition of the virtues of practices.
It should be noted that this is not to claim that autotelic activity is impossible in a
coercive context. It is perfectly possible—indeed, it is an everyday occurrence—for
an agent to begin working at a practice in pursuit of external goods, and then slowly
come to grasp the internal goods of the practice. For example, a student who was
compelled to undertake an activity may come to value a practice for its own sake—for
example, because a teacher, or reading the right book at the right time, succeeds
in opening her eyes to its worth. Similarly, a child may begin playing a musical
instrument in order to please his parents (another example of an external incentive),
but come to love the music-making for its own sake. However, what has occurred in
such cases is not that autotelic activity has been brought about by the influence of
external incentives or disincentives. Rather, what has occurred is a transformation in
the agent’s desires, and how she sees and values the activity. This has occurred in spite
of the presence of external (instrumental) motivations, rather than because of them.
External motivations necessarily cannot produce autotelic engagement. Indeed, the
more oppressive, or compelling, the external reasons appear to the agent, the less
likely it is for that agent to be able to ‘look past’ such motivations, to grasp the
internal goods of a practice.
In this way, in virtue of its instrumentalist tendencies, education—and this is truer,
the greater its reliance on external motivators (i.e., the more coercive or manipulative
it is)—tends to undermine the pursuit of excellence in practices, and thereby tends to
44 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
undermine agents’ acquisition of the virtues of those practices. In other words, edu-
cation is intrinsically hostile to agents engaging in practices with the kind of quality
of attention, or love for what they are doing, that is required for the ‘best learning’.
Compulsory schooling is an obvious example of a highly coercive framework—and
one which was Holt’s focus—but such coercion can come in more subtle ways. For
example, whilst university study is not compulsory, and thus lacks the legal coercion
that forms the framework of more junior levels of schooling, it is nonetheless the case
that, as remarked in the previous chapter, in many countries a university qualification
has become more and more essential for access to decent work. This credentialism
is a powerful external motivator for students, and it is easy to see that it is hostile to a
student’s pursuit of a practice for its own sake. After all, if one’s primary motivation
is to obtain a credential perceived as necessary to a decent standard of living, then,
for example, plagiarism, exam cheating, or the use of essay mills, may well appear
to the agent as an efficient means to that end (and certainly appears that way to many
students). But if one is undertaking a practice of inquiry for its own sake, then such
cheating makes no sense at all.
Holt’s critique of education as instrumentalised learning can be seen as a radicali-
sation of the well-known concept of the ‘hidden curriculum’. The hidden curriculum
is the idea that compulsory schooling does not communicate simply the content of its
official, explicit curriculum (numeracy, literacy, and so on) to its students. Rather, it
also implicitly communicates certain ideas in virtue of its bureaucratic, authoritarian
form—such as epistemological ideas about the nature of knowledge and the know-
ing self; political ideas about individualism and competitiveness. All of these are
implicitly ‘taught’ by school’s organisation, hierarchy, and procedures (cf. Barrow
1978, pp. 136–9.) Holt’s critique of education can be seen as radically extending
this idea by criticising the impact of the instrumentalist form that education tends
overwhelmingly to take in our culture, and how this impacts the evaluative outlook
that learners bring to their own activity.
Making use of the Aristotelian analysis developed earlier in the chapter, I have
discussed Holt’s claims that the ‘best learning’ is essentially a by-product of practices
engaged in for their own sake, and that the instrumental motivations characteristic of
educational practice are hostile to such learning. Of the claims we began the chapter
with, there is one more that needs explanation and clarification. This is Holt’s claim
that education has an intrinsic tendency to be damaging to the agent qua inquirer.
Or, in his own flamboyantly counter-intuitive words, “To a very large degree, school
is a place where children learn to be stupid” (Holt 1982, p. 263).
Stated in the terms used here, this latter claim is that engaging instrumentally
in a practice not only prevents the acquisition of the virtues of a practice, but is
in fact conducive to developing the vices of the practice. The vices of a practice,
after all, are those character traits in virtue of which an agent is susceptible to the
2.9 Stupidity and Intelligence 45
In this passage, Holt’s distinction between the ‘bright child’ and the ‘dull child’ is
framed entirely—to use the Aristotelian terminology of this chapter—in terms of
possession of the virtues and vices of inquiry: the character traits that make people
good inquirers or bad inquirers. The bright child, that is, is a person who possesses
the virtues of inquiry to a high degree: intellectual courage, curiosity, imaginative-
ness, resourcefulness, hopefulness, and so on. The dull child, on the other hand, is
someone who possesses the vices of inquiry to a high degree: lack of imagination,
passivity, helplessness, intellectual cowardice, self-distrust, and so on. Similarly, con-
sider Holt’s summation in Teach Your Own of what the ‘best learning’ is concerned
with: “What makes people smart, curious, alert, observant, competent, confident,
resourceful, persistent—in the broadest and best sense, intelligent” (p. 235). What
is this characterisation of intelligence (‘in the broadest and best sense’) but a list of
the key virtues of inquiry?
46 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
A number of issues could be raised with this definition, such as the intellectualist
presuppositions contained in the word ‘mind’, but the key issue lies in the bland
phrase ‘problems with which it is confronted’. This is a conception of intelligence as
a General Problem Solver, where it is irrelevant whether those problems are humanly
significant or trivial. It is, in other words, a strongly instrumentalist account of
intelligence—of intelligence not as involving the grasping of ends, but simply as a
calculator of efficient means.
What this helps to bring out is that, in important ways, calling something ‘intelli-
gent’ is praise, so there is no ethically neutral definition of it to be had. That is, any
account of intelligence will, implicitly or explicitly, build in some conception of the
human good; some conception of the kinds of activities that are considered valuable,
important, and significant. Hence, it is unsurprising that a civilisation like ours, that
focuses on instrumental uses of reason to the exclusion of the autotelic, will tend to
think of intelligence as a kind of raw ‘problem solving’ capacity—focused on the
efficient reaching of goals. Thus, for example, the attention given to IQ testing, which
focuses on the agent’s capacity to manipulate abstractions in highly decontextualized
ways. In contrast, Holt, like Aristotle, sees the human good as lying in ‘work worth
doing’: in rich human practices, done for their own sake, with passionate attention to
the particulars of the context, and a striving to meet the practice’s internal standards
of excellence. To engage in practices of inquiry in this way, demands that the agent
possess the virtues of inquiry.
Holt’s argument thus leads to the conclusion that education—thanks to its ten-
dency to rely on external incentives and disincentives—systematically encourages
learners to develop the vices of understanding. That is, as he puts it, school tends
to make students stupid. As we have seen, striving for excellence (and hence the
development of the virtues of a practice) involves a continuous attention to the inter-
nal goods of that practice. Engaging in an activity out of instrumental motivations,
however, is hostile to this sort of loving attention. As Holt writes,
Give a child the kind of task he gets in school, and whether he is afraid of it, or resists it, or
is willing to do but bored by it, he will do the task with only a small part of his attention,
energy, and intelligence. In a word, he will do it stupidly—even if correctly. (Holt 1982,
pp. 263–4)
In contrast,
A child is most intelligent when the reality before him arouses in him a high degree of
attention, interest, concentration, involvement—in short, when he cares most about what he
is doing. (Holt 1982, p. 265)
2.9 Stupidity and Intelligence 47
As we have seen, when we are dealing with practices of inquiry (rather than simple,
mechanical tasks), the way in which an activity is done by an agent makes all the dif-
ference in the world. We can imagine two students in school, who are engaged in the
same kind of inquiry and—in an ‘external’ sense—are both ‘doing the same things’.
However, one student is reading imaginatively, analysing thoughtfully, and writing
carefully; whilst the other student is reading unimaginatively, analysing thought-
lessly, and writing carelessly. The former student is on the way to developing the
virtues of inquiry; the latter student is on the way to developing the vices of inquiry.
In other words, the quality of attention given to one’s practice relates directly to how
one’s agency is related to it—whether the present activity is seen by the agent as
merely a burdensome means to a future end, or as something that is loved for its own
sake.
In particular, as Holt discusses in detail in How Children Fail, if fear is a dominant
external motive for children in schooling—as it too often is—then that is enormously
destructive of their intelligence. In Holt’s words, “the scared learner is always a poor
learner” (Holt 1982, p. 93). Consider his comments about ‘Emily’:
The child must be right. She cannot bear to be wrong, or even to imagine that she might
be wrong. … When she is told to do something, she does it quickly and fearfully, hands it
to some higher authority, and awaits the magic word right or wrong. If the word is right, she
does not have to think about that problem anymore; if the word is wrong, she does not want
to, cannot bring herself to think about it. (Holt 1982, pp. 21–2)
As Holt remarks, if an agent is motivated by fear (of getting a wrong answer) this is
productive of various vices of inquiry: it tends to produce an agent who, like Emily,
is defensive, evasive, helpless, and passive. In Holt’s words,
The strategies of most of these kids have been consistently self-centred, self-protective,
aimed above all else at avoiding trouble, embarrassment, punishment, disapproval, or loss
of status. (Holt 1982, p. 91)
At bottom, this principle rests upon the fact of habit, when habit is interpreted biologically.
The basic characteristic of habit is that every experience enacted and undergone modifies the
one who acts and undergoes, while this modification affects, whether we wish it or not, the
quality of subsequent experiences. For it is a somewhat different person who enters into them.
The principle of habit so understood obviously goes deeper than the ordinary conception
of a habit as a more or less fixed way of doing things, although it includes the latter as
one of its special cases. It covers the formation of attitudes, attitudes that are emotional and
intellectual; it covers our basic sensitivities and ways of meeting and responding to all the
conditions which we meet in living. (Dewey 2015, p. 35)
“Hence”, writes Dewey, “the central problem of an education based upon experi-
ence is to select the kind of present experiences that live fruitfully and creatively
in subsequent experiences” (2015, pp. 27–8). Dewey thus shares with Holt, then,
the thought that the relationship between education and the learner’s character is of
particular importance. However, as Dewey’s language of ‘habit’ and ‘modification’
in the passage just quoted indicate, he conceives of the learner as essentially pas-
sive. The learner is, for Dewey, the subject of experiences, who is causally modified
by them. The active person in Dewey’s model is thus the educator, who designs an
educational context in order to ‘select’ the right (growth-oriented) experiences that
will then ‘form’ the learner’s attitudes. In contrast, as argued in this chapter, Holt
has a much richer account of the relations between activity and character—and, in
particular, how character relates to the learner’s agency. Hence, the crucial differ-
ence between Dewey and Holt is that, for Holt, the learner is not a subject but the
actor; rather than being transformed by experiences, the learner transforms herself
through her own activity (in engaging passionately with various human practices and
pursuing their internal goods).
Closer to Holt’s perspective is the thought of another Deweyan, the influential
William Kilpatrick. In his famous paper ‘The project method’ (1918), Kilpatrick
argues that the best form of learning comes from “wholehearted purposeful activity
proceeding in a social environment, or more briefly, in the unit element of such
activity, the hearty purposeful act” (Kilpatrick 1918, p. 320). Hence, he argues,
If the purposeful act be in reality the typical unit of the worthy life, then it follows that to
base education on purposeful acts is exactly to identify the process of education with worthy
living itself. The two become then the same. (Kilpatrick 1918, p. 323)
That is, as Holt would agree, ‘living is learning’. Kilpatrick thus shares with Holt
the emphasis on the importance of the learner’s exercise of agency—of engaging in
activity in a way that is “wholehearted” and driven by “the presence of a dominating
purpose” (Kilpatrick 1918, p. 321)—and how the quality of engagement plays a role
in shaping the learner’s character. However, Kilpatrick’s account of the relationships
between agency, activity, and character are conceptually crude. Under the influence
of a mechanistic psychology that only here and there resembles a human being, he
views ‘wholeheartedness’ as a simple ordinal variable, and claims that the “psycho-
logical value [of a learner’s activity] increases with the degree of approximation to
‘wholeheartedness’” (Kilpatrick 1918, p. 322). Entirely missing from Kilpatrick’s
account are the distinctions—so crucial to understanding Holt’s position—between
instrumental and autotelic activity, external and internal goods. After all, a learner
2.9 Stupidity and Intelligence 49
2.10 Conclusion
The argument of this chapter has been long and complex, so a summary may be
found useful. In this chapter I have constructed an Aristotelian model of agency and
activity in order to make clear and coherent sense of Holt’s account of learning and
his critique of education. The main results of the analysis are as follows:
1. Holt holds that there is a kind of learning that is particularly valuable and impor-
tant. This learning is the agent’s development of her character, through acquiring
the virtues of practices.
2. This ‘best learning’ can only be acquired by undertaking those practices in pursuit
of their internal goods. It cannot be acquired through instrumental activity (that
is, by undertaking a practice as an efficient means to some external good).
3. That is, this ‘best learning’ is essentially a by-product of activities pursued for
themselves, or autotelically—that is, because the agent loves the activity for
itself, and thus engages in it passionately or wholeheartedly.
4. Hence, external incentives and disincentives (grades, threats of punishment,
etc.)—such as are typical of educational practice—cannot produce the ‘best
learning’. Insofar as students manage to acquire the ‘best learning’ in an (instru-
mentalised) educational context, they do so in spite of that context rather than
because of it.
5. Furthermore, engaging in practices out of such instrumental motives tends to
encourage the agent to develop the vices of the practice in question.
6. In the case of practices of inquiry, possessing the vices of that practice (to a
significant degree) is (a form of) stupidity.
7. Hence, educational practice, insofar as it relies on instrumental motives, tends to
‘make students stupid’.
This account of Holt’s position still remains, however, rather abstract. To make it
somewhat more concrete is the job of the rest of this book. The next chapter (Chap. 3)
will fill in further details of Holt’s account, by way of responses to the most salient
and significant objections to that account. The final chapter (Chap. 4) will then
briefly examine the practical strategies—homeschooling, in particular—that Holt
recommends for mitigating the problems with education that are diagnosed by his
account, and for improving children’s chances of acquiring ‘the best learning’.
50 2 The Spirit in Which the Work Is Done
References
Aristotle (1984). Nichomachean ethics (W. D. Ross, Trans.). In J Barnes (Ed.), The complete works
of Aristotle: The revised Oxford translation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Baehr, J. (2011). The inquiring mind: On intellectual virtues and virtue epistemology. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Barrow, R. (1978). Radical education: A critique of freeschooling and deschooling. Oxford: Martin
Robertson.
Brewer, T. (2009). The retrieval of ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Burnyeat, M. F. (1980). Aristotle on learning to be good. In A. O. Rorty (Ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s
Ethics (pp. 69–92). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Crawford, M. (2010). Shopcraft as soulcraft: An inquiry into the value of work. London: Penguin.
Dewey, J. (2015). Experience and education. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Elster, J. (1983). Sour grapes: Studies in the subversion of rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Foot, P. (2002). Virtues and vices. Virtues and vices and other essays in moral philosophy (pp. 1–18).
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Green, B. (1986). The inner game of music. New York: Doubleday.
Hirst, P. (1975). What is teaching? In R. S. Peters (Ed.), The philosophy of education (pp. 163–77).
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Holt, J. (1970). What do I do Monday? New York: E. P. Dutton and Co.
Holt, J. (1971). Big bird, meet Dick and Jane: A critique of Sesame Street. Atlantic Monthly, 227(5),
72–8.
Holt, J. (1972). Fundamental reminders: We learn for ourselves. Edcentric: A Journal for Educa-
tional Change, September, 4–6.
Holt, J. (1976). Instead of education. New York: E. P. Dutton and Co.
Holt, J. (1981). Teach your own: A hopeful path for education. Liss, Hants: Lighthouse Books.
Holt, J. (1982). How children fail (revised ed.). New York: Merloyd Lawrence.
Holt, J. (1983). How children learn (revised ed.). London: Penguin.
Holt, J. (1989). Learning all the time. New York: Merloyd Lawrence.
Holt, J. (1990). Letter to Joanna Picciotto, 1/1/82. In S. Sheffer (Ed.), A life worth living: Selected
letters of John Holt (pp. 249–52). Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press.
Hookway, C. (2003). How to be a virtue epistemologist. In M. DePaul & L. Zagzebski (Eds.),
Intellectual virtue: Perspectives from ethics and epistemology (pp. 183–202). Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Kilpatrick, W. H. (1918). The project method. Teachers College Record, 19(4), 319–35.
MacIntyre, A. (1984). After virtue: A study in moral theory (2nd ed.). Notre Dame, IN: University
of Notre Dame Press.
MacIntyre, A. (1994). The T heses on Feuerbach: A road not taken. In C. C. Gould & R. S. Cohen
(Eds.), Artifacts, representations and social practice (pp. 277–90). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Marsalis, W. (1995). Marsalis on music. New York: Norton.
Peters, R. S. (1966). Ethics and education. London: George Allen and Unwin.
Pirsig, R. M. (2004). Zen and the art of motorcycle maintenance: An inquiry into values
(25th anniversary ed.). London: Vintage.
Roberts, R. C., & Wood, W. J. (2007). Intellectual virtues: An essay in regulative epistemology.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sennett, R. (2008). The craftsman. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Sudnow, D. (2001). Ways of the hand: A rewritten account. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Von Wright, G. H. (1963). The varieties of goodness. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophische Untersuchungen/Philosophical Investigations (2nd ed.).
(G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Wood, L. (1963). Intelligence. In D. D. Runes (Ed.), Dictionary of philosophy. New York: Philo-
sophical Library.
Chapter 3
Objections and Replies
… the small child’s sense of the wholeness and openness of life is … his most human trait. It
is above all else what makes it possible for him—or anyone else—to grow and learn. (Holt
1970, p. 24)
3.1 Introduction
According to this account, for the ‘best learning’ to be acquired, learners need to
engage in a practice for its own sake—in pursuit of the internal goods of that practice.
But that is a very sophisticated, adult desire to have—and children, after all, have
childish desires. Hence, whilst engaging in practices for their own sake may be an
appropriate aim for adult learners, it is not so for young children.
There are two connected errors that lie behind this objection. First, it mis-
takes the sophistication of the analytical framework—or, rather, the language
in which that framework is expressed—for the sophistication of the phenom-
ena being described. Stated more plainly, all this talk in the previous chapter of
‘agency’, ‘internal goods’ versus ‘external motivations’, ‘practices’, and ‘autotelic
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019 51
A. Dickerson, John Holt, SpringerBriefs on Key Thinkers
in Education, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18726-2_3
52 3 Objections and Replies
activity’ may not be ordinary and everyday; but it is part of a philosophical anal-
ysis of something that is ordinary and everyday. The second error lying behind
the objection is that it misses the significance of the fact that human practices are
dialectical in nature—that through engaging in a practice, one’s grasp of its internal
standards of excellence grows in depth and sophistication.
The first point is easily dealt with. Whilst the Aristotelian language in which this
point is expressed may not be familiar to all, to engage in a practice ‘in pursuit of
its internal goods’, ‘in pursuit of its internal standards of excellence’, or ‘for its own
sake’ is an everyday phenomenon. Some examples should help to make this clear:
If one is reading a novel that one loves, then the aim of the activity is the reading itself—to
read with as much attention and care as possible, immersing oneself in the language and the
story. It is not, for example, simply ‘to find out what happens’—for in that case, it would be
far more efficient to read a plot summary, or skip to the last chapter.
If one is building a piece of fine wooden furniture as a gift for a loved one then the aim is to
bring the project to completion; but it is to do this by building it as carefully and skilfully as
one can (attempting to do full justice to the beauty of the grain; by being as precise as one can
with the joinery, etc.). The fact that the agent, in this imagined case, would reject as offensive
the idea of simply purchasing a piece of furniture (even if that were more ‘efficient’) shows
that this activity is being pursued autotelically, not instrumentally.
For someone who loves cooking, then the aim of that activity is indeed that a meal be
prepared—but it is to be prepared by way of the activity of the agent himself cooking as well
as he possibly can (taking pains to bring out the best in the ingredients; cooking the meat just
so; balancing the flavours, etc.). In this imagined case, the cooking is not undertaken simply
as an efficient means to the end of ‘having a meal prepared’—and this is shown in the fact
that the agent would scornfully reject the suggestion that ‘it would be more efficient’ simply
to purchase some takeaway food or hire in a cook for the day.
If one is playing a piece of music, then the aim is to play that music as well as
possible—playing it with the right sort of expressiveness, tone, rhythm, etc. The playing of
the music is not simply an efficient means to the end of ‘having music played’—for in that
case, simply hitting a button on a stereo would achieve the end far more efficiently than all
the work of practice, tuning, maintaining the instrument, etc.
When one plays a game such as chess, then the aim is to win (of course), but it is to win by play-
ing the best chess one can play (rather than, for example, by cheating, or by paying one’s oppo-
nent to deliberately lose—even if this could be shown to be a ‘more efficient’ path to a win).
In each of these cases, the central point of doing the activity is to do it as well as
one can; in Aristotelian terms, in each case, the agent is aiming at excellence in
that activity. In each case, the measure of what counts as ‘doing the activity well’ or
‘excellence’, comes from within the practice itself—what counts as excellent reading,
cooking, woodwork, music-making, and so on. That is to say, in each case one is
aiming at the internal goods of the activity. This is so, even when the activity also
produces an outcome (such as a win, or a piece of fine furniture, or a delicious meal,
or a good musical performance). This is because the outcome in itself was not the
motive—as we only desired the outcome through undertaking the activity (rather than
achieving it in some other way, such as by purchasing it as a commodity). That is, the
activity is engaged in autotelically, rather than instrumentally (as an efficient means
to an end). It is a revealing fact that, in many of these imagined cases, attempting to
treat them as if they were purely instrumental (by suggesting ‘more efficient means’)
3.2 Objection #1: Childish desires 53
is not simply a missing of the point—it is a missing of the point that can be deeply
ethically offensive, for it demonstrates a failure to understand how the activity fits
into a good human life.
It is worth emphasising that the assumption made in each of the above examples
is that the agent is engaged in the activities in a particular way—namely, with care,
attention, seriousness, focus, or love; rather than idly, frivolously, inattentively, half-
heartedly, or distractedly. This is because to engage in a practice ‘seriously’, ‘with
care, focus, attention’, or, most strongly, ‘with love for what one is doing’ are simply
alternative names for what has been termed here ‘engaging in a practice in pursuit
of its internal goods’. Words like ‘care’, ‘focus’ and ‘love’ (and so on) refer to the
agent’s on-going attentiveness and responsiveness to those internal goods. For to talk
of ‘internal goods’ is to talk about those things that make the practice worth doing
(for that agent)—they are what the agent cares about; what she is attending to; what
she values; what she loves.
Let us now return to the objection that children have ‘childish’ desires, and there-
fore lack the sophistication to desire such internal goods. As mentioned above, what
this misses is the point that human practices are dialectical. What this means, to recall
the previous chapter’s discussions, is that the internal goods of a practice are (if all
goes well) progressively revealed to the agent, by her on-going engagement in the
practice. So, for example, I come to grasp the internal goods of music-making—or,
what excellence in music-making demands of me—through making music. That is,
agents begin a practice with only the most inchoate, inarticulate sense of its internal
goods, but then that sense develops, ramifies, becomes more sophisticated, through
the agent’s engagement in the practice.
This point about the dialectical nature of practices, helps us to see the kind of
unities, or continuities, that exist in human activity. The most sophisticated forms of
human practices have their origins in fundamental human desires and motivations;
those practices are immensely complex developments, or elaborations, of much sim-
pler or more basic activities and desires. As Holt repeatedly emphasises, the most
sophisticated sorts of inquiry—in physics and chemistry, for example—have their
roots in fundamental human feelings of wonder and curiosity, and are developments
of the most basic forms of inquiry that humans engage in. Holt thus writes that,
children have a passionate desire to understand as much of the world as they can, even what
they cannot see and touch, and as far as possible to acquire some kind of skill, competence,
and control in it and over it. (Holt 1989, p. 159)
And that,
Children are born passionately eager to make as much sense as they can of things around them.
The process by which children turn experience into knowledge is exactly the same, point
for point, as the process by which those whom we call scientists make scientific knowledge.
Children observe, they wonder, they speculate, and they ask themselves questions. They
think up possible answers, they make theories, they hypothesise, and then they test theories
by asking questions or by further observations or experiments or reading. Then they modify
the theories as needed, or reject them, and the process continues. (Holt 1989, p. 94)
telling the child he had to study Physics in order to find out about the jet engine would be
like telling him he had to study initial and final consonants, digraphs, and blends in order
to find out what words say and mean. With such advice we cut him off from his intention,
his purpose, send him on a long detour. We put things backwards. Physics is not going to
lead the child to jet engines, but wondering about jet planes will lead him to Physics. In fact,
wondering about jet planes is Physics. The child asking such a question is doing Physics.
(Holt 1976, p. 84)
Hence Holt’s confidence that, given the right surroundings, children will “find within
themselves their reasons for doing worthwhile things” (Holt 1981, p. 113).
As a way of drawing this essay to a close, it is worth remarking here how Holt’s
view of the profound continuity that exists between children’s practices of inquiry,
and those of sophisticated practitioners, sidesteps a significant problem that exists
for those liberal philosophies of education that focus on the achievement of auton-
omy as the primary goal of education. These views descend from Kant, who draws
a sharp distinction between ‘heteronomy’ and ‘autonomy’. For Kant, heteronomy
was a state of being ruled by one’s desires (thus seen as ‘external’ to one’s self),
whilst autonomy was a state of being ruled by reason—which, for Kant, was gen-
uine human freedom and agency. This dichotomy thus entails that, for a Kantian,
education is a site of profound tension—because it is supposed to lead children from
one side of this dichotomy to the other. Children begin, in this picture, as existing in
a state of heteronomy, driven by their desires. They therefore need to be disciplined
and controlled through external motivations (‘bribe’ and ‘threat’, in other words), as
appeals to reason are ineffective. However, the whole raison d’être of this constraint
is, somehow, to transform them into autonomous adults. Hence, for a Kantian, edu-
cation must answer the question: “How do I cultivate freedom under constraint?”
(Kant 2007, 9: 453). And in case it is thought that this picture is a relic of the eigh-
teenth century, it is worth pointing out that we find precisely the same dichotomy at
work, for example, in Amy Gutmann’s influential book Democratic Education. She
writes there that, “The earliest education of children is not and cannot be by precept
or reasoning; it must be by discipline and example” (Gutmann 1999, p. 50); hence,
“Being educated as a child entails being ruled” (p. 3).
It should be clear by now that Holt rejects this Kantian picture root and branch.
For reasons we have explored in the previous chapter, he argues that the external
56 3 Objections and Replies
In this graph, the horizontal axis (labelled ‘t’) is time. The vertical axis (labelled ‘u’)
is utility, which is economists’ jargon for what, in more ordinary language, might
3.3 Objection #2: Disagreeable Hard Work 57
be called ‘pleasure’ or ‘satisfaction’. Above the junction with the horizontal axis is
‘positive utility’; below is ‘negative utility’ (i.e., displeasure, or dissatisfaction). The
progression of time—from A, to B, to C—represents (in a very simplified, schematic
form) an agent’s engagement in a practice. At the beginning (the interval A–B), the
agent is learning basic skills and the work is hard and unpleasant; the agent obtains
only negative utility from the activity. But at a certain point (B), this investment of
effort begins to pay off, and, thanks to her greater skills, the agent begins to obtain
pleasure from the activity. Eventually, ‘hedonic adaptation’ sets in and the practice
becomes boring or pleasureless to the agent (C).1 Taken as a whole (the interval
A–C), the learning of the practice has been worth doing, because the total amount
of pleasure (represented here as the area between the horizontal axis and the line
from B to C) that the agent obtains, is greater than her total amount of displeasure
(represented here as the area between the horizontal axis and the line from A to B).
To make this schema less abstract, let us consider an example; say, learning to
play the cello. The thought is then that, at the beginning, the cello playing is only a
source of dissatisfaction or displeasure to the agent—it is, that is to say, disagreeable
hard work. She struggles to hit the notes with accuracy, has to take great efforts even
to play short passages of simple music, her hands and forearms quickly get sore;
in sum, she is unable to play in any way that gives her pleasure. However, if she
perseveres with this frustration, she will reach a point (B) where she will start to
get pleasure from her music-making—her fingers can find the right notes with ease;
she can play more complex and therefore interesting pieces; she no longer finds the
music-making as physically and mentally taxing.
Now, given this model, we can make clear sense of what the objection is claiming.
It is saying that children (typically? always?) are not prepared, off their own bats,
to make the investment of time and effort represented by the interval A–B. That is,
they are not prepared to commit to the investment of this disagreeable hard work,
even though, if they were to do this, there would be a pay-off of lots of pleasure
or satisfaction for them forthcoming in interval B–C. To be incapable of putting up
with displeasure in the short term, so as to be able to gain greater pleasure in the
long term, is to lack the capacity for deferred gratification. The lack of this capacity
is, as Frank Ramsey puts it in a classic discussion, a “weakness of the imagination”
(Ramsey 1928, p. 543): one is so consumed by the present displeasure (in A–B) that
one is unable to make ‘living’ (and hence motivating) for oneself the thought of the
much greater pleasure to come (in B–C).
Given the supposed lack of this capacity in children, it would therefore seem to
be an appropriate role for educators to incentivise children so that they will do the
disagreeable hard work required to start gaining utility from the practice. That is, the
educator’s role would be to provide external motivations so that children will get to
B, at which point internal motivations (i.e., the utility obtained by the agent from the
activity) can take over. The educator can thus say, with truth, “I am doing this for
your own good, and you will thank me for it in the future”.
1 Elster’s
assumption of hedonic adaptation is not essential to the point being made; the agent’s
pleasure could flatten out, rather than declining back to zero.
58 3 Objections and Replies
According to the objection, then, Holt’s whole model of the ‘best learning’ and cri-
tique of education make sense only on the assumption that children have the capacity
for deferred gratification, but this is not something they tend to possess. Therefore
much important learning (especially at the early stages) needs to proceed via the
impetus provided by external motivations. And therefore children need professional
teachers, compulsory schooling, the Department of Education, and the rest …
Holt’s response to this objection is to point out that the very idea of ‘deferred grat-
ification’ takes for granted the instrumentalist conception of activity that he rejects.
This is because it conceptualises pleasure (utility, satisfaction) as an external good
and the activity as a means to that external good. That is, it treats the pleasure as
something that is conceptually separable from the activity, and ‘produced’ by the
activity as a ‘goal’ or ‘output’. The pleasure thereby provides the motive or incentive
for the agent to undertake the activity (or provides a disincentive, in the case of dis-
pleasure). In doing this, the objection treats effort as something that an agent finds
unpleasant, and hence will engage in only in return for an adequate ‘pay off’. Holt
thinks this entire model—with its instrumentalist conception of the relation between
activity, effort, and pleasure—is utterly mistaken. As he writes,
They say that to do anything takes Disagreeable Hard Work, that all work is Disagreeable
Hard Work. In those three words is a whole way of life and of looking at life, very widespread,
very deeply rooted, and very wrong. (Holt 1972, p. 110)
The way to dig out this deeply rooted instrumentalism is to begin with a reconceptual-
isation of the notion of pleasure. Once again, Aristotle offers us the best starting point
for this. In the Nichomachean Ethics, he argues that the pleasure we take in activity is
not a separate ‘sensation’, which is produced by our doings. Rather, Aristotle writes,
“pleasure completes the activity” (Aristotle 1984, 1175a5; my emphasis), and that it
“supervenes” on the activity “as the bloom of youth does on those in the flower of
their age” (1174b33). For this reason, pleasure in an activity is conceptually tied to
the love of an activity—in that “each kind of person finds pleasure in whatever he is
called a lover of” (1099a8-9).
Gilbert Ryle gives a clear account of what Aristotle means by this talk of pleasure
as ‘completing’ and ‘supervening’ on an activity. In The Concept of Mind, and in his
1954 paper “Pleasure”, Ryle argues that to take pleasure in an activity, or to enjoy it,
is not for certain sensations to accompany the activity, or result from it. Rather, it is
to perform the activity in a certain way, namely, to perform it wholeheartedly, or in
a deeply absorbed way. He writes that,
when a child is absorbed in a game he—every drop of him—is sucked up into the business
of manipulating his clockwork trains. … His game is, for the moment, his whole world.
(Ryle 2009, p. 346)
And this absorption just is for that child to enjoy, or take pleasure in, that game. For,
to say that a person has been enjoying digging is not to say that he has been both digging and
doing or experiencing something else as a concomitant or effect of the digging; it is to say
that he dug with his whole heart in his task, i.e. that he dug, wanting to dig and not wanting
to do anything else. (Ryle 1990, p. 104)
3.3 Objection #2: Disagreeable Hard Work 59
As Talbot Brewer points out, Ryle’s verbal formulation here is potentially misleading.
Imagine a person performing an activity under threat of death. No doubt this person
would be reluctant to stop, and would indeed be likely to be absorbed in that activity.
However, we would hardly talk of a person in such circumstances ‘taking pleasure’
in the activity. Brewer thus suggests that a better way of capturing Ryle’s point is to
say that,
to take pleasure in an activity is to engage in that activity while being absorbed in it, where
this absorption consists in single-minded and lively attention to whatever it is that makes the
activity good or worth pursuing. (Brewer 2009, p. 116)
This formulation captures not just the sense in which ‘taking pleasure in’ a certain
activity ‘completes’ or ‘supervenes on’ the activity, but also Aristotle’s point about
the connection between taking pleasure in an activity and the agent’s love of that
activity. Taking pleasure in an activity is to be deeply absorbed in that activity for
its own sake (i.e., for the sake of the internal goods of that activity); that is, it is for
an agent to do it wholeheartedly, out of love for the activity. Pleasure thus lies in the
quality of attention that an agent brings to an activity.
There are closely related thoughts in another of the great critics of instrumen-
talism, Karl Marx. In the Grundrisse, Marx discusses Adam Smith’s assumption
that human beings naturally prefer ‘ease’ or ‘leisure’, and therefore require incen-
tives in order to engage in anything requiring effort. In capitalism, of course, this
incentive is a wage. This thought of Smith’s directly parallels the model of deferred
gratification discussed above, except in this latter case, the incentive or ‘wage’ is
the promised future pay-off of pleasure or utility. For Marx, the instrumentalist split
between ‘leisure’ and ‘work’—which is given social reality in a capitalist econo-
my—is simultaneously a degradation of both human activity, and pleasure. This is
because, on the one hand, it reduces pleasure to “mere fun”—an end to be derived
from trivial “amusement”; whilst making genuinely effortful activity a mere means
for earning a wage, undertaken only under compulsion. In contrast, Marx writes,
“Really free working, e.g., composing, is at the same time the most damned serious,
intensive exertion”, for the “overcoming of obstacles is in itself a liberating activity”
(Marx 1973, p. 611). That is, given the right social circumstances, humans will freely
choose to engage in activities that require great effort, and will take great joy in that
doing. With these words of Marx in mind, consider the following passage from Holt
about his great love, music:
The assumption is that while playing music we vary from the ‘no fun’ end of the scale to
the ‘fun’ end. If we spend 99 percent of our time at the ‘no fun’ end of the scale, eventually
we will get to the point where we have a little fun. I think this is a disastrously mistaken
way of looking at music. Nowhere on that scale of ‘no fun’ to ‘fun’ can I find any of the
emotions that I feel when I am working with my cello. These range from arduous effort to
intense concentration, great frustration and exasperation to something that can only be called
60 3 Objections and Replies
exaltation. There are feelings so deep that one can barely play the music. You can’t use the
word fun to describe that range of feeling. (Holt 1989, pp. 123–4)
What these thinkers—Aristotle, Marx, Ryle, Brewer—show us, is that the claim
that children cannot engage in practices because they ‘lack a capacity for deferred
gratification’ is itself a result of a weakness of the imagination. This is because such
a claim can only conceive of agency and motivation in instrumental terms, viewing
the agent’s activity as a means for maximising pleasure (or utility). However, what
Aristotle and the others remind us, is that we are not forced to think of matters in this
way. Instead, we can recapture the thought that—in the magnificent words of Albert
Borgmann (1984, p. 202)—when engaging wholeheartedly in human practices, the
agent finds that her “effort and joy are one; the split between means and ends, labor
and leisure is healed”.
Holt is part of this alternative tradition of non-instrumental ways of thinking of
activity and agency, and the thoughts sketched above can help us to see the clear
sense in what he says about ‘deferred gratification’. To begin with, Holt points to
the obvious empirical fact that children just do engage in activities that demand
great effort. Indeed, as he reminds us, it is one of the salient characteristics of young
children that they live with great intensity, throwing the whole of themselves into
what they do. It is thus common to find them “in that dreamlike state children get
into when they are really absorbed in something. [In which] Time meant nothing”
(Holt 1983, p. 265). Hence, as Holt writes,
Anyone who has known many children growing up knows that many of them, even though
they may not have much time of their own after school and schoolwork, throw themselves
with great energy and discipline into very demanding kinds of work, often much harder than
the work they can’t or don’t do in school, often involving the very ‘skills’ that the school
says they don’t have and can’t learn. (Holt 1972, p. 115)
Holt also argues against the idea—embedded in the model of delayed gratification
discussed above—that the initial stages of a difficult venture must involve unpleas-
antness, some sense of “uphill struggle” or “going against the grain”, and that “sat-
isfaction” comes later (as claimed in Elster 1985, p. 89). Holt suggests that it is only
when instrumentalist conceptions of ‘success’ and ‘failure’ raise their head, that this
is the case. For example, he writes that,
Babies learning to walk, and falling down as they try, or healthy six- and seven-year-olds
learning to ride a bike, and falling off, do not think, each time they fall, “I failed again”.
Healthy babies or children, tackling difficult projects of their own choosing, think only when
they fall down or off, “Oops, not yet, try again”. Nor do they think, when finally they begin to
walk or ride, “Oh, boy, I’m succeeding!” They think, “Now I’m walking! Now I’m riding!”
The joy is in the act itself, the walking or the riding, not in some idea of success. … Children
… do not think in terms of success and failure but of effort and adventure. (Holt 1982,
pp. 69–70; my emphasis)
3.3 Objection #2: Disagreeable Hard Work 61
Or, consider this passage from Escape From Childhood, with its echoes of the state-
ments from Marx and Borgmann quoted above:
there is something very appealing and exciting about watching children just learning to walk.
They do it so badly, it is so clearly difficult, and in the child’s terms may even be dangerous.
… Most adults, even many older children, would instantly stop trying to do anything that they
did as badly as a new walker does his walking. But the infant keeps on. He is so determined,
he is working so hard, and he is so excited; his learning to walk is not just an effort and
struggle but a joyous adventure. (Holt 1974, pp. 119–20; my emphasis)
These obvious empirical facts only appear difficult to explain if one is wedded to
the instrumentalist conceptions of activity and pleasure. We do not need to ascribe
to these children some complex feat of rationality and imagination, in which they
are calculating the total amount of future pleasure to be gained from walking or
riding and weighing that against the current displeasure of investing an effort in
learning to do this. Rather than this preposterous picture of the child as a miniature
Homo economicus, we simply need to remind ourselves that these children are doing
things they want to do—often things that are “the most damned serious, intensive
exertion”—and doing them wholeheartedly—and that this just is what it is to take
pleasure in what one is doing. That is, to repeat Borgmann’s words, in such activities
the children’s effort and their joy are one and the same. Hence, as Holt concludes,
It is a serious mistake to say that, in order to learn, children must first be able to ‘delay
gratification’ … It is their desire and determination to do real things, not in the future but
right now, that gives children the curiosity, energy, determination, and patience to learn all
they learn. (Holt 1983, p. 288)
Wolf, e.g., who is otherwise a fine debunker of many of the myths surrounding education, takes it
62 3 Objections and Replies
In his book Freedom and Beyond, Holt ends his lengthy discussion of
these issues—of the creed of ‘disagreeable hard work’ and its instrumentalist assump-
tions—by quoting the last stanza of Robert Frost’s poem “Two Tramps in Mud Time”
(at Holt 1972, p. 117; quote corrected):
But yield who will to their separation,
My object in living is to unite
My avocation with my vocation
As my two eyes make one in sight.
Only where love and need are one,
And the work is play for mortal stakes,
Is the deed ever really done,
For Heaven and the future’s sakes.
for granted—asking her reader: “How much work do you do without either an immediate incentive
or a deadline?” (2002, p. 289, n. 2), and clearly expecting the answer ‘not much’. The word doing
the work in Wolf’s question is, of course, ‘work’.
3.4 Objection #3: Noble Savages 63
conflict between the natural individual and the oppressive and corrupting effects of organised
social life. (Franzosa 1984, p. 231)
Both Franzosa and Morgan, then, suggest that Holt’s view presupposes a dichoto-
mous split between ‘nature’ and ‘culture’ (or ‘organised social life’), which exist in
‘irreconcilable conflict’. ‘Nature’ is authenticity, whilst ‘culture’ is the corruption
of that authenticity. Given this framework, Holt’s call for freedom in learning is
then understood as involving the following argument: authenticity is the key good,
and therefore children must be left as free from cultural or social influence as possi-
ble—for only with such freedom can they develop naturally, and hence authentically.
Both Franzosa and Morgan then argue that such a view—a crudely lop-sided carica-
ture of Rousseau—is deeply problematic on a number of grounds.
The position they ascribe to Holt is certainly problematic; indeed, it is preposter-
ous. However, it bears almost no relation to the views he actually holds. Any careful
reading of Holt’s works will readily refute the claim that he believes anything like
this, but the citation of a couple of relevant passages will suffice here. First, consider
the following passage from Teach Your Own:
Many people who quite like and enjoy children still seem to be in the grip of the old idea
that in civilising them we have to give up or destroy some important part of them. To me that
idea seems mistaken and harmful. … Many free schools, and some kindly and well-meaning
parents, have suffered from the notion that there was something wild and precious in children
that had to be preserved against the attacks of the world for as long as possible. Once we get
free of this idea we will find our lives with children much easier and children themselves
much happier. … basically [children] want to fit in, take part, and do right—that is, do as we
do. (Holt 1981, p. 100)
And, a decade previously, in Freedom and Beyond, after a careful discussion of the
“natural authority” of adults (Holt 1972, p. 64), Holt writes that,
Man is a social, a cultural animal. Children sense around them this culture, this network of
agreements, customs, habits, and rules binding the adults together. They want to understand
it and be a part of it. They watch very carefully what people around them are doing and want
to do the same. They want to do right, unless they become convinced they can’t do right.
(Holt 1972, p. 106)
64 3 Objections and Replies
As Holt’s talk of ‘agreements’ and ‘rules’ makes clear, this social context is pro-
foundly normative—it involves questions of what is right and wrong; correct and
incorrect; appropriate and inappropriate; what is valuable and what is valueless;
what matters and does not matter; what ought to be done and what ought not to be
done. From this it follows that the social context involves constraints. Hence it is, as
Holt points out, simply an obvious fact that, “As there is no life without structure,
so there is no life without constraints” (Holt 1972, p. 25). Furthermore, this net-
work of rules and agreements gives adults certain kinds of normative authority over
children—the adults, for example, know the rules when the children may not. There-
fore, as Holt writes, “we [adults] often and rightly intervene in the lives of children”
(Holt 1972, p. 57; my emphasis).
This textual evidence demonstrates that Holt does not in the least believe (as
Franzosa claims he does) that there is an “irreconcilable conflict between the natural
individual and the oppressive and corrupting effects of organised social life”. Holt
does not think that there is a dichotomy between ‘nature’ and ‘culture’. Nor does he
hold that there is some pre-cultural or a-cultural notion of ‘authenticity’. Nor does
he hold the absurd view that children ought to be free from all social constraints. The
objection’s suggestion that Holt has some sentimentalised notion of the child as ‘a
kind of noble savage’ is thus without merit.
However, we now need to consider whether a less extreme version of the objec-
tion has some truth to it; in particular, whether Holt believes—as Morgan suggests
in the passage quoted above—that “all the learning that is thought desirable … can
be found to be naturally motivated from within the child”. Whether this is a cor-
rect description of Holt’s position or not, all depends upon how we take the words
‘naturally’ and ‘from within’. As Morgan glosses it, it means that the child develops
certain motivations (to learn) independently of any social influence or interaction.
We have already seen that this cannot be Holt’s view, for at no point does he speak
of the individual-independent-of-society (there is no such thing), but only of the
individual-in-her-social-context.
Holt’s account certainly starts from the premise that almost all children, from
a very young age, are profoundly moved by motivations of wonder, curiosity, and
desires for competence in the world. He would suggest that this is simply a basic
empirical fact about young human beings—and I see no reason to disagree. Infants
and young children who lack these fundamental motivations—as in cases of brain
injury, or severe deprivation—we see as profoundly damaged or disabled. This is not
to claim, however, that the particular form that these motivations take is ‘pre-cultural’
or ‘a-cultural’. For Holt, as we have seen, there is simply no point in talking about
what the child might be like in a ‘pre-cultural’ or ‘a-cultural’ state, for to be human
is to exist in a social context—in ‘this network of agreements, customs, habits, and
rules’. The question of what sorts of motivations and desires would exist in an infant
raised by wolves may be of interest to some, but—at least until large numbers of our
children are raised by wolves—it is not a question that we need to answer in order
to think clearly about learning and education.
Hence, while Holt would perhaps agree that curiosity, wonder, and desires for
competence exist ‘naturally’ in a child, the particular forms that those motivations
3.4 Objection #3: Noble Savages 65
and desires take will always be socially inflected. As we have seen, Holt argues that
the ‘best learning’ occurs through undertaking practices for their own sake. Such
autotelic activity begins with the child glimpsing something of the internal goods
of a practice—some glimpse of the beauty or power of music; of the understanding
produced by an explanation; of a piece of mathematics ‘making sense’; of the chal-
lenges inherent in some sport or game, etc. But which practices the child is exposed
to, and which ones will appear particularly valuable or significant, will all depend
upon the social context in which the child lives. After all, children grow up in a world
primarily structured by adult concerns and values, and they are deeply influenced by
what activities the adults around them treat with seriousness of purpose, and what
activities the adults consider contemptible or trivial.
At this point we can thus dispose of the suggestion that Holt’s views consign
adults to an entirely passive, or merely facilitative, role in respect to children and
their desires. This is a common critique of ‘child-centred’ approaches to learning.
Barrow, for example, has argued that ‘radical educators’ like Holt must, if they are
to be true to their own principles, facilitate a child in pursuing whatever interests
it has—suggesting that they are committed to the view that “if something interests
somebody at a particular time it is for that reason a good thing for him to be doing
it”. He then raises the obvious counter-example: “Suppose a child has an interest
in torturing cats. Shall I put information, sharp knives and a cat at his disposal?”
(Barrow 1978, p. 103). R. S. Peters makes a similar argument, in more measured
tones, remarking that,
The child-centred teacher [has] the moral problem of choosing between letting children
pursue their interests, which may be not at all in their interest, and getting them to pursue
what is in their interest. (Peters 1966, pp. 35–6)
Barrow et alii are claiming that someone with a view like Holt’s is confronted by a
dilemma. Either—they claim—Holt must permit the child to pursue whatever inter-
ests she happens to have at the time, even when such pursuit may be harmful to the
child, or he must allow that adults have a role in providing external motivations to
push the child to pursue things that the child is not presently interested in—which
would seem to be inconsistent with his broader views on the ‘best learning’. How-
ever, this dilemma is generated by a false assumption. To begin with, Holt’s position
is not that whatever interests a child should be encouraged; rather, it is the converse
of this, that whatever activities are encouraged should link to interests (desires, moti-
vations) of the child. This erroneous understanding of what Holt is saying is further
encouraged by the critics’ failure to see the fundamental continuity (as emphasised
in my reply to Objection #1) between the interests of children and those of adults.
As discussed above, Holt suggests (with good reason) that all children—unless pro-
foundly damaged—have deep motivations of wonder and curiosity, and desires for
66 3 Objections and Replies
competence in the adult world. Given this, all children have the desires that are the
starting points of a vast range of valuable human practices—and practices of inquiry
in particular.
The objection that Holt presupposes some ‘pre-cultural’ or ‘a-cultural’ conception
of the child, with its ‘natural’ motivations, that must be left uninfluenced by society
in order to develop ‘authentically’, thus misses the mark. However, this objection is a
response to something in Holt; it does not come from nowhere. What it is a response
to, is Holt’s repeated insistence on the importance of the freedom of the learner.
As I have argued, this does not mean that the learner is free from the influence of
human society, for only a wolf-child is free in that sense. It means that the learner
learns best when she is able to engage in practices for their own sake rather than as
efficient means to external ends. However, this raises the question of how engaging
in a practice can yet be freedom. For, it might be thought, to engage in a practice is
to be subject to the standards of excellence that constitute that practice. And, as Holt
himself notes, to learn many practices may therefore entail engaging in activities that
are,
very tightly and rigidly structured. Any school of dance or the martial arts puts the students
under the most intense and inflexible discipline. Watch students in a ballet or karate class at
their work. As long as they stay in the class, they have no choices at all. Now, the instructor
tells them, move like this. Arms move, legs move, all together. Go when I say go. Stop when
I say stop. (Holt 1976, p. 21)
To understand how this ‘most intense and inflexible discipline’ can yet be freedom,
it is worth looking more closely at how Holt’s position compares to that of Rousseau,
who faced a closely related problem in his philosophy of education. That is, to be
clear, we need to compare Holt to the real Rousseau, rather than to a simple-minded
caricature who talks of the child as a ‘noble savage’.
Stated briefly, the problem that Rousseau undertakes to solve in his novel Émile
is as follows. A child needs to be made a member of a society, and thus brought into
a normative order (that ‘network of agreements, customs, habits, and rules’ of which
Holt speaks). The usual way that this is done, Rousseau notes, is through the overt
imposition of another’s will on the child—the baby is swaddled, the young child is
told what to do, and beaten if he does not do it. These impositions the child thinks of as
injustices, and they inflame his amour propre—the concern that all humans possess
for their right recognition as a fellow being in the eyes of others (cf. Rosenow 1980;
Dent 1988). Over time, this produces an adult who suffers from a profound internal
conflict—a fragmentation of the self—in that his desires will tend to run in opposition
to what is required of him by social norms (thus, his duties, obligations, and the like).
As Rousseau writes,
He who in the civil order wants to preserve the primacy of the sentiments of nature does
not know what he wants. Always in contradiction with himself, always floating between his
inclinations and his duties, he will never be either man or citizen. (Rousseau 1979, p. 40)
For such people, neither freedom nor sincerity is possible; they can neither
wholeheartedly do what they desire to do, nor wholeheartedly avow what they believe
(cf. Williams 2002, Chap. 5).
3.4 Objection #3: Noble Savages 67
Rousseau argues that this manipulation (what we might call a behavioural condition-
ing) produces an integrated psyche whose desires have been shaped to correspond
to social norms. Those social norms are thus perceived by that psyche as necessities
and as ‘natural’, rather than as the imposition of an alien will. As Émile remarks at
the end of the book, “I would want only what is and therefore would never have to
struggle against destiny” (Rousseau 1979, p. 472). Émile, in other words, has become
a true citizen, who wholeheartedly desires to do what he ought to do.
Before relating this back to Holt, it is worth noting how Aristotle’s concept of
virtue provides a solution to a structurally parallel problem. As discussed in the
previous chapter, a virtue relates to the will, in that to ascribe a virtue to a person is,
in part, to ascribe to them certain sorts of desires and motivations. The virtuous person,
that is, is someone who not only knows the right act to perform in the circumstances,
but also wants to perform that act. In this way, in Aristotle’s account, the virtues
give unity to the psyche—it is through possession of the virtues that the agent will
experience no internal conflicts between her desires and the felt demands of social
norms.
Now, Holt is not operating on as large a metaphysical canvas as these philoso-
phers, but he faces a similar problem in his own domain of learning. As noted above,
68 3 Objections and Replies
Rousseau sought to resolve the problem of how to bring children into a society (a
normative order) without the overt imposition of another’s will. The solution given in
Émile may not be directly coercive, but there is no doubt that it is profoundly manip-
ulative. In contrast to Rousseau, Holt’s main focus is not with children’s relation to
broader social norms, but he is concerned with their entry into the normative orders of
practices. That is, Holt’s question is how children can come to accept the normative
demands of practices (such as mathematics, reading, music, and so on) without the
imposition of an educator’s will. In other words, how is freedom in learning possible?
Holt’s solution to this question contains a significant conceptual advance over
Rousseau. For Rousseau, the only way for an agent to come to accept a normative
demand is by way of the imposition of another’s will. That is why the only alternative
that Rousseau sees to the overt imposition of that will, is its covert imposition; hence
the tutor’s deceptive manipulation of Émile’s environment. Holt, however, distin-
guishes between two kinds of what he terms ‘discipline’. On the one hand, there is
what he terms the “Discipline of Superior Force” (Holt 1972, p. 107), which corre-
sponds to Rousseau’s notion of the imposition of another’s will. Unlike Rousseau,
Holt sees nothing wrong with such coercion per se—writing that, “There is bound to
be some of this in a child’s life. Living as we do surrounded by things that can hurt
children, or that children can hurt, we cannot avoid it” (Holt 1972, 107). But, as we
have seen, Holt argues that there is no place for the exercise of such ‘superior force’
in learning—in coercing people into learning one thing rather than another. There
is, however, a place in learning for another kind of discipline, Holt’s term for which
is the “Discipline of Culture, of Society, of What People Really Do” (Holt 1972,
p. 106). This concept—which is not visible to Rousseau—allows Holt to resolve the
question of how freedom in learning is possible, for it allows us to make good sense
of the idea of an agent’s willing submission to norms.
In order to understand this, consider Holt’s two paradigm examples of learning, to
which he returns again and again in his works: the infant’s acquisition of language,
and learning to play a musical instrument. In neither case, does it make the least
sense to think of the learner as beginning ab initio, and inventing this knowledge
from the ground up. As Holt writes,
We do not ask or expect a child to invent the wheel starting from scratch. He doesn’t have
to. The wheel has been invented. It is out there, in front of him. … The whole culture is out
there. (Holt 1983, p. 290)
This is thus how Holt resolves the problem of freedom in learning. Through
engagement in a practice, the internal goods of that practice are progressively revealed
to the agent and made her own. Such engagement is, therefore, not the imposition of
another’s will on the agent, but a process of the agent’s self-transformation. This is
clearly expressed by MacIntyre, who contrasts the model in which
the educator takes her or himself not only to know more, but also to know best, … to know
what is genuinely good for others, something that they do not themselves know. Hence
educators suppose themselves to be entitled to impose upon others their conception of the
good. (MacIntyre 1994, p. 287)
This is the coercive or manipulative model of education that Holt rejects—it is, in
his words, “the ugly and antihuman business of people-shaping” (Holt 1976, p. 4).
It involves the imposition of another’s will (justified, of course, on the paternalistic
grounds that the educators ‘know best … what is genuinely good for others’). In
contrast to this, MacIntyre writes, there is
quite another kind of practice, one such that those engaged in it transform themselves and
educate themselves through their own self-transformative activity, coming to understand
their good as the good internal to that activity. (MacIntyre 1994, p. 287)
As should now be clear, this is the sort of ‘doing’ and ‘best learning’ of which Holt
speaks. Through such activity, engaged in for its own sake, the self is transformed.
The agent enters a normative order, not through coercion or manipulation by another,
but through her willing submission to the internal standards of excellence of the
practice. Her submission is willing, because through that activity those standards
progressively reveal themselves to her as goods—as valuable, significant, and worth
pursuing, in themselves (not simply as a means to some external end). And this is why
engagement with practices is, as MacIntyre writes, a self-transformative activity; a
deep expression of agency.
Despite its emphasis on the freedom of the learner, Holt’s position can thus be
seen, in an important sense, as an inversion of a ‘constructivist’ and ‘child-centred’
approach. Knowledge is not shaped to the learner’s desires and experience; on the
contrary, the learner shapes herself to the knowledge, by transforming her will.
Through progressively grasping the internal goods of the practices—as she develops
the virtues of those practices—her sense of what is valuable, significant, and worth
doing, is transformed. In other words, through engaging in practices, through her own
pursuit of their goods, the learner makes herself into a mathematician, a musician, a
joiner, a chess-player, a speaker of a language, etc.
Holt’s position is faced with a dilemma: either he is suggesting that teachers and
teaching have no role at all to play in learning, which is absurd; or he is saying
that teachers and teaching do have a legitimate role, in which case his ‘critique of
education’ is far less radical than it is claimed to be.
3.5 Objection #4: Teachers and Teaching 71
In order to answer this objection, more clarity is needed on how Holt’s views have
the conceptual space to provide, without inconsistency, a legitimate role for teachers
and explicit teaching. To begin with, as should be clear from the previous discussions
in this chapter, Holt does not think that learning is intrinsically or essentially a solitary
pursuit, nor does he hold the view that the learner must construct knowledge ab initio.
Even when Holt’s focus is on the individual child, exploring the world in her own
way, without direct assistance of any kind, this is not a view of the child as a sort of
Robinson Crusoe. For the world she is exploring is a deeply social one: a world of
normative order; of culture, communities, and human practices; of people engaged
together in various activities. Holt is thus clear that learning involves, in many cases,
learning from others. After all, he writes, it is just obvious that “you would be unlikely
to learn any complicated and difficult human activity without drawing heavily on the
experience of those who know it better” (Holt 1972, pp. 108–9). There are many
ways of learning from others; or, as he puts it in the subtitle of Instead of Education,
there are many ways “to help people do things better”.
There is little doubt that Holt’s views have been strongly associated with a par-
ticular way in which adults can help children learn, or ‘do things better’. This is the
thought that (particularly very young) children can best learn by being given access
to a rich and stimulating human world, and then allowed to explore it in their own
way, with no, or very few, episodes of explicit teaching. As he writes in the final
paragraph of Learning All the Time:
We can best help children learn, not by deciding what we think they should learn and thinking
of ingenious ways to teach it to them, but by making the world, so far as we can, accessible
to them, paying serious attention to what they do, answering their questions—if they have
any—and helping them explore the things they are most interested in. (Holt 1989, p. 162)
This sort of free exploration in the world is sometimes thought to be the essential and
appropriate method of ‘unschooling’, and there is no doubt that it is an approach that
Holt strongly emphasises. One reason for this is that such emphasis is an antidote
to the disempowering thought—implicit in much of the practice of our official edu-
cational institutions—that “everything, however trivial, must be deliberately taught”
(Holt 1971, p. 72). However, if we read the above passages in the broader context of
his work as a whole, it is clear that Holt recognises a huge variety of ways in which
people can learn from one another as being consistent with his views about learning
and education.
Holt’s works—in particular, Instead of Education (especially Chaps. 7–8), and
the many examples given in Teach Your Own—discuss a wide range of ways in
which people can help others ‘do things better’. As just remarked, he discusses the
many ways in which children can learn by doing things without any explicit kinds of
teaching. For example: through solitary activities, with adults simply being there as a
72 3 Objections and Replies
supportive presence, able to answer questions or offer advice when requested; through
cooperative play and fantasy with other children; through working with others at real-
world activities (by assisting with cooking meals, shopping for groceries, gardening,
etc.). However, along with these expected forms of ‘unschooling’ approaches, Holt
also discusses in many places various forms of explicit teaching, and the legitimate
role that teachers can play in the ‘best learning’. Hence, it is not the case that Holt’s
position rules out teaching and teachers per se. Rather, as he repeatedly remarks, “It
all depends on the spirit in which this is done” (Holt 1981, p. 154). So, to make sense
of how Holt can consistently hold this view, and thus answer the objection, we need
an account of just what this right ‘spirit’ is.
The answer to this question comes if we examine a passage in Instead of Education,
in which Holt is discussing a particularly authoritarian form of teaching, namely,
training in classical ballet. Such teaching—rigid in sequencing and structure, with
no room for individual choice—is a world away from the sort of ‘free exploration’ and
‘learning through play’ with which Holt and ‘unschooling’ is typically associated,
yet Holt sees it as entirely legitimate. The reason why Holt thinks such teaching is
compatible with his views about ‘best learning’ and the freedom of the learner comes
in the following passage, where he writes that,
the tasks that the dancing master gives the student make sense. The student can see, and feel
in his body, the connection between these beginning movements and the full skill and art
he wants to master. Indeed, the greatest dancers begin their work every day with the same
simple movements the student is trying to learn to do. (Holt 1976, p. 59; my emphasis)
In contrast to this, too often in the kind of teaching that is characteristic of ‘education’
(in Holt’s sense of the word), “The child cannot see any connection between the things
he is told to do, and the goal he at first wanted to reach” (Holt 1976, p. 59). These
remarks give us the criterion that distinguishes good ways of helping people to learn,
from harmful ways: the teacher must so act that the internal goods of the practice
remain in sight for the learner. Or, to put this criterion in the way that Holt states
it later in Instead of Education, the ‘doing’ must remain the project of the learner,
rather than becoming the project of the teacher (Holt 1976, p. 102).
This is another way of putting the point that was discussed in the previous chapter,
when we looked at Holt’s account of the role in music-making of exercises such as
scales, arpeggios, and the like. The key point reached in that discussion was that the
agent should not think of such exercises in instrumental terms, as efficient means to
certain ends. Rather, such exercises should be thought of as organic parts of a unified
practice of music-making—that is, as oriented to a pursuit of the internal goods of
that practice. In the same way, Holt is emphasising that the study of classical ballet
is composed of activities that the student can see as directly connected to the internal
goods of the practice. In this way, the ballet student’s study, whilst rigidly sequenced
and structured by the teacher, can be seen by the student as an organic part of his
(the student’s) engagement in the practice of ballet, oriented to its internal goods.
Hence, recalling the discussion of the previous objection above, the student can see
his own activity as a student not as a submission to the will of the individual who
is his teacher, but as a submission to the demands of ballet—and thus as part of
3.5 Objection #4: Teachers and Teaching 73
his own self-transformation into a ballet dancer. That is, although the teaching is
authoritarian, the student can grasp the exercise of that authority as embodying the
standards of excellence of the practice, rather than it simply appearing to him as the
more-or-less arbitrary will of the individual who is the teacher. All of this, of course,
presupposes that the student has chosen to undertake the practice of ballet for its own
sake—in pursuit of its internal goals. But, given such a choice, there is a clear and
legitimate role for explicit teaching.
However, Holt is also clear that this sort of explicit teaching carries dangers and
temptations with it. As he writes, “teaching is a very strong medicine, which like
all strong medicines can quickly and easily turn into a poison” (Holt 1978, p. 209).
As I have discussed, teaching (even of the most authoritarian kind) is legitimate
so long as the learner retains the locus of agency—that is to say, so long as the
activities engaged in under the teacher’s direction can be grasped by the learner as
organic parts of her own ‘project’, or unified engagement in a practice. The danger
of explicit teaching lies in the fact that it is all too easy for the locus of agency to shift
to the teacher. This is particularly the case when the teacher-student relationship is
strongly marked by other power dynamics, such as when the learner is a child and the
teacher an adult. This shift of agency occurs when the student can no longer grasp
his own activity as submission to the internal goods of the practice; that is, as Holt
puts it, when the student can no longer “see any connection between the things he
is told to do, and the goal he at first wanted to reach”. Rather, from the student’s
perspective it has become submission to the will of another—motivated by external
incentives and disincentives. To use Holt’s terms, it is no longer genuine ‘doing’;
instead, it is now ‘education’. When such a shift of agency occurs, the teacher thus
becomes an educator: someone who, in the words of Alasdair MacIntyre in the
passage quoted above, “know[s] what is genuinely good for others, something that
they do not themselves know”.
As discussed in the previous chapter, this form of teaching, in which the agency
lies with the teacher rather than with the student, promotes various vices of practices.
In particular, it tends to promote what we might term the vices of disempowerment
and alienation: passivity, helplessness, intellectual cowardice, and the like. As Holt
writes,
Most of our schools convey to children a very powerful message, that they are stupid,
worthless, untrustworthy, unfit to make even the smallest decisions about their own lives or
learning. (Holt 1970, p. 56)
This is alienation because, by its very form, teaching of this nature tends to encourage
the student to think that she is unable to be the agent of her own transformation, but
must instead be transformed by the hands of another—the teacher. In this way, the
student comes to think that the teacher is the source of something that is, in fact, her
own capacity. At this point, it is worth recalling a fable told by the great anarchist
thinker Errico Malatesta, who asks us to imagine that,
a man who had had his limbs bound from his birth, but had nevertheless found out how to
hobble about, might attribute to the very hands that bound him his ability to move, while,
74 3 Objections and Replies
on the contrary, they would be diminishing and paralyzing the muscular energy of his limbs.
(Malatesta 2013, p. 2)
In this fable, Malatesta was talking of how we come to think of the capacity of organ-
isation as something that is provided by government (without which we would exist
in chaos), when in fact (he argues) government is entirely parasitic upon the ordi-
nary human capacity for self-organisation and mutual aid. Holt’s views run parallel
to Malatesta’s thought: education, Holt argues, encourages us to think that valuable
learning is a product of teaching; that we can learn anything significant only by being
taught according to another’s conception of the good; that any learning we gain for
ourselves, outside of credential-granting institutions, is therefore trivial and worth-
less. Yet, Holt is saying, all such instrumentalised learning is only a ‘hobbling’ of
our deep capacities for self-reliance, self-organisation, and self-transformation.
Holt in fact suggests that not only is teaching a ‘strong medicine’ that must be
used sparingly if it is not to work against the student’s ‘best learning’, but also that
it contains within it something potentially corrupting of the teacher. In Instead of
Education, Holt approvingly cites Illich’s angry disavowal of the role (addressed
to an audience member at a symposium): “Please sit down. I am not your teacher”
(quoted in Holt 1976, p. 108). And in a 1978 letter to Illich, Holt writes that,
I find myself thinking, saying, and writing more and more in recent months that the very
idea of a full-time teacher is deeply mistaken, that whatever teaching we do we ought to
do as an incidental part of the rest of our life. I hardly think any more that it’s possible to
be a full-time teacher, I don’t care [in] what kind of school or institutional setting, without
corrupting the relationships between oneself and other people. (Holt 1990, pp. 215–6)
As a contrast to help to make this point clearer, consider the character of Socrates,
as Plato presents him. It is a cliché that Socrates is one of the ‘great teachers’ of
history. But, in an important sense, Socrates is not a teacher. He himself states this
in the Apology as clearly as anyone can:
I have never set up as any man’s teacher, but if anyone, young or old, is eager to hear me
conversing and carrying out my private mission, I never grudge him the opportunity; nor
do I charge a fee for talking to him, and refuse to talk without one. I am ready to answer
questions for rich and poor alike, and I am equally ready if anyone prefers to listen to me and
answer my questions. If any given one of these people becomes a good citizen or a bad one,
I cannot fairly be held responsible, since I have never promised or imparted any teaching to
anybody, and if anyone asserts that he has ever learned or heard from me privately anything
which was not open to everyone else, you may be quite sure that he is not telling the truth.
(Plato 1961, 33a–b)
I can, of course, learn from Socrates—and Plato clearly wants us to do that. But
Socrates never speaks and acts with the intention of producing learning in others; he
does not view his own words and acts as instruments in this way.3 Indeed, it is a core
part of his critique of the Sophists and the rhetoricians that they view their words
as instruments in just such a way, and that this is an aspect of their commitment
to a reductionist view of the human being and the human good. It is precisely the
heart of Socrates’s integrity that he does not use his words manipulatively, as tools or
instruments. Rather, all his words and actions express his sense of his own life; they
are the activity of him living ‘the examined life’; he stakes and commits himself with
every word that he speaks. To put this another way, Socrates does not set out to teach
his hearers and interlocutors. Instead, he sets out to seek the truth in dialogue with
them—to engage in the practice of philosophy with them, and strive wholeheartedly
in pursuit of its internal goods. That is to say, Socrates is not setting out to ‘educate’
people; his philosophical discussions are not ‘learning activities’, engaged in with
one eye on the ‘learning outcomes’ to be produced by them; he does not intend his
actions as ‘models’ for those around him. Socrates, in Holt’s terms, is engaged in
genuine ‘doing’ rather than ‘educating’—and just this is why he is worth learning
from.
Holt’s views are utopian and therefore entirely unhelpful. Our society is simply not
structured in a way that is favourable for the ‘best learning’, and there is no realistic
chance it will become so. Hence, Holt’s views are useless for helping us devise, here
and now, practical strategies for positive change. That is, his views fail to help us to
answer the question ‘What is to be done?’.
This is a crucial objection, and it is what I will discuss in the final chapter of this
book.
3 This point has not been well-understood in the literature on Socrates’s claim. It is missed entirely,
e.g., in Mintz 2013.
76 3 Objections and Replies
References
Aristotle. (1984). Nichomachean ethics (W. D. Ross, Trans.). In J. Barnes (Ed.), The complete works
of Aristotle: The revised Oxford translation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Barrow, R. (1978). Radical education: A critique of freeschooling and deschooling. Oxford: Martin
Robertson.
Borgmann, A. (1984). Technology and the character of contemporary life: A philosophical inquiry.
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Brewer, T. (2009). The retrieval of ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Burnyeat, M. F. (1980). Aristotle on learning to be good. In A. O. Rorty (Ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s
Ethics (pp. 69–92). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Dearden, R. F. (1968). The philosophy of primary education: An introduction. London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul.
Dent, N. (1988). Rousseau: An introduction to his psychological, social and political theory. Oxford:
Basil Blackwell.
Elster, J. (1985). Making sense of Marx. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Elster, J. (1986). Self-realization in work and politics: The Marxist conception of the good life.
Social Philosophy and Policy, 3(2), 97–126.
Franzosa, S. D. (1984). The best and wisest parent: A critique of John Holt’s philosophy of education.
Urban Education, 19(3), 227–44.
Gutmann, A. (1999). Democratic education (revised ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Hirst, P. (1975). What is teaching? In R. S. Peters (Ed.), The philosophy of education (pp. 163–77).
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Holt, J. (1970). What do I do Monday? New York: E. P. Dutton and Co.
Holt, J. (1971). Big bird, meet Dick and Jane: A critique of Sesame Street. Atlantic Monthly, 227(5),
72–8.
Holt, J. (1972). Freedom and beyond. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Holt, J. (1974). Escape from childhood: The needs and rights of children. New York: E. P. Dutton
and Co.
Holt, J. (1976). Instead of education. New York: E. P. Dutton and Co.
Holt, J. (1978). Never too late: My musical life story. New York: Merloyd Lawrence.
Holt, J. (1981). Teach your own: A hopeful path for education. Liss, Hants: Lighthouse Books.
Holt, J. (1982). How children fail (revised ed.). New York: Merloyd Lawrence.
Holt, J. (1983). How children learn (revised ed.). London: Penguin.
Holt, J. (1989). Learning all the time. New York: Merloyd Lawrence.
Holt, J. (1990). Letter to Ivan Illich, 5/24/78. In S. Sheffer, (Ed.). (1990). A life worth living: Selected
letters of John Holt (pp. 213–8). Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press.
Kant, I. (2007). Lectures on pedagogy (R. B. Louden, Trans.) In Anthropology, history, and educa-
tion (G. Zöller & R. B. Louden, Eds.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mach, E. (1903). Populär-Wissenschaftliche Vorlesungen. Leipzig: Johann Ambrosius Barth.
MacIntyre, A. (1994). The Theses on Feuerbach: A road not taken. In C. C. Gould & R. S. Cohen,
(Eds.), Artifacts, representations and social practice (pp. 277−90). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Malatesta, E. (2013). Anarchy. Saint Louis, MO: Dialectics.
Marx, K. (1973). Grundrisse: Introduction to the critique of political economy (M. Nicolaus, Trans.).
Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Matthews, G. B. (1992). Dialogues with children. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Matthews, G. B. (1994). The philosophy of childhood. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Mintz, A. I. (2013). Why did Socrates Deny that he was a teacher? Locating Socrates among the new
educators and the traditional education in Plato’s Apology of Socrates. Educational Philosophy
and Theory, 46(7), 735–47.
Morgan, K. (1976). Children, bonsai trees, and open education. The Journal of Educational Thought,
10(1), 22–33.
References 77
Murdoch, I. (1997). The sovereignty of good over other concepts. Existentialists and mystics:
Writings on philosophy and literature (pp. 363–85). London: Chatto and Windus.
Orff, C., & Keetman, G. (1950). Musik für Kinder: In Fünftonraum (Vol. 1). Mainz: Schott.
Peters, R. S. (1966). Ethics and education. London: George Allen and Unwin.
Plato. (1961). Collected dialogues (E. Hamilton & H. Cairns, Eds.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton Uni-
versity Press.
Ramsey, F. P. (1928). A mathematical theory of saving. The Economic Journal, 38(152), 543–59.
Rosenow, E. (1980). Rousseau’s Émile: An anti-utopia. British Journal of Educational Studies,
28(3), 212–24.
Rousseau, J-J. (1979). Émile: Or on education (A. Bloom, Trans.). New York: Basic Books.
Ryle, G. (1990). The concept of mind. London: Penguin.
Ryle, G. (2009). Pleasure. Collected essays 1929−1968 (pp. 339–48). London: Routledge.
Williams, B. (2002). Truth and truthfulness: An essay in genealogy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Uni-
versity Press.
Wolf, A. (2002). Does education matter? Myths about education and economic growth. London:
Penguin.
Chapter 4
What Is to Be Done?
… we have created a world of dynamic machines or tools and institutions, and static men;
or living tools and dead men. (Holt 1990a, p. 149)
4.1 Introduction
It is now time to turn from theory to a brief consideration of practice—to ask the
question, if something like the analysis given in the preceding chapters is correct,
then what, if anything, does it demand that we do? At the end of chapter one, it was
pointed out that, considered analytically, Holt’s works consist of three main compo-
nents. First, they contain a positive or constructive account of what he considers the
‘best learning’, the sorts of conditions that promote such learning, and the sorts of
conditions that are hostile to it. Secondly, they contain a critique of education, which
is justified by appeal to the foregoing account of ‘best learning’. And thirdly, they
contain a range of practical strategies, aimed at mitigating the problems of education
(especially compulsory schooling) and maximising the opportunity of acquiring the
‘best learning’. This third component was of great significance to Holt. Although
there is a sense in which Holt’s work is ‘utopian’, in that it criticises some founda-
tional cultural assumptions and envisages a possible society that exists nowhere, he
is, at the same time, a deeply practical, realistic thinker. He does not offer airy plans
for grand social reconstruction, addressed to nobody in particular; rather, he tries to
answer the question of what can be done by us, here and now. In the words of one of
his book titles, he wants to answer the question: What do I do Monday?
As was remarked in the first chapter, Holt is best known today as a key figure
in the history of the homeschooling movement. For this reason, this concluding
chapter will focus particularly on his proposal that homeschooling is the best practical
strategy for providing a context in which children can maximise their opportunities
of achieving the ‘best learning’. I have no intention of offering a detailed assessment
or discussion of homeschooling in general—an area on which there is a substantial
literature, both scholarly and non-scholarly (for a recent, systematic survey, see
Rothermel 2015). The focus here will be much more restricted and specific: looking
at how homeschooling, as a practical strategy, relates to Holt’s views on learning and
education.
To understand Holt’s recommendation of homeschooling, it is important to situate
it within the context of his developing thought about practical strategies. I have argued
in previous chapters that a particular conception of the ‘best learning’ is present in
all his works. This conception was deepened and clarified over the course of Holt’s
writing, but in fundamentals it remains the same from his first book, How Children
Fail, through to the posthumous Learning All the Time. However, over this period the
practical strategies he recommends in his books shift substantially. In Holt’s early
works (How Children Fail through to What do I do Monday?) the strategies are
largely pedagogical, aimed at teachers who wish to make their classes more friendly
to learner-directed learning. By the time of Instead of Education (1976) Holt has
largely given up on the idea that the ‘best learning’ can be achieved in any real way
within the context of compulsory schooling. The strategies he proposes in this work
thus shift to what might be termed, with a nod to anarchist thought, ‘mutual aid
solutions’—the building of non-hierarchical counter-institutions and resources that
can promote learning outside of the official educational system. Finally, in Teach
Your Own (1981), Holt extends this mutualism to the building of a community of
homeschoolers, offering detailed practical advice on all aspects of what is involved
in withdrawing a child from compulsory schooling.
I will examine each of these three proposed strategies in a little more detail in
a moment, but to begin with, this summary allows me to clarify an important pre-
liminary point. In order to answer the question ‘what is to be done?’, it is of crucial
importance to specify the intended agent of this doing—or, equivalently, the audi-
ence being addressed by these practical recommendations and exhortations. Holt’s
practical strategies are addressed to particular groups of people at a particular time
and place. The particular time and place is, of course, the USA in the 1970s and
early 1980s. The particular groups he aims at change with the shifts in his proposed
strategies. The early, pedagogical strategies are, obviously enough, aimed at teachers
who shared Holt’s views about learning, and were looking for approaches that could
be used within the classroom to maximise the learner’s freedom. The later strate-
gies are increasingly aimed at parents and children, who shared Holt’s views and
were looking for ways of escaping the educational system altogether. Holt’s practi-
cal strategies are thus aimed at providing suggestions for action that can realistically
be implemented (on Monday!) by agents who are relatively powerless in relation to
the education system.
In this way, Holt stands in stark contrast to too many books on educational theory,
which tend to offer vague prescriptions addressed to a mythical agent—namely, “an
all-powerful and all-benevolent policy-making apparatus” (Ferguson 1990, p. 280).
Consider, for example, the following passage (taken more or less at random) from
Amy Gutmann’s Democratic Education:
4.1 Introduction 81
… states should take greater responsibility for financing primary education or for mak-
ing more effective use of existing resources; the content of education should be reoriented
towards teaching students the skills of democratic deliberation; and the federal government
should give local schools more money for educating handicapped children. (Gutmann 1999,
p. 171)
As noted, in his early works Holt’s practical strategies were addressed primarily to
an audience of like-minded teachers in the US school system. These were teachers
who were looking for ways of making their classrooms much more ‘child-centred’,
in the context of the authoritarian nature of typical US public schools at this time.
Holt’s early works are thus rich collections of very detailed pedagogical techniques
and suggestions for connecting learning more closely to the motivations of children,
and bringing more ‘real’ activities into their learning. They include suggestions for
setting up contexts which will encourage children to explore literacy and numeracy in
more self-directed ways; approaches to explaining arithmetical concepts in ways that
connect more closely to children’s understanding; lists of useful teaching resources
and where to obtain them; advice on how to deal with the external demands of
the schooling system (e.g., grading) in ways that will render them less harmful to
learning.
Holt’s views about the best practical strategies have shifted dramatically by the
time he wrote Instead of Education. As its title indicates, Holt is no longer discussing
how people working inside the education system can mitigate its negative impacts on
learning, but on how learning can best occur outside of official educational systems
altogether. This shift in approach reflects the belief that,
1 All too typical, in fact, of much contemporary political philosophy in general. For an excellent
critique of this approach, see Geuss (2008).
82 4 What Is to Be Done?
constructive change in human affairs does not come about through people clashing with and
reforming old institutions, but by their setting up new institutions which because they meet
more important human needs gradually displace the old. (Holt 1990b, pp. 60–1)
Holt’s clarity about these issues, and his growing understanding of the foundational,
irremediable problems with compulsory schooling, stemmed in part from his increas-
ing links to a community of radical scholars and critics of education. Of particular
importance in this regard is Holt’s friendship with Ivan Illich, the author of Deschool-
ing Society, and his time spent at Illich’s Centro Intercultural de Documentación
(CIDOC) in Cuernavaca. As Holt writes in a letter in 1970,
My short visit to CIDOC has made me feel much more strongly than before that our world-
wide system of schooling is far more harmful, and far more deeply and integrally connected
with many of the other great evils of our time, than I had supposed. (Holt 1990c, p. 56)
Hence we find that in Instead of Education, Holt has shifted away from pedagogy as
the site of resistance, to strategies of mutual aid. Through a series of real examples, the
book examines how communities can build counter-institutions that ‘help people do
things better’—that open the world of practices to learners in ways that are compatible
with their freedom and autonomy. The examples discussed by Holt in this book
include learning exchanges, that offer free courses taught to all-comers by volunteers
from the community; community libraries of various kinds of resources (books, of
course, but also tools, sporting equipment, etc.); community sporting associations
and facilities; community printing presses; community art studios. A particularly
important example for Holt in this book is the Peckham Health Centre (which existed
in Peckham, London, from 1926 to 1951). Described by Colin Ward as “a unique
laboratory of anarchism”, this was a highly successful health and social centre in an
impoverished area in South London, which was collectively organised and managed
by the local community, and made medical knowledge available in a non-paternalistic
way (Goodway 2012, pp. 363–5; Pearse and Crocker 1943).
Instead of Education ends with some very practical suggestions for children, to
assist them in making their time in school more useful and engaging. One of these
suggestions concerns the fun that can be had from school children purchasing their
own copy of the teacher’s manual. With regard to this, Holt writes that,
4.2 Shifting Strategies 83
I can imagine a number of ways in which older children could use the manuals to make
school much more interesting. They might, for example, keep a close check on the teacher,
to see how closely he stuck to the manual, and in what ways he departed from it. Or they
might have some fun at beating the teacher to the draw; thus, if the manual suggested that on
a given day the teacher ask a certain question or propose a certain discussion, the children
might ask the question or propose the discussion first. Then they could watch the teacher’s
reactions. Or, where the manual says, ‘Have a discussion and bring out this point’, they could
bring out the point right away, thus ending the fake discussion, or, on the other hand, refuse
to bring out the point wanted, no matter how the teacher pushed and prodded. … I have no
qualms at all about suggesting any of this. Any teacher who is dumb and lazy enough to do
his teaching out of a manual deserves whatever he gets. (Holt 1976, pp. 216–7)
Of course, this is not just a ‘bit of fun’, but a practical lesson for school students
in resistance and empowerment—in children regaining, through their own activity,
power, capacity, and self-respect in the face of the school system’s coerciveness. As
Holt writes,
of course, the most important trick in beating the school game is to know that it is a game, as
abstract, unreal, and useless as chess, and that beating it is a trick. The game is important only
because (as with chess) there are rewards for playing it well, and (unlike chess) penalties for
playing it badly. (Holt 1976, p. 217)
With his promotion of mutual aid solutions as the most promising form of resis-
tance to compulsory schooling systems, the Holt of Instead of Education can thus be
seen as part of the anarchist tradition of thought (cf. Ward 2008, Chap. 9). Compare,
for example, the 18th century English anarchist William Godwin, who writes in The
Enquirer that,
The best motive to learn, is a perception of the value of the thing learned. The worst motive
… may well be affirmed to be constraint and fear. … If I learn nothing but what I desire
to learn, what should hinder me from being my own preceptor?… The boy, like the man,
studies because he desires it. He proceeds upon a plan of his own invention, or which, by
adopting, he has made his own. (Godwin 1965, Essay IX, pp. 78–80)
And, from the 19th century, consider the following passage from Mikael Bakunin,
who writes in God and the State that, under anarchism,
From these schools will be absolutely eliminated the smallest applications or manifestations
of the principle of authority. They will be schools no longer; they will be popular academies,
in which neither pupils nor masters will be known, where the people will come freely to get,
if they need it, free instruction, and in which, rich in their own experience, they will teach
in their turn many things … This, then, will be a mutual instruction, an act of intellectual
fraternity. (Bakunin 1970, p. 42, n.)
By the time he publishes Teach Your Own, Holt’s thinking was focussed on the
practical strategy of homeschooling (or, to use Holt’s term, ‘unschooling’). In 1977,
Holt had established the newsletter Growing Without Schooling, which was intended
to be (and became) the information hub of a growing community of homeschoolers.
Teach Your Own emerged from this activism, and is the first comprehensive discussion
of homeschooling in the literature. It contains chapters on the arguments in favour of
homeschooling, and replies to common objections. It has extensive accounts (illus-
trated with lengthy quotations from letters published in Growing Without Schooling)
of the varied ways in which homeschooling parents and students approach learn-
ing—with chapter titles such as ‘Learning in the world’, ‘Serious Play’, and ‘Learn-
ing without teaching’. It also gives detailed advice on dealing with the legal issues
involved in withdrawing children from compulsory schooling. In other words, as is
typical of Holt’s works, Teach Your Own is at once a philosophical discussion of
the nature of learning, a polemic against compulsory schooling, and a manual for
practical action.
It is important to emphasise that homeschooling, as Holt saw it, was not an indi-
vidualistic rejection of the mutual aid approach outlined in Instead of Education, but
rather a focussing of that anarchist strategy. The aim was to encourage homeschoolers
to build, through their own efforts, a community of mutual support, and the exchange
of advice, skills, and resources. Holt thus writes of “this miniature society that home-
schoolers are creating—this country within a country, this ancestor (I hope) of a very
different, larger society that some of us may someday see” (Farenga and Holcomb,
Eds., 1990, p. 33). Growing Without Schooling aimed to facilitate this self-activity,
but in no way did Holt claim a ‘leadership’ or ‘authority’ role within the community.
Furthermore, the very act of withdrawing a child from school (which, at this point in
US history, was very difficult or even illegal) was itself an example of ‘work worth
doing’. Through such an act both parents and children would learn and be empow-
ered by becoming aware of their own capacities—to make autonomous choices and
see them through, to question authority, to argue for their legal rights, and so forth.
Homeschooling, as envisaged by Holt, was thus an example of precisely the sort
of prefigurative politics familiar from anarchist history and theory (see Boggs 1977;
Breines 1989). That is, the way in which the movement was organised was itself
an attempt to embody (or ‘prefigure’) the kind of future society it was aiming to
create—a community of autonomous, empowered citizens of all ages, who trans-
formed themselves through their own self-activity, without the need for ‘authorities’
and ‘experts’ to shape them and their lives. As Holt saw it, the homeschooling
movement was, in other words, to be the building of a counter-institution of mutual
aid, in opposition to the bureaucratic, authoritarian official education system. We
thus find Holt writing in a letter in 1980 that,
The big picture in the US is discouraging. There are large and visible signs everywhere of a
society in a state of collapse. … At the same time there are hundreds of very encouraging
small pictures. On a small and local scale Americans are doing a great many interesting,
constructive, significant things—building a new and very different society under the shadow
of the old. It is with this work and these people that I identify myself. (Holt 1990d, pp. 233–4)
4.2 Shifting Strategies 85
‘Building a new and very different society under the shadow of the old’: with this
(surely deliberate) echo of the famous slogan of the International Workers of the
World (‘building the new world in the shell of the old’), Holt summarises his hopes
for the homeschooling movement that he had done so much to nurture and encourage.
4.3 Homeschooling
How have those hopes been borne out? Writing with the benefit of hindsight, more
than thirty years after Holt’s death, I would argue that the results are disappointing.
If we focus on the situation in the USA, the contemporary homeschooling movement
is, in some senses, far more successful than Holt could have dreamed possible. US
Department of Education figures suggest that around two million children are now
homeschooled (Redford et al. 2017), and the movement has strong political clout
(see, e.g., Cooper and Sureau 2007). However, taken as a whole, it has failed to
build, as Holt had hoped for, a web of counter-institutions to ‘help people do things
better’—rooted in collective mutual aid, and accessible to all, rich and poor alike.
There are two reasons for this failure.
The first reason is that the homeschooling movement in the USA is overwhelm-
ingly dominated, not by Holt-inspired ‘unschoolers’, but by evangelical Christians
(who make up more than 80% of the total; Kunzman and Gaither 2013, p. 9). Most of
the latter have withdrawn their children from school, not because they share Holt’s
vision of the ‘best learning’ and a community of autonomous ‘do-ers’, but because
they reject what they see as the liberal and secular worldview of the public school
system. The sort of learning that these evangelical homeschoolers provide for their
children can be even more narrow and authoritarian, in both form and content, than
that found in compulsory schools. The result of such homeschooling can thus be, not
an opening of the world to children, as Holt argued for, but an even deeper enclosing
of children within the confines of the nuclear family.
This leads me to the second reason for the failure of the homeschooling movement
to build counter-institutions. By its nature, homeschooling as a practical strategy
focuses on the struggle of each individual family to withdraw its children from
compulsory schooling. Although it thereby encourages families to join together as
an advocacy group to fight at the political level for such withdrawal to be a legal right,
it does not encourage the building of alternative, non-hierarchical institutions through
collective action. In other words, homeschooling seeks to extend liberalism’s ‘sphere
of freedom’ to children’s educational provision, but does not contain within itself
the seeds of further mutual aid. Hence, the contemporary homeschooling movement,
taken as a whole, is not an engaged, grass-roots resistance to the instrumentalism of
contemporary society, but, in some respects, an instance of some of that society’s
most negative features: the decay of the public realm, and the conception of the
neoliberal individual as free from all bonds of social solidarity (cf. Apple 2000;
Lubienski 2000). It thus fails to be a fulfilment of Holt’s dreams of the beginnings
of “a new and very different society”. Rather, the contemporary homeschooling
86 4 What Is to Be Done?
for the ‘best learning’ than other alternatives realistically available, here and now, to
many children. It is simply an unfortunate fact that, in the absence of a network of
non-coercive counter-institutions and resources, for many children the compulsory
school—for all its failings and coerciveness—still represents their best option for
acquiring the ‘best learning’.
4.4 Conclusion
The failure of the contemporary homeschooling movement to achieve what Holt had
hoped for is not really surprising. For Holt’s vision of learning is, after all, funda-
mentally opposed to the dominant trends of our time. To make this clear, consider
what, in the light of the previous chapters’ analysis, he would consider to be the
ideal or perfect learning situation. This would be one in which children would have
the maximal opportunity for acquiring the ‘best learning’, and it would have the
following characteristics:
Children would have easy access to a world of adults engaged in serious, meaningful
work—work worth doing, as Holt would put it.
This would, in other words, be a world of varied practices, being undertaken by people with
voluntary discipline and a wholehearted love for what they did.
It would be in the context of a broader culture which valued the excellent performance of
such practices, along with such qualities as skill and dedication, for their own sake.
By ‘easy access’ is meant that adults engaged in such serious work can be observed by
children, and that there are spaces in those practices for children (and novices in general)
to participate in serious work to whatever level is possible for them.
Furthermore, along with access to adults doing serious work, children would also have
easy access to a wide variety of resources relevant to such practices (such as art facilities,
sporting facilities, tools, workshops, libraries, cultural institutions and the like).
In Holt’s own words, this would be a ‘doing’ society, of which he writes as follows:
The best and only really good place for do-ers would be a society that does not yet exist. In
that society all people, of whatever age, sex, race, etc., could have work to do which was
varied and interesting, which challenged and rewarded their skill and intelligence, which they
could do well and take pride in doing well, over which they could exercise some control,
and whose ends and purposes they could understand and respect. Today, very few people
feel this way about their work … In such a society no one would worry about ‘education’.
People would be busy doing interesting things that mattered, and they would grow more
informed, competent, and wise in doing them. They would learn about the world from living
in it, working in it, and changing it, and from knowing a wide variety of people who were
doing the same. But nowhere in the world does such a society exist, nor is there one in the
making. (Holt 1976, p. 6)
It seems clear that our present culture, society, and economy are overwhelmingly
hostile to this ideal. Holt writes in the passage just quoted that, “nowhere in the
world does such a society exist, nor is there one in the making”. I would go fur-
ther, and suggest that some words of George Orwell are apposite to our situation:
88 4 What Is to Be Done?
“The actual outlook, so far as I can calculate the probabilities, is very dark, and any
serious thought should start out from that fact” (Orwell 2000, p. 375). Of course
things vary from place to place, but, generalising, the salient features of our modern
world include the following. To begin with, a very large amount of the labour—that
is, the paid work—done by adults is not meaningful and highly skilled, but rather
the reverse: degraded, deskilled, and mind-numbing. What is more, whilst there are
still many adults engaged in practices for their own sake (communities of scholars,
scientists, artists, craftspeople, and the like), access to such serious work for chil-
dren (indeed, for novices in general), tends to be very difficult. There are, that is,
substantial walls between the world of adults and the world of children. Further-
more, such practices are being undertaken in the context of a broader culture that,
increasingly, does not value them for their own sake, but only as instruments for the
attainment of external goods—money, status, power. In addition, in many countries
the influence of neoliberalism since the 1980s has seen the growing privatisation and
enclosure of public resources that could facilitate access to practices (e.g., orchestras,
public library systems, art galleries, sporting facilities, etc.). Such neoliberalism com-
bined with galloping credentialism, has in many countries also seriously undermined
previous routes of access to certain practices, such as apprenticeships, cadetships,
traineeships, and vocational forms of education and training more generally.
In his emphasis on the vital importance, for both adults and children, of work
worth doing for its own sake, Holt’s view of learning thus runs in direct opposition
to the dominant features of our contemporary world. It is in this running against
the grain of contemporary society that Holt’s views are—despite superficial resem-
blances—ultimately very different from those of other major philosopher of ‘child-
centred’ learning, John Dewey. Consider the following well-known passage from
Democracy and Education, where Dewey writes,
To savages it would seem preposterous to seek out a place where nothing but learning was
going on in order that one might learn. But as civilisation advances, the gap between the
capacities of the young and the concerns of adults widens. Learning by direct sharing in
the pursuits of grown-ups becomes increasingly difficult except in the case of less advanced
occupations. Much of what adults do is so remote in space and in meaning that playful
imitation is less and less adequate to reproduce its spirit. Ability to share effectively in adult
activities thus depends upon a prior training given with this end in view. (Dewey 2004, p. 7)
Holt’s ideal for ‘best learning’—namely, a world in which children learn ‘by direct
sharing in the pursuits of grown-ups’, rather than in separate ‘learning institu-
tions’—is precisely what Dewey rejects in this passage as no longer possible. Dewey’s
stated reason for rejecting such a world as impossible (for us moderns, if not for
‘savages’) is that with ‘advancing civilisation’ there is a widening gap between ‘the
capacities of the young’ and the ‘concerns of adults’.
If we look at the typical ‘developed’ economy today, Dewey’s contention looks
implausible. Dewey is arguing that, as civilisation ‘advanced’, more and more sophis-
ticated levels of knowledge and expertise would be required to engage in adult work.
However, as just remarked, what we have in fact seen is largely the reverse of this:
that more and more adult work has been degraded, so that it demands less skill and
knowledge of the worker, rather than more (see Braverman 1974 for a classic study
4.4 Conclusion 89
of this phenomenon). Indeed, there is good reason to think that, in the decades since
Dewey wrote, we have seen a tremendous deskilling of our societies, rather than a
growth in ‘advanced occupations’. Of course there is a cadre of experts and pro-
fessionals engaged in work of extraordinary technical sophistication, but if we look
at the majority of jobs in many wealthy economies, they involve low-skilled ‘ser-
vice’ work (consider typical work in retail, hospitality, and aged care, to name three
major areas of employment). A child might struggle to tolerate the mind-numbing
tediousness and drudgery of such work, but Dewey’s suggestion that such work is
‘too advanced’ for children’s capacities is not remotely persuasive.
In sum, Dewey suggests that schools are required because the cognitive nature of
adult work (its demands of knowledge and expertise) makes integration of children
into that work impossible. Schools, in other words, are an inescapable necessity for
any ‘advanced civilisation’. Holt—with, I suggest, good reason—rejects any such
claim. But it seems clear that for us to build a society in which all—adults and children
alike—could join in genuinely meaningful work, would demand a thorough-going
remaking of our culture, society, and economy. It would, in other words, demand a
new world.
There is thus an important sense in which Holt’s critique, unlike Dewey’s philos-
ophy of education, is not constructive. Holt is not offering some plan to ‘reform’ or
even ‘replace’ the education system. For Holt, it would be better if we had a ‘doing’
society and no schools, but that we do not have, and almost all the trends—as he
well knew—are going in precisely the opposite direction. Homeschooling may offer
palliatives for some of these trends, for some people in some contexts, but, in the
final analysis, there is no place that can provide children with a safe shelter from the
surrounding world’s deep instrumentalism. Ideally, Holt desired a society with no
‘space’ for education at all—but he is well aware that that would involve a whole-sale
reconstruction of the society we have now. (It would entail, for example, a completely
different way of organising work, which in turn would entail a completely different
way of organising the economy.) And Holt (who was not only a philosopher, but also
a deeply experienced campaigner and activist) was under no illusions that any such
reconstruction was in the offing—and that, furthermore, proposing utopian plans for
it was worth than useless (for, after all, to whom would such plans be addressed?).
In this sense, then, for those fundamentally committed to the world as it is, Holt’s
critique is worse than useless—being, ultimately, neither ‘constructive’ nor ‘reason-
able’. For what those words ultimately mean is such people’s mouths is: keeping
things much as they are (cf. Geuss 2014).
But for those of us who can no longer share that commitment—as the world
rushes headlong towards ecological, social, cultural, and economic disaster—Holt’s
vision can help to orientate our thoughts and acts. This is precisely because his
account of the ‘best learning’, and his critique of education, run so directly contrary
to the deep instrumentalism that dominates our culture and economy. One way of
summing up this point, is to say that Holt’s works are a critique of a powerful cultural
idea: that education is a technology. That is, in Borgmann’s definition of that word,
that it is “an essentially uninteresting if powerful tool, neutral in its relations to
cultural values and subservient to political goals” (Borgmann 1984, p. 35). This can
90 4 What Is to Be Done?
be seen in the way that contemporary debates about learning concern themselves,
on the one hand, with the question of the right means (such as which pedagogical
techniques should be used), and, on the other hand, with the question of the right ends
(such as what curriculum should be taught). Underpinning this way of structuring
the debate is an unquestioned (indeed, unarticulated) assumption that thinking of
education as comprising activities that are efficient means to achieve ends is itself
unproblematic. That is, it takes for granted that the division into means and ends is
a neutral framework which begs no questions, and within which any (‘reasonable’)
position can be taken up.
What Holt’s account of the ‘best learning’ helps us to see is that to take up this
instrumentalist framing—with its view of education as a technology—is, implicitly,
already to have accepted certain substantive views about value and the human good,
and to have rendered certain alternative views of that good invisible. The instru-
mentalist framework entails thinking of human activities as intrinsically, essentially
geared towards the efficient production of future goods, which are thus seen as con-
ceptually separable from the activities themselves. As I have argued in previous
chapters, this instrumentalism goes along with certain conceptions of agency, plea-
sure, motivation, and learning. It is thereby of a part with the division of our lives
under capitalism into, on the one hand, mere consumption, and, on the other hand,
increasingly degraded forms of labour. It encourages a conception of the good life
as one spent in activities aimed at external goods—at money, status, power; it is a
framework which is corrosive of the excellences, because it systematically offers
incentives for developing the vices of the practices; it tends to break our lives and
activities into disconnected fragments.
In contrast, Holt’s account of learning and education, with its focus on autotelic
activity and the virtues of practices, embodies a profoundly different vision of the
human good. This vision is a very ancient one, and from its perspective, the instru-
mentalist model of education and its accompanying assumptions appears as, to use
Holt’s phrase once more, “the creed of a slave”. Holt’s vision is concerned with
the importance of: self-realisation through work worth doing for its own sake; deep
engagement with present activity rather than a focus on future outcomes; replacing
resentful dutifulness with the agent’s self-transformation through a wholehearted,
loving submission to the demands of excellence in a practice. This vision is—as
should be obvious, and as was certainly obvious to Holt—in deep opposition to
much in our contemporary world.
What is of enduring value in Holt is his combination of this profoundly critical
vision, with a deeply pragmatic, common-sense realism. With that realism, what
he offers us is not grand utopian plans, but a politics of piecemeal resistance and
self-defence—located wherever we are, beginning today. Holt’s works can help us
to see that the reign of instrumentalism is not total. Even in the most apparently
inhospitable places, there are always interstices, gaps, and spaces for the pursuit of
autotelic activity by both adults and children, and the nurture of the excellences that
such activity brings along with it.
I will end with a story told more than two millennia ago by the great Chinese
philosopher Zhuangzi. It can serve as a reminder that the conception of the human
4.4 Conclusion 91
good that we find in Holt’s works has deep roots in human history and culture—which
is to say, in us, and what we value. And deep roots, after all, are not reached by the
frost.2
Qing carved a bell-stand, and when it was completed, all who saw it were astonished as if
it were the work of spirits. The Duke of Lu went to see it, and asked by what art he had
succeeded in producing it.
“Your subject is but a humble wood carver,” was Qing’s reply; “what art should I be possessed
of? Nevertheless, there is one thing which I will mention. When your servant had undertaken
to make the bell-stand, I did not venture to waste any of my power, and felt it necessary to
fast in order to compose my mind. After fasting for three days, I did not presume to think of
any congratulation, reward, rank, or emolument which I might obtain by the execution of my
task; after fasting five days, I did not presume to think of the condemnation or commendation
which it would produce, or of the skill or want of skill which it might display. At the end of the
seven days, I had forgotten all about myself—my four limbs and my whole person. By this
time the thought of your Grace’s court for which I was to make the thing had passed away;
everything that could divert my mind from exclusive devotion to the exercise of my skill had
disappeared. Then I went into the forest, and looked at the natural forms of the trees. When I
saw one of a perfect form, then the figure of the bell-stand rose up to my view, and I applied
my hand to the work. Had I not met with such a tree, I must have abandoned the object; but
my Heaven-given faculty and the Heaven-given qualities of the wood were concentrated on
it. Thus it was that my spirit was engaged in the production of the bell-stand.” (Zhuangzi
2018, §11; translation modified)
References
Apple, M. (2000). The cultural politics of home schooling. Peabody Journal of Education, 75(1–2),
256–71.
Bakunin, M. (1970). God and the state. New York: Dover Publications.
Boggs, C. (1977). Revolutionary process, political strategy, and the dilemma of power. Theory and
Society, 4(3), 359–93.
Borgmann, A. (1984). Technology and the character of contemporary life: A philosophical inquiry.
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Braverman, H. (1974). Labor and monopoly capital: The degradation of work in the twentieth
century. New York: Monthly Review Press.
Breines, W. (1989). Community and organization in the New Left, 1962–1968: The great refusal
(revised ed.). New Brunswick and London: Rutgers University Press.
Coleman-Jensen, A., Rabbitt, M. P., Gregory, C. A., & Singh, A. (2018). Household food security in
the United States in 2017. Economic Research Report No. 256. Washington, DC: US Department
of Agriculture.
Cooper, B. S., & Sureau, J. (2007). The politics of homeschooling: New developments, new chal-
lenges. Educational Policy, 21(1), 110–131.
Dewey, J. (2004). Democracy and education. Mineola, NY: Dover.
Farenga, P., & Holcomb, J. P. (Eds.). (1990). Sharing treasures: Book reviews by John Holt. Cam-
bridge, MA: Holt Associates.
Ferguson, J. (1990). The anti-politics machine: Depoliticization and bureaucratic power in Lesotho.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Geuss, R. (2008). Philosophy and real politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Geuss, R. (2014). Must criticism be constructive? A world without why (pp. 68–90). Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Godwin, W. (1965). The enquirer: Reflections on education, manners, and literature. New York,
NY: Augustus M. Kelley.
Goodway, D. (2012). Anarchist seeds beneath the snow: Left-libertarian thought and British writers
from William Morris to Colin Ward. London: PM Press.
Gutmann, A. (1999). Democratic education (revised ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Holt, J. (1970). What do I do Monday? New York: E. P. Dutton and Co.
Holt, J. (1976). Instead of education. New York: E. P. Dutton and Co.
Holt, J. (1981). Teach your own: A hopeful path for education. Liss, Hants: Lighthouse Books.
Holt, J. (1990a). Letter to Ivan Illich, 2/22/73. In S. Sheffer (Ed.), A life worth living: Selected
letters of John Holt (pp. 147–52). Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press.
Holt, J. (1990b). Letter to Boston University Students, 2/27/70. In S. Sheffer (Ed.), A life worth
living: Selected letters of John Holt (pp. 60–5). Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press.
Holt, J. (1990c). Letter to Students at the Center for Intercultural Documentation, 2/19/70. In S.
Sheffer (Ed.), A life worth living: Selected letters of John Holt (pp. 56–9). Columbus, OH: Ohio
State University Press.
Holt, J. (1990d). Letter to Hartmut von Hentig, 8/25/80. In S. Sheffer (Ed.), A life worth living:
Selected letters of John Holt (pp. 228–35). Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press.
Kunzman, R., & Gaither, M. (2013). Homeschooling: A comprehensive survey of the research.
Other Education: The Journal of Educational Alternatives, 2(1), 4–59.
Lubienski, C. (2000). Whither the common good? A critique of home schooling. Peabody Journal
of Education, 75(1–2), 207–32.
Orwell, G. (2000). Toward European unity, Partisan Review, 1947. In S. Orwell & I. Angus (Eds.), In
front of your nose, 1945–1950. The collected essays, journalism and letters (pp. 370–5). Boston,
MA: Nonpareil Books.
Pearse, I. H., & Crocker, L. H. (1943). The Peckham experiment: A study of the living structure of
society. London: George Allen and Unwin.
Redford, J., Battle, D., Bielick, S., & Gradey, S. (2017). Homeschooling in the United States 2012
(revised ed.). Washington, DC: US Department of Education.
Rothermel, P. (Ed.). (2015). International perspectives on home education: Do we still need schools?
London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Tolkien, J. R. R. (1954). The lord of the rings. London: Allen and Unwin.
Ward, C. (2008). Anarchy in action (2nd ed.). London: Freedom Press.
Zhuangzi. (2018). The full understanding of life. In The outer chapters (J. Legge, Trans.). Available
at https://ctext.org/zhuangzi/full-understanding-of-life. Accessed December 2018.