The Evolution of A Memeplex in Late Moza PDF
The Evolution of A Memeplex in Late Moza PDF
Steven Jan
This article appeared in the above issue but the uncorrected version
of the music was published in error. Therefore the complete article
follows in full.
Journal of the Royal Musical Association, 128 (2003) © Royal Musical Association
The author is grateful to Julian Rushton for stimulating the development of some of the ideas in
this article, to Douglas Jarman and two anonymous reviewers for perceptive comments on earlier
drafts, and to Graham Cummings for the translation of Metastasio’s ‘Ecco quel fiero istante’ in
Section 6.
1 Julia Kristeva, in Kevin Korsyn, ‘Beyond Privileged Contexts: Intertextuality, Influence, and
Dialogue’, Rethinking Music, ed. Nicholas Cook and Mark Everist (Oxford, 1999), 55–72 (p. 56).
2 Ibid.
3 Kevin Korsyn, ‘Towards a New Poetics of Musical Influence’, Music Analysis, 10 (1991), 3–72
(p. 15).
4 Korsyn, ‘Beyond Privileged Contexts’, 56.
5 Korsyn, ‘Towards a New Poetics’, 6–7.
6 Lydia Goehr, The Imaginary Museum of Musical Works: An Essay in the Philosophy of Music
(Oxford, 1992).
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART 331
7 Norman Carrell, Bach the Borrower (London, 1967; repr. Westport, CT, 1980).
8 Leonard G. Ratner, Classic Music: Expression, Form, and Style (New York, 1980); Wye J. Allan-
brook, Rhythmic Gesture in Mozart: ‘Le nozze di Figaro’ and ‘Don Giovanni’ (Chicago, 1983); V. Kofi
Agawu, Playing with Signs: A Semiotic Interpretation of Classic Music (Princeton, 1991).
9 Jean Chantavoine, Mozart dans Mozart (Paris, 1948).
10 Leonard B. Meyer, Style and Music: Theory, History, and Ideology (Philadelphia, 1989), 24.
332 STEVEN JAN
then will move on, after examination of memetic theory and its appli-
cation to music (Sections 3 and 4), to a dialect-orientated perspective
(Section 5), suggesting how some of Mozart’s material may have come
from particular antecedent sources and how it may have been adapted
in other contexts by later composers. Finally, I shall consider how
certain verbal-conceptual (textual) memes exist in association with the
purely musical memes in these four pieces (Section 6), before sum-
marizing the principal issues raised here (Section 7).
related to the final chorus, Heil sei euch Geweihten!’ (no. 21, bars 828ff.), and ‘Melodies related to
the Adagio before the chorale’ (no. 21, bars 190ff.), respectively (ibid., 20–1). The melodies consti-
tuting this complex might best be regarded as based upon a (1̂–7̂ . . . 2̂–1̂) ‘changing-note’
archetype/schema in the Meyer/Gjerdingen sense; see Robert O. Gjerdingen, A Classic Turn of
Phrase: Music and the Psychology of Convention (Philadelphia, 1988), 55–9.
13 Eckelmeyer, ‘Two Complexes’, 16.
14 The example is a particella showing the principal melodic line, the bass line and an occa-
sional inner part of the arietta, Adagio, lied (here transposed from F minor to G minor) and aria.
(To facilitate comparison with the other three pieces, all analytical discussion of the lied in this
article will refer to this transposed version, speaking of it as if it were in G minor. The relevance
of the difference between the key of the lied and that of the other three pieces will be considered
in Section 6.) Figured bass numerals are added at times to clarify the harmonic content. The
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART 333
————
music is disposed so as to align vertically major structural correspondences – the seven memes
A–G – between groups of bars. The symbols used in the particella are as follows. (1) The seven
memes are shown enclosed by solid vertical continuity of the barlines. Where the differences of
metre permit, these continuous lines also occur within the groups. (2) Continuous dotted
(bar)lines indicate functional parallelisms, e.g. bar 19 of the arietta and bar 8 of the aria, where
the passages linked by the dotted line are analogous contrasting themes in the relative major. (3)
Without continuity of barlines, even when barlines are aligned vertically, passages are not in direct
correspondence; such coincidences are necessary to allow alignment of the structural corre-
spondences. (4) Brackets and lines (apart from such lines as indicate the voice exchanges within
meme C) draw attention to specific pitch correspondences (as in meme G). Some secondary
correspondences, because of the overriding influence of more important similarities, are not
vertically aligned (e.g. the bass of bars 12–13 of the arietta and the bass of bars 3–4 of the aria).
334 STEVEN JAN
Arietta
(1786)
5
1 2 3 4
Adagio
(16.v.1787)
Lied
(23.v.1787)
Aria
(1791)
3 4 5
Arietta
6 7 8 9
Adagio
Lied
Aria
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART 335
Example 1 continued
A
6 7 8 9 10
Arietta 6 5
4 3
11 12 13 14
10
6 / 7 6
4 6 3
Adagio 4
2
2 3 4 5
1
6 5
Lied 4 3
1 2 3
6 / 7 5
Aria 4 6 3
4
2
B
11 12 13 14
Arietta
15 16
Adagio
6 7 8 9
Lied
4 5
Aria
336 STEVEN JAN
Example 1 continued
15 16 17
Arietta
17
Adagio
10 11 12
Lied
6 7
Aria
18 19 20 21
Arietta
Adagio
Lied
8 9 10
Aria
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART 337
Example 1 continued
22 23
Arietta
Adagio
Lied
11 12 13
Aria
24 25
Arietta
Adagio
Lied
14 15
Aria
338 STEVEN JAN
Example 1 continued
26 27 28 29
Arietta
Adagio
Lied
16 17 18
Aria
30 31
Arietta
Adagio
Lied
19 20 21 22
Aria
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART 339
Example 1 continued
C
32 33 b.34
Arietta
18 19 20
Adagio
15
12 13 14
Lied
25 26 3
23 24
Aria
Arietta
22 23 24
21 25
Adagio
15
( )
Lied
26
Aria
340 STEVEN JAN
Example 1 continued
D
Arietta
26 [ ]
27 28 29
Adagio
16 17
Lied
27 28 29 30
Aria
34 35 36
Arietta
30 31
Adagio
Lied
31
Aria
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART 341
Example 1 continued
E
37 38 39
Arietta
32
Adagio
18
Lied
32
Aria
40 41
Arietta
33 34
Adagio
Lied
33 34 35
Aria
342 STEVEN JAN
Example 1 continued
F
Arietta
35 36
Adagio
20
19
Lied
36 37
Aria
G
Allegro moderato
Arietta
37 38 Allegro
Adagio
22
21
Lied
38
Aria
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART 343
Example 1 continued
42
Arietta
39 40
Adagio
Lied
39
Aria
Arietta
41 42
Adagio
Lied
40 41
Aria
344 STEVEN JAN
15 In some works of Mozart’s – such as bars 21–5 of the second movement of K.516 – the
rising upper-voice structure 3̂– 3̂– 4̂– 4̂–5̂ is associated with the descending chromatic tetra-
chord 1̂– 7̂– 6̂– 6̂–5̂ in the lower voice. It is this association which prompts my reading of the
structure in the Adagio and aria as ‘quasi-tetrachordal’, for these passages are perhaps best under-
stood as selections from a total resource. For a fuller discussion of these figures, see Steven Jan,
Aspects of Mozart’s Music in G Minor: Toward the Identification of Common Structural and Compositional
Characteristics (London and New York, 1995), Chapter 7. See also Peter Williams, The Chromatic
Fourth during Four Centuries of Music (Oxford, 1998), Chapter 6; the tetrachordal figures in the
Adagio and aria are, however, not examined by Williams.
16 Eckelmeyer, ‘Two Complexes’, 15.
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART 345
lied with bars 36–8 and bars 37–8 respectively of the Adagio and aria
(these passages being designated meme F below). This is certainly
tenable, for there is a shared melodic contour; but if the piano coda
of the lied’s strophe (bars 19–22) and not its bar 18 is held to contain
meme F, then the harmonic content of bar 18, essentially a dominant
chord preceded by its lower neighbour note, supports a reading of this
bar as meme E. Example 1 shows that the arietta and aria present
meme E in a very similar manner.
Meme G: Continuations
Not present in the arietta and lied, this meme – the basis of the theme
of the 6/8 G major Allegro which forms the main part of the quintet’s
final movement, and of the instrumental coda to the aria – is
characterized by a scalic descent 5̂– 7̂(–1̂). Harmonically, aside
from the common tonic opening and analogous concluding
ii6–3/ II 6–3–I6–4/i6–4–V–(i) cadences, there is an equivalent emphasis
on the subdominant in bar 405 of the quintet’s finale and bar 393 of
the aria. The change of mode and mood at this point of the quintet is
akin to the procedure of the arietta (bars 42ff.), although I do not read
any memetic connections between these passages.
17 Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (2nd edn, Oxford, 1989), 192.
346 STEVEN JAN
18 For book-length treatments offering an overview of memetics, see Susan Blackmore, The
Meme Machine (Oxford, 1999); Richard Brodie, Virus of the Mind: The New Science of the Meme
(Seattle, 1996); and Aaron Lynch, Thought Contagion: How Belief Spreads through Society – The New
Science of Memes (New York, 1996). For more critical voices, some of the essays in Darwinizing
Culture: The Status of Memetics as a Science, ed. Robert Aunger (Oxford, 2000), come from disci-
plinary perspectives (such as anthropology and sociology) which are somewhat sceptical of the
meme concept. A more technical, mathematically orientated account of memetic transmission
and evolution is given in Aaron Lynch, ‘Units, Events and Dynamics in Memetic Evolution’,
Journal of Memetics – Evolutionary Models of Information Transmission, 2/1 (1998) (<http://
jom-emit.cfpm.org/1998/vol2/lynch_a.html>). For more on the application of memetics to
music, see Steven Jan, ‘Replicating Sonorities: Towards a Memetics of Music’, Journal of
Memetics – Evolutionary Models of Information Transmission, 4/1 (2000) (<http://
jom-emit.cfpm.org/2000/vol4/jan_s.html>); ‘The Memetics of Music and its Implications for
Psychology’, Proceedings of the Sixth International Conference on Music Perception and Cognition, ed.
Christopher Woods, Geoffrey B. Luck, Renaud Brochard, Susan A. O’Neill and John A. Sloboda
(CD-ROM, Keele, 2000); ‘The Selfish Meme: Particularity, Replication, and Evolution in Musical
Style’, International Journal of Musicology, 8 (2002), 9–76; and ‘The Illusory Mozart: Selfish Memes
in the Priests’ Marches from Idomeneo and Die Zauberflöte’, International Journal of Musicology, 10
(forthcoming, 2004). A few passages in the present article are adapted from Jan, ‘Replicating
Sonorities’, ‘The Memetics of Music’ and ‘The Selfish Meme’. The recently established online
Journal of Memetics – Evolutionary Models of Information Transmission (<http://
jom-emit.cfpm.org>) offers a forum for articles on various aspects of the subject.
19 Brodie, Virus of the Mind, 13.
20 That is, forms of analogous configuration whose similarity is such that a relationship of
Such a particle as the phrase ‘To be, or not to be, that is the question’
(Shakespeare, Hamlet, 3, i, 56) survives intact by replication within
Western culture because it has the property of cultural salience – in
Brodie’s terms, it has the effect of ‘pushing our [psychological-
emotional] buttons’ because of its arresting existential imagery23 –
which promotes its replication. The attributes of ‘longevity’ (the dura-
bility of any single copy of a replicator), ‘fecundity’ (the propensity of
a replicator to engender its duplication), and ‘copying-fidelity’ (the
accuracy of the replication process)24 ultimately decide the fate of all
replicators, be they genes, patterns of pitches and rhythms, or ‘a sheet
of paper that is xeroxed’.25
Just as with the gene, however, there is no hard-and-fast definition of
what constitutes a meme. Indeed, the biologist Seymour Benzer
proposed refining the somewhat loose concept of the gene by focusing
it into the categories of ‘muton’ (‘the minimum unit of mutational
change’), ‘recon’ (‘the minimum unit of recombination’) and ‘cistron’
(‘the unit responsible for synthesizing one polypeptide chain’).26 In
Dawkins’s view, however, the gene is
any portion of chromosomal material that potentially lasts for enough
generations to serve as a unit of natural selection . . . a genetic unit that is
small enough to last for a large number of generations and to be distrib-
uted around in the form of many copies . . . a unit which, to a high degree,
approaches the ideal of indivisible particulateness.27
tion of the musical continuum into memes by means of the criteria of particulateness and co-
equality.
30 Blackmore, The Meme Machine, 63.
348 STEVEN JAN
31 See Juan D. Delius, ‘Of Mind Memes and Brain Bugs: A Natural History of Culture’, The
Nature of Culture: Proceedings of the International and Interdisciplinary Symposium, October 7–11, 1986
in Bochum, ed. Walter A. Koch (Bochum, 1989), 26–79. Examples of such harmful memes, by
which is meant those which in some way impede the replication of the host’s genes, include, at
their most extreme, suicide cults (Blackmore, The Meme Machine, 47, 51) and, more subtly, memes
for contraception (Lynch, Thought Contagion, 91–2). The complex subject of gene-culture (meme)
‘coevolution’ is examined in William H. Durham, Coevolution: Genes, Culture, and Human Diversity
(Stanford, 1991).
32 Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of
Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life (2nd edn, London, 1860), ed. Gillian Beer (Oxford, 1996),
342.
33 Luigi L. Cavalli-Sforza and Marcus W. Feldman, Cultural Transmission and Evolution: A Quan-
All three conditions are satisfied by the meme, from its tendency to
miscopying (variation), its capacity for replication within the members
of a cultural community (heredity), and the contrasting fecundity of
different memes (differential fitness). On this reasoning, then, the
transmission and reception of musical culture is, in essence, the
outcome of a process of relentless competition between a near infinity
38 See Jan, ‘The Memetics of Music’ for an account, couched in terms of Narmour’s impli-
cation-realization model, of how mutational changes to a meme may increase its perceptual and
cognitive salience and therefore its propensity to imitation.
39 Dawkins, The Extended Phenotype, 284.
40 Ibid., 283.
41 Dawkins, The Selfish Gene, 192.
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART 351
From this synopsis of the memetic paradigm, and from the connec-
tions between the four pieces shown in Example 1 and discussed in
Section 2 above, it is reasonable to suggest that each of the patterns
A–G is indeed a meme, because each is a discrete and particulate entity
replicated in at least two of the four pieces – and in the case of four of
the memes, replicated in all four pieces. From their initial union in the
arietta, memes A, B, C and E are replicated in the Adagio, lied and aria
with three additional memes – D, F and G – being added in the Adagio
and subsequently replicated (aside from the absence of meme G in the
lied) in the later pieces.
Moreover, because the pieces – certainly the Adagio and the aria –
contain essentially the same complement and sequence of memes, the
succession in each piece might be regarded as a memeplex43 consist-
ing of the seven memes A–G. As Dawkins notes,
Memes, like genes, are selected against the background of other memes in
the meme pool. The result is that gangs of mutually compatible memes –
coadapted meme complexes or memeplexes – are found cohabiting in indi-
vidual brains. This is not because selection has chosen them as a group, but
because each separate member of the group tends to be favoured when its
environment happens to be dominated by the others.44
43 For a memeplex to occur, it seems reasonable to suggest the following two necessary
conditions. First, each of the particles constituting the memeplex must be replicated individually
in at least one other context, in order for each particle to attain independent memetic status.
Secondly, the collection of memes, the memeplex, must be replicated collectively in at least one
other context, in order for this higher-level grouping itself to attain memetic status.
44 In Blackmore, The Meme Machine, xiv.
45 It will be understood that the two types of hierarchy represented here are structural, as
opposed to Meyer’s cultural hierarchies (the concepts of laws, rules, etc.) discussed in Section 3.
The arrangement of this figure into ‘Context 1’ and ‘Context N’ represents the notion of repli-
cation over time.
46 That memes also exist in the rhythmic dimension, sometimes independent of pitch, can
be seen by comparing bar 6 of Example 1(a) with bar 10 of Example 1(b), where the pattern
is replicated. Indeed, a memetic reading of Maury Yeston, The Stratification of Musical
Rhythm (New Haven, 1976), suggests the existence of rhythmic memes at hierarchic levels above
the immediate foreground of local attack points. For present purposes, however, I will focus
largely on memes in the parameter of pitch.
47 Narmour might regard the level-3 memes as ‘style forms’. These, he notes, are ‘those para-
metric entities which achieve enough closure so we can understand their functional coherence
without reference to the specific intraopus context from which they come – all those seemingly
time-independent patterns, large and small, from parameter to parameter, which recur with statisti-
cally significant frequency’ (Eugene Narmour, Beyond Schenkerism: The Need for Alternatives in Music
Analysis, Chicago, 1977, 173). Narmour might consider the level-2 memes to be ‘style structures’.
He notes that ‘the [statistically common] contexts which result from [the syntactic] arrangement
[of style forms] can be called style structures in the sense that they are directly tied to and contribute
to the structure of real pieces, not just to constructed classes of things, as are style forms. Unlike
the description of style forms, the identification of style structures involves ascribing time-
dependent function to patterns . . . in intraopus relationships’ (ibid., 174).
Level 1
Level 2
Level 3
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART
∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧
Background " ! " !
Middleground ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧
" # $ # ! " ! " # $ # ! " !
Foreground ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧ ∧
! $ " # $ " ! $ " # $ "
353
6
Arietta
10
Adagio
1
Lied
1
Aria
( )
Meme D E F
( )
Meme G
( )
)
(
( )
49 Constraints of space prevent a detailed examination of the four pieces in Schenkerian terms.
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART 357
50 Psychological studies have shown that the perceptual and cognitive reality of such virtual
structures, at least to most listeners untrained in formal/structural analysis, is often fragile. Long
concerned with this dichotomy, Cook speaks of ‘discrepancies between the way in which theo-
reticians and analysts think of compositions . . . and the way in which listeners respond to them’
(Nicholas Cook, Music, Imagination, and Culture, Oxford, 1990, 57). As a further complication, it
will be evident that the conceptual and graphical constructs used to comprehend musical pattern-
ing and structure are themselves memeplexes, being propagated within music-theoretical
communities and subject to variation and selection, especially according to the criterion of
perceived fit with that which they purport to explain. As such, they may not necessarily be suited
clearly to resolve (or even detect) elements of the music the composer situates below the immedi-
ately perceptible surface.
51 See Jan, ‘Replicating Sonorities’, Section 6, for more detailed discussion of the structural-
TABLE 1
PITCH EVOLUTION IN LEVEL-2 MEMES
Adagio lied aria a
meme A Adds a dissonant 7– 7–6–4–2 on G in bar 131. Reverts to the arietta’s treatment of the 6̂–5̂ melodic Restores the dissonant 7– 7–6–4–2 on G of the Adagio in bar 26.
motion (arietta bars 8–9; lied bar 4).
meme B Intensifies the dominant prolongation of bars Retains the vii7/V prolongation and its associated 4̂. Mutates the vii7/V of the Adagio and lied into an augmented-sixth
15–17 by means of the vii7/V of bar 16 and its Replaces the sequence V– vii7/V–V of the Adagio chord ( iv6–3, bar 56; ii 6–4–3, bar 66), perhaps derived from the
associated 4̂. (bars 15–17) with V– vii7/V–V– vii7/V–V (bars 8–12). arietta, bar 162–3. Retains the V–X–V–X–V pattern of the lied,
where X is vii7/V or an augmented-sixth chord.
meme C Mutates the melodic 4̂– 7̂ motion of bar 32 of Retains the 6̂– 7̂ motion of the Adagio in bar 13, and Mutates the rising motion 6̂– 7̂ into a falling pattern (bar 241).
the arietta to 6̂– 7̂ in bar 18. Eschews the double restores (bars 13–14) the double voice exchange of Inverts the double voice exchanges of the arietta and lied to
voice exchange f "/c'–g"/b –c"/f –b '/g of the the arietta. c"/f –b '/g–f '/c–g'/B (bars 244–253).
arietta (bars 32–4).
meme D Simplifies (bars 16–17) the descent 2̂ . . . 3̂ (bar 26) Retains (bars 264–273) the interruption V–VI of the lied (bars
of the Adagio. Reverts to the diatonic iv in bar 17. 152–161), and its unfilled melodic descent 2̂– 3̂. Combines this
(bars 27–303) with the harmonic plan of the Adagio (bars 26–9).
meme E Eliminates the cadence pattern of bar 39 of the The descending motion from 7̂ of the arietta (bars The pattern of bar 39 of the arietta is mutated and intensified by
arietta; but the emphases on V prolonged by 39–401) is simplified and taken further, to 7̂ (bar 2̂ in bar 32. Bars 33–5 intensify the prolongation of V of bars 40–1
harmonies containing 4̂ and 6̂ of the arietta 182), the bass figure of the arietta being retained. The of the arietta, introducing the chromatic 6̂ (bar 346).
(bars 40–1) are recreated in bars 33–5. prolongation of V of the arietta and Adagio is
eschewed.
meme F The descent 6̂ . . . 7̂ of the Adagio (bars 37–8) is Bars 362–38 of the Adagio are recreated in the tonic minor in bar
recreated in bars 20–2, but retains the tonic minor 374–6.
and cadences on 1̂.
meme G Recreates, in bars 384–406, the contour of bars 384–423 of the
Adagio/finale, retaining the tonic minor and adding chromatic
emphases on iv in bar 393 and the melodic 2̂ in bar 404.
a Looking vertically at some of the memes represented in Example 1 (or horizontally in Table 1), it might be said that, at times, the aria represents an evolutionary synthesis or amalgamation of features found in the other
pieces. For instance, in meme A the aria adopts the pitch sequence d'''–g" of bars 10–11 of the Adagio but in the register d"–g', first opened up in bars 1–2 of the lied. Similarly, the dissonant 7–7–6–4–2 on G of bar 13 of the
Adagio is restored in bar 4 of the aria, after its absence in the lied, but with the prefatory melodic octave rise g'–g" in bars 2–3, first introduced in the analogous bars 2–3 of the lied. Comparable syntheses may be found in
other memes in the aria, such as that concerning meme D noted in Section 2.
STEVEN JAN
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART 359
copy is made of the new form. When Mozart mutated the memes of the arietta in the Adagio in
May 1787 the resultant level-3 particles may not have been memetic, for they may, for a time, have
been unique, not yet imitated by other composers. Lynch speaks of a ‘mnemon’ – ‘an item of
brain-stored memory. When copied from one brain to another, it becomes a meme’ – in such
cases (Aaron Lynch, Mnemon 1998a: Y2K Memes (Issue 1), <http://www.mcs.net/~aaron/
Mnemon1998a.html>). See Jan, ‘Replicating Sonorities’, Sections 7 and 8, for more detailed
discussion of the mechanism of memetic mutation and stylistic evolution.
53 Dawkins, The Selfish Gene, 86.
360 STEVEN JAN
54 The difficulty of verifying this point – requiring the examination of all Mozart’s output –
TABLE 2
Violin
Viola I
Viola II
Violoncello
Vln
Vla I
Vla II
Vc.
(b) Antecedent coequal of meme C: Handel, Rinaldo, HWV 7a (1711), recitative before no. 20,
‘Qual incognita forza’, bars 16–18.
(b)
Rinaldo Eustazio Rinaldo
4+ 6
2
Example 4 continued
(c) Consequent coequal of meme D: Beethoven, 32 Variations on an Original Theme in C minor,
WoO
(c) 80 (1806), bars 1–8.
Allegretto
(d) Antecedent coequal of meme E: Haydn, String Quartet in F minor, op. 20 no. 5 (1772), I,
bars
(d)
9–12.
Allegro moderato
9
11
Example 4 continued
(e) Consequent coequal of meme G: Beethoven, Grosse Fuge in B major, op. 133 (1825), bars
726–34.
(e)
Allegro molto e con brio
726
cresc.
729
732
al più
exaptations. . . . They are fit for their current role, hence aptus, but they were
not designed for it, and are therefore not ad aptus, or pushed towards
fitness. They owe their fitness to features present for other reasons, and are
therefore fit (aptus) by reason of (ex) their form, or ex aptus.56
While an account of the aetiology and evolution of the dominant
prolongation is beyond the scope of this article, it is not difficult to
imagine, in the context of late-modal/early-tonal music, the notion of
the end-dominant being an exaptation from a historically earlier begin-
ning-dominant – or vice versa.
Example 4(e), the consequent coequal of meme G, is closest to the
aria in its harmonic structure of chords based upon the descending-
third sequence G–E –C (the antecedent coequal of this meme, from
the finale of Haydn’s String Quartet op. 17 no. 5, is perhaps closer,
certainly in melodic terms, to the quintet’s finale theme). Beethoven’s
progression occurs, however, in the context of B major, not G minor,
and starts with an initial third drop B –G. Moreover, Beethoven’s
phrase is not a mutation of the whole of Mozart’s meme but of only a
part of it; were Mozart’s bar 38 to begin in B , then Beethoven’s
passage would be a copy of Mozart’s bars 38–395. In this process of
cutting and splicing, in which a segment of a meme is taken from an
antecedent source and embedded into a later context, the passage
from the Grosse Fuge may be regarded as a memetic analogue to the
biological process of ‘crossing over’. Here, the random exchange of
components of the chromosome occurring during meiosis (cell
division) results in segments of genes being extracted and repositioned
on other chromosomes.
56 Stephen J. Gould and Elisabeth S. Vrba, ‘Exaptation – A Missing Term in the Science of
number,57 these last five are intimately linked by the content of their
texts. To my knowledge, no commentator has identified that, despite
the widely different dramatic context of each aria, the sentiments of
the characters have a common motivation: the experience of parting
or loss.58
From this, it seems reasonable to suggest that G minor is a key Mozart
began to associate, in the 1780s, with loss – not, as Einstein maintains,
with the arguably less focused notion of ‘fate’59 – and that the repli-
cation of the same memes in the four pieces considered here may
imply that the G minor quintet’s Adagio has ‘hidden’ the same verbal-
conceptual memes explicitly presented in the three vocal contexts. Put
in more conventional terminology, the quintet’s Adagio might be seen
as having a ‘subtext’ of parting or loss. This notion is readily explica-
ble from a semiotic perspective, wherein the musical memes fulfil the
function of ‘signifier(s)’, and the verbal-conceptual memes with which
they are coadapted in the arietta, lied and aria act as the ‘signified’. In
the Adagio, the signified, whilst not explicitly presented, is neverthe-
less resonant by virtue of the unequivocal presence of the signifiers.
Memes A, D and F, in particular, are strongly conformant in the
Adagio and aria, and it seems reasonable to suggest that a memetic
perspective may facilitate a hermeneutic analysis of the Adagio,
whereby one may ‘retrospectively’ append the verbal-conceptual
memes associated with certain musical memes in the aria to the corre-
sponding musical memes in the Adagio.
Why does the F minor Trennungslied contain memes replicated in
three G minor pieces? This seems to be the consequence of some
striking similarities between the verbal-conceptual memes of ‘Da
schlägt’ and ‘Die Engel’, which may have acted as a cue for the repli-
cation in the lied of the musical memes associated with the verbal-
conceptual memes of the arietta. The texts of the arietta, by the
librettist of Die Entführung aus dem Serail, Gottlieb Stephanie
(1741–1800), and of the lied, by Klamer Eberhard Karl Schmidt
(1746–1824), contain general similarities in imagery which gravitate
around the remarkably specific replication of certain verbal-concep-
tual memes. In the arietta, ‘the hour of parting strikes’ and the singer
contemplates, in the meme ‘Und du, und du, vielleicht auf ewig
vergißt . . .’ (bars 26–32), the possibility that her departed lover will
forget her. In the lied, this same meme is a persistent refrain at the end
of the vocal element of each strophe (bars 12–19). This verbal-concep-
tual meme occurs in the context of meme C, perhaps the most overtly
rhetorical of the seven level-2 memes in its surface realization; it seems
57 These arias are ‘Betracht dies Herz’ (Der Engel), no. 2 of the Grabmusik (Passionskantate),
K.42/35a (1767); ‘Nel sen mi palpita’ (Aspasia), no. 4 of Mitridate, re di Ponto, K.87/74a (1770);
‘Ma qual virtù’ (Cabri), no. 2 of La Betulia liberata, K.118/74c (1771); ‘Vorrei punirti indegno’
(Arminda), no. 13 of La finta giardiniera, K.196 (1775); and ‘Tiger! wetze nur die Klauen’ (Zaïde),
no. 13 of Zaïde, K.344/336b (1779).
58 Jan, Aspects of Mozart’s Music in G Minor, 56–7.
59 Alfred Einstein, Mozart: His Character, his Work, trans. Arthur Mendel and Nathan Broder (6th
to come from the world of opera seria, as does its possible progenitor
shown in Example 4(b) above.
The memetic connections between these texts are the result of their
descent from Metastasio’s celebrated canzonetta ‘Ecco quel fiero
istante’ (La Partenza) of 1746, as shown by the extracts in Table 3. ‘Die
Engel’ (1779) is a ‘second-generation’ copy, being modelled on ‘Da
schlägt des Abschieds Stunde’ (Die Trennung) of 1773 by Johann
Joachim Eschenburg (1743–1820), an earlier reworking of Metastasio’s
canzonetta.60 Both Eschenburg and Schmidt preserve the metrical
structure of Metastasio’s poem in their reworking of its content into
German. ‘Da schlägt’, as Table 3 shows, is based on the first verse of
the Metastasio and is derived from the Eschenburg version, as
evidenced by the replication, with mutation, of the meme ‘Da schlägt
des Abschieds Stunde’; indeed, Stephanie takes nothing from Schmidt
that is not already in Eschenburg. The memetic connections between
the four poems are italicized in Table 3.
From these observations one might identify three context-specific
conditions governing the relationship in Mozart between the key of G
minor, the memeplex considered here, and its associated verbal-
conceptual memes. First, it may be said that the strongest ‘trigger’ for
this memeplex appears to be verbal-conceptual memes expressing the
sentiment of loss plus the key of G minor. Secondly, the complex may
also appear in other minor keys provided that the verbal-conceptual
memes are present. Thirdly, from the case of the Adagio, it can be seen
that the memeplex may also appear when only the key of G minor is
present, in the absence of the verbal-conceptual memes. Nevertheless,
it will also be evident – given that the memeplex does not appear in
the G minor ‘loss’ arias ‘Padre, germani’, ‘Traurigkeit’ and ‘Zum
Leiden’ – that the first of the three conditions noted above is neces-
sary but not sufficient.
The following closing points should draw together the various themes
considered here. First, I hope the discussion of the four Mozart pieces
in Sections 2, 4 and 5 is seen as offering convincing evidence for the
validity of the memetic paradigm, both as a means of understanding
the nature of human culture in general, and as a specific tool for
comprehending synchronic musical organization and diachronic
musical style change.
Secondly, I hope to have offered a different perspective on Mozart’s
compositional processes, showing how large-scale intertextual struc-
tures may have been an important element of his approach to compo-
sition, and indeed that of other composers.
Thirdly, however, I hope to have suggested – yet not without a tinge
Amadé Mozarts, ed. Franz Giegling, Alexander Weinmann and Gerd Sievers (8th edn, Wiesbaden,
1983), 583.
TABLE 3
368
Ecco quel fiero istante; Da schlägt des Die Engel Gottes weinen, Da schlägt die
Nice, mia Nice, addio. Abschieds Stunde, wo Liebende sich trennen! Abschiedsstunde,
Um grausam uns zu trennen; um grausam uns zu trennen.
Come vivrò, ben mio, Wie werd’ ich leben können, Wie werd’ ich leben können, Wie werd’ ich leben können,
così lontan da te? O Mädchen, ohne dich? o Mädchen, ohne dich? o Damon, ohne dich?
Io vivrò sempre in pene, Ein Fremdling aller Freuden Ein Fremdling allen Freuden, Ich will dich begleiten,
io non avrò più bene; Leb’ ich noch, um zu leiden, leb’ ich fortan dem Leiden! im Geist dir zu Seiten
schweben um dich.
e tu, chi sa se mai Und du, und du Und du? und du? Und du, und du,
vielleicht auf ewig Vielleicht auf ewig vielleicht auf ewig
ti sovverrai di me! Vergißt nun Daphne mich! vergißt Louisa mich! vergißt dafür auf mich!
Doch nein!
wie fällt mir sowas ein?
Du kannst gewiß nicht treulos sein,
ach nein, ach nein.
Here is the fierce moment; The hour of parting strikes, The angels of God weep, The hour of parting strikes,
Nice, my Nice, farewell. that so cruelly sunders us; where lovers separate! that so cruelly sunders us.
How shall I live, my darling, How shall I be able to live, How shall I be able to live, How shall I be able to live,
thus far from you? without you, oh maiden? without you, oh maiden? O Damon, without you?
I shall live ever in pain, A stranger to all joys, A stranger to all joys, I want to go with you,
I shall have no more good things; I live on through the sorrow, I live on through the sorrow! in spirit by your side
to hover near you.
and you, who knows if by chance And you? and you? And you? and you? And you, and you,
you should think again of me! Perhaps for ever Perhaps for ever perhaps for ever
Daphne will forget me! Louisa will forget me! will forget me!
But no!
How can I think such a thing?
You surely cannot be untrue,
STEVEN JAN
ah no, ah no.
THE EVOLUTION OF A ‘MEMEPLEX’ IN LATE MOZART 369
of regret – that taking the ‘meme’s eye view’61 of these pieces calls into
question traditional conceptions of Mozart’s conscious intentionality –
and indeed, by extension, that of every composer – and at the same
time illustrates how fragile are the boundaries of his works. This is
because, as was implied at the end of Section 3,
The self is a vast memeplex – perhaps the most insidious and pervasive
memeplex of all. I shall call it the ‘selfplex’. The selfplex permeates all our
experience and all our thinking so that we are unable to see it clearly for
what it is – a bunch of memes. It comes about because our brains provide
the ideal machinery on which to construct it, and our society provides the
selective environment in which it thrives.62
‘If this memetic analysis is correct’, Blackmore asserts,
the choices you make are not made by an inner self who has free will, but
are just the consequence of the replicators playing out their competition in
a particular environment. In the process they create the illusion of a self
who is in control.63
In a similar vein, Dennett asks ‘Cui bono?’, apropos of ‘those cases
when push comes to shove, and the interests of the body . . . conflict
with the interests of the genes’.64 Memetics applies the same principle
to the meme and therefore motivates a model of the composer as
vessel, a conception which maintains that, essentially, Mozart was the
conduit through which the selfish memes he imitated and mutated
passed. In short, I suggest the evidence considered here speaks, ulti-
mately, for the power of the replicator over that of the vehicle, to
employ Dawkins’s dichotomy.65
Fourthly, as implied in Section 4, I believe that the memetic
paradigm can motivate and guide a rethinking of the theory and
practice of analytical musicology, leading to a reconsideration of the
notion of structural value in analysis. A significant conclusion deriving
from the material considered here seems to be that a replicated struc-
ture common to two or more contexts should be privileged analytically,
irrespective of whether elements of that structure satisfy, for instance,
the Fuxian/Schenkerian voice-leading considerations (or, for that
matter, the Fortean/neo-Riemannian set/group-theoretical criteria)
normally imposed as conditions of structural importance in analysis.
In this sense, to a consideration of Satz (the surface profile of the
music and its articulation into units of structure and expression) and
of Ursatz (the deep-structural products – to reverse Schenker’s aeti-
ology – of voice-leading processes at shallower levels of organization),
analysis might profit from incorporating a sensitivity to what might be
termed the Memesatz. This dimension of music might be defined as
those salient intertextual structures generated and defined by repli-
cation. Such a focus on replication tends automatically to emphasize
61 Blackmore, The Meme Machine, Chapter 4.
62 Ibid., 231.
63 Susan Blackmore, ‘Meme, Myself, I’, New Scientist, 161/2177 (1999), 40–2 (p. 42).
64 Dennett, Darwin’s Dangerous Idea, 325.
65 Dawkins, The Extended Phenotype, 112.
370 STEVEN JAN
ABSTRACT
‘Memetics’, a concept most elegantly expounded by Richard Dawkins in The
Selfish Gene, asserts that human culture consists of a multitude of units trans-
mitted between individuals by imitation and subject to evolutionary pressures.
Such particles, ‘memes’, are broadly analogous to the genes of biological
transmission. Four late pieces of Mozart’s, including Pamina’s aria ‘Ach ich
fühl’s’ from Die Zauberflöte, are examined in terms of the meme concept and
a conglomeration, or ‘memeplex’, consisting of seven memes is identified
within them. The nature of the musical memeplex, in this specific case and
also more generally, is considered, particularly from the perspective of its
location at different levels of the structural hierarchy. The evolutionary
history of some of Mozart’s memes is examined with reference to selected
passages from works of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. Finally,
relationships between the musical memes under investigation and memes in
the verbal-conceptual realm are explored.