Chap2 Austin Truth
Chap2 Austin Truth
`What is truth?' said jesting Pilate, and would not stay for an answer.
Pilate was in advance of his time. For `truth' itself is an abstract noun,
a camel, that is, of a logical construction, which cannot get past the
eye even of a grammarian. We approach it cap and categories in hand:
we ask ourselves whether Truth is a substance (the Truth, the Body of
Knowledge), or a quality (something like the color red, inhering in
truths), or a relation (`correspondence').1 But philosophers should take
something more nearly their own size to strain at. What needs discussing
rather is the use, or certain uses, of the word `true.' In vino, possibly,
`veritas,' but in a sober symposium `verum.'
What is it that we say is true or is false? Or, how does the phrase `is true'
occur in English sentences? The answers appear at ®rst multifarious. We
say (or are said to say) that beliefs are true, that descriptions or accounts
are true, that propositions or assertions or statements are true, and that
words or sentences are true: and this is to mention only a selection of the
more obvious candidates. Again, we say (or are said to say) `It is true that
the cat is on the mat,' or `It is true to say that the cat is on the mat,' or
` ``The cat is on the mat'' is true.' We also remark on occasion, when
someone else has said something, `Very true' or `That's true' or `True
enough.'
26 J. L. Austin
Most (though not all) of these expressions, and others besides, cer-
tainly do occur naturally enough. But it seems reasonable to ask whether
there is not some use of `is true' that is primary, or some generic name for
that which at bottom we are always saying `is true.' Which, if any, of
these expressions is to be taken au pied de la lettre? To answer this will
not take us long, nor, perhaps, far: but in philosophy the foot of the letter
is the foot of the ladder.
I suggest that the following are the primary forms of expression:
It is true (to say) that the cat is on the mat.
That statement (of his, etc.) is true.
The statement that the cat is on the mat is true.
But ®rst for the rival candidates.
a. Some say that `truth is primarily a property of beliefs.' But it may be
doubted whether the expression `a true belief' is at all common outside
philosophy and theology: and it seems clear that a man is said to hold a
true belief when and in the sense that he believes (in) something which is
true, or believes that something which is true is true. Moreover if, as
some also say, a belief is `of the nature of a picture,' then it is of the
nature of what cannot be true, though it may be, for example, faithful.2
b. True descriptions and true accounts are simply varieties of true state-
ments or of collections of true statements, as are true answers and the
like. The same applies to propositions too, in so far as they are genuinely
said to be true (and not, as more commonly, sound, tenable and so on).3
A proposition in law or in geometry is something portentous, usually a
generalization, that we are invited to accept and that has to be recom-
mended by argument: it cannot be a direct report on current observation
Ðif you look and inform me that the cat is on the mat, that is not a
proposition though it is a statement. In philosophy, indeed, `proposition'
is sometimes used in a special way for `the meaning or sense of a sentence
or family of sentences': but whether we think a lot or little of this usage, a
proposition in this sense cannot, at any rate, be what we say is true or
false. For we never say `The meaning (or sense) of this sentence (or of
these words) is true': what we do say is what the judge or jury says,
namely that `The words taken in this sense, or if we assign to them such
and such a meaning, or so interpreted or understood, are true.'
c. Words and sentences are indeed said to be true, the former often, the
latter rarely. But only in certain senses. Words as discussed by philolo-
gists, or by lexicographers, grammarians, linguists, phoneticians, printers,
Truth 27
critics (stylistic or textual) and so on, are not true or false: they are
wrongly formed, or ambiguous or defective or untranslatable or unpro-
nouncable or misspelled or archaistic or corrupt or what not.4 Sentences
in similar contexts are elliptic or involved or alliterative or ungrammati-
cal. We may, however, genuinely say `His closing words were very true'
or `The third sentence on page 5 of his speech is quite false': but here
`words' and `sentence' refer, as is shown by the demonstratives (posses-
sive pronouns, temporal verbs, de®nite descriptions, etc.), which in this
usage consistently accompany them, to the words or sentence as used by
a certain person on a certain occasion. That is, they refer (as does `Many
a true word spoken in jest') to statements.
A statement is made and its making is an historic event, the utterance
by a certain speaker or writer of certain words (a sentence) to an audi-
ence with reference to an historic situation, event or what not.5
A sentence is made up of words, a statement is made in words. A sen-
tence is not English or not good English, a statement is not in English or
not in good English. Statements are made, words or sentences are used.
We talk of my statement, but of the English sentence (if a sentence is
mine, I coined it, but I do not coin statements). The same sentence is used
in making different statements (I say `It is mine,' you say `It is mine'): it
may also be used on two occasions or by two persons in making the same
statement, but for this the utterance must be made with reference to the
same situation or event.6 We speak of `the statement that S,' but of `the
sentence ``S,'' ' not of `the sentence that S.'7
When I say that a statement is what is true, I have no wish to become
wedded to one word. `Assertion,' for example, will in most contexts do
just as well, though perhaps it is slightly wider. Both words share the
weakness of being rather solemn (much more so than the more general
`what you said' or `your words')Ðthough perhaps we are generally being
a little solemn when we discuss the truth of anything. Both have the merit
of clearly referring to the historic use of a sentence by an utterer, and of
being therefore precisely not equivalent to `sentence.' For it is a fashion-
able mistake to take as primary `(The sentence) ``S'' is true (in the English
language).' Here the addition of the words `in the English language'
serves to emphasize that `sentence' is not being used as equivalent to
`statement,' so that it precisely is not what can be true or false (and more-
over, `true in the English language' is a solecism, mismodeled presum-
ably, and with deplorable effect, on expressions like `true in geometry').
28 J. L. Austin
3a
Troubles arise from the use of the word `facts' for the historic situations,
events, etc., and in general, for the world. For `fact' is regularly used in
Truth 29
conjunction with `that' in the sentences `The fact is that S' or `It is a fact
that S' and in the expression `the fact that S,' all of which imply that it
would be true to say that S.11
This may lead us to suppose that
i. `fact' is only an alternative expression for `true statement.' We note
that when a detective says `Let's look at the facts' he does not crawl
round the carpet, but proceeds to utter a string of statements: we even
talk of `stating the facts';
ii. for every true statement there exists `one' and its own precisely cor-
responding factÐfor every cap the head it ®ts.
It is (i) which leads to some of the mistakes in `coherence' or formalist
theories; (ii) to some of those in `correspondence' theories. Either we
suppose that there is nothing there but the true statement itself, nothing
to which it corresponds, or else we populate the world with linguistic
DoppelgaÈnger (and grossly overpopulate itÐevery nugget of `positive'
fact overlaid by a massive concentration of `negative' facts, every tiny
detailed fact larded with generous general facts, and so on).
When a statement is true, there is, of course, a state of affairs which
makes it true and which is toto mundo distinct from the true statement
about it: but equally of course, we can only describe that state of affairs
in words (either the same or, with luck, others). I can only describe the
situation in which it is true to say that I am feeling sick by saying that it is
one in which I am feeling sick (or experiencing sensations of nausea):12
yet between stating, however truly, that I am feeling sick and feeling sick
there is a great gulf ®xed.13
`Fact that' is a phrase designed for use in situations where the distinc-
tion between a true statement and the state of affairs about which it is a
truth is neglected; as it often is with advantage in ordinary life, though
seldom in philosophyÐabove all in discussing truth, where it is precisely
our business to prize the words off the world and keep them off it. To ask
`Is the fact that S the true statement that S or that which it is true of?'
may beget absurd answers. To take an analogy: although we may sen-
sibly ask `Do we ride the word ``elephant'' or the animal?' and equally
sensibly `Do we write the word or the animal?' it is nonsense to ask `Do
we de®ne the word or the animal?' For de®ning an elephant (supposing
we ever do this) is a compendious description of an operation involving
30 J. L. Austin
both word and animal (do we focus the image or the battleship?); and so
speaking about `the fact that' is a compendious way of speaking about a
situation involving both words and world.14
3b
`Corresponds' also gives trouble, because it is commonly given too re-
stricted or too colorful a meaning, or one which in this context it cannot
bear. The only essential point is this: that the correlation between the
words ( sentences) and the type of situation, event, etc. which is to be
such that when a statement in those words is made with reference to an
historic situation of that type the statement is then true, is absolutely and
purely conventional. We are absolutely free to appoint any symbol to
describe any type of situation, so far as merely being true goes. In a small
one-spade language tst nuts might be true in exactly the same circum-
stances as the statement in English that the National Liberals are the
people's choice.15 There is no need whatsoever for the words used in
making a true statement to `mirror' in any way, however indirect, any
feature whatsoever of the situation or event; a statement no more needs,
in order to be true, to reproduce the `multiplicity,' say, or the `structure'
or `form' of the reality, than a word needs to be echoic or writing picto-
graphic. To suppose that it does, is to fall once again into the error of
reading back into the world the features of language.
The more rudimentary a language, the more, very often, it will tend to
have a `single' word for a highly `complex' type of situation: this has such
disadavantages as that the language becomes elaborate to learn and is
incapable of dealing with situations which are nonstandard, unforeseen,
for which there may just be no word. When we go abroad equipped only
with a phrase-book, we may spend long hours learning by heartÐ
A 1 -moest-fai nd-e tschaÃr woume n,
Mai hwõÃl-iz-waur pt (beÁnt),
and so on and so on, yet faced with the situation where we have the pen
of our aunt, ®nd ourselves quite unable to say so. The characteristics of
a more developed language (articulation, morphology, syntax, abstrac-
tions, etc.), do not make statements in it any more capable of being true
Truth 31
or capable of being any more true, they make it more adaptable, more
learnable, more comprehensive, more precise, and so on; and these aims
may no doubt be furthered by making the language (allowance made for
the nature of the medium) `mirror' in conventional ways features descried
in the world.
Yet even when a language does `mirror' such features very closely (and
does it ever?) the truth of statements remains still a matter, as it was with
the most rudimentary languages, of the words used being the ones con-
ventionally appointed for situations of the type to which that referred to
belongs. A picture, a copy, a replica, a photographÐthese are never true
in so far as they are reproductions, produced by natural or mechanical
means: a reproduction can be accurate or lifelike (true to the original), as
a gramophone recording or a transcription may be, but not true (of ) as a
record of proceedings can be. In the same way a (natural) sign of some-
thing can be infallible or unreliable but only an (arti®cial) sign for some-
thing can be right or wrong.16
There are many intermediate cases between a true account and a
faithful picture, as here somewhat forcibly contrasted, and it is from the
study of these (a lengthy matter) that we can get the clearest insight into
the contrast. For example, maps: these may be called pictures, yet they
are highly conventionalized pictures. If a map can be clear or accurate or
misleading, like a statement, why can it not be true or exaggerated? How
do the `symbols' used in mapmaking differ from those used in state-
mentmaking? On the other hand, if an air-mosaic is not a map, why is it
not? And when does a map become a diagram? These are the really illu-
minating questions.
so'). For we are aware that this relation is one which we could alter at
will, whereas we like to restrict the word `fact' to hard facts, facts which
are natural and unalterable, or anyhow not alterable at will. Thus, to
take an analogous case, we may not like calling it a fact that the word
elephant means what it does, though we can be induced to call it a (soft)
factÐand though, of course, we have no hesitation in calling it a fact
that contemporary English speakers use the word as they do.
An important point about this view is that it confuses falsity with
negation: for according to it, it is the same thing to say `He is not at
home' as to say `It is false that he is at home.' (But what if no one has
said that he is at home? What if he is lying upstairs dead?) Too many
philosophers maintain, when anxious to explain away negation, that a
negation is just a second order af®rmation (to the effect that a certain ®rst
order af®rmation is false), yet, when anxious to explain away falsity,
maintain that to assert that a statement is false is just to assert its nega-
tion (contradictory). It is impossible to deal with so fundamental a matter
here.22 Let me assert the following merely. Af®rmation and negation are
exactly on a level, in this sense, that no language can exist which does not
contain conventions for both and that both refer to the world equally
directly, not to statements about the world: whereas a language can quite
well exist without any device to do the work of `true' and `false.' Any
satisfactory theory of truth must be able to cope equally with falsity:23
but `is false' can only be maintained to be logically super¯uous by making
this fundamental confusion.
There is another way of coming to see that the phrase `is true' is not
logically super¯uous, and to appreciate what sort of a statement it is to
say that a certain statement is true. There are numerous other adjectives
which are in the same class as `true' and `false,' which are concerned, that
is, with the relations between the words (as uttered with reference to an
historic situation) and the world, and which nevertheless no one would
dismiss as logically super¯uous. We say, for example, that a certain state-
ment is exaggerated or vague or bald, a description somewhat rough or
misleading or not very good, an account rather general or too concise.
34 J. L. Austin
second part? I agree that to say that ST `is' very often, and according to
the all-important linguistic occasion, to con®rm tstS or to grant it or
what not; but this cannot show that to say that ST is not also and at the
same time to make an assertion about tstS. To say that I believe you `is'
on occasion to accept your statement; but it is also to make an assertion,
which is not made by the strictly performatory utterance `I accept your
statement.' It is common for quite ordinary statements to have a per-
formatory `aspect': to say that you are a cuckold may be to insult you,
but it is also and at the same time to make a statement which is true
or false. Mr. Strawson, moreover, seems to con®ne himself to the case
where I say `Your statement is true' or something similarÐbut what of
the case where you state that S and I say nothing but `look and see' that
your statement is true? I do not see how this critical case, to which
nothing analogous occurs with strictly performatory utterances, could be
made to respond to Mr. Strawson's treatment.
One ®nal point: if it is admitted (if ) that the rather boring yet satis-
factory relation between words and world which has here been discussed
does genuinely occur, why should the phrase `is true'' not be our way of
describing it? And if it is not, what else is?
Notes
6. `The same' does not always mean the same. In fact it has no meaning in the
way that an `ordinary' word like `red' or `horse' has a meaning: it is a (the typical)
device for establishing and distinguishing the meanings of ordinary words. Like
`real,' it is part of our apparatus in words for ®xing and adjusting the semantics
of words.
7. Inverted commas show that the words, though uttered (in writing), are not to
be taken as a statement by the utterer. This covers two possible cases, (i) where
what is to be discussed is the sentence, (ii) where what is to be discussed is a
statement made elsewhen in the words `quoted.' Only in case (i) is it correct to say
simply that the token is doing duty for the type (and even here it is quite incorrect
to say that `The cat is on the mat' is the name of an English sentenceÐthough
possibly The Cat is on the Mat might be the title of a novel, or a bull might be
known as Catta est in matta). Only in case (ii) is there something true or false, viz.
(not the quotation but) the statement made in the words quoted.
8. Both sets of conventions may be included together under `semantics.' But they
differ greatly.
9. `Is of a type with which' means `is suf®ciently like those standard states of
affairs with which.' Thus, for a statement to be true one state of affairs must be
like certain others, which is a natural relation, but also suf®ciently like to merit
the same `description,' which is no longer a purely natural relation. To say `This
is red' is not the same as to say `This is like those,' nor even as to say `This is like
those which were called red.' That things are similar, or even `exactly' similar, I
may literally see, but that they are the same I cannot literally seeÐin calling them
the same color a convention is involved additional to the conventional choice of
the name to be given to the color which they are said to be.
10. The trouble is that sentences contain words or verbal devices to serve both
descriptive and demonstrative purposes (not to mention other purposes), often
both at once. In philosophy we mistake the descriptive for the demonstrative
(theory of universals) or the demonstrative for the descriptive (theory of monads).
A sentence as normally distinguished from a mere word or phrase is characterized
by its containing a minimum of verbal demonstrative devices (Aristotle's `refer-
ence to time'); but many demonstrative conventions are nonverbal (pointing,
etc.), and using these we can make a statement in a single word which is not a
`sentence.' Thus, `languages' like that of (traf®c, etc.) signs use quite distinct
media for their descriptive and demonstrative elements (the sign on the post,
the site of the post). And however many verbal demonstrative devices we use as
auxiliaries, there must always be a nonverbal origin for these coordinates, which
is the point of utterance of the statement.
11. I use the following abbreviations:
S for the cat is on the mat.
ST for it is true that the cat is on the mat.
tst for the statement that.
I take tstS as my example throughout and not, say, tst Julius Caesar was bald
or tst all mules are sterile, because these latter are apt in their different ways
Truth 39