Multiculturalism and Indigenous Peoples
Multiculturalism and Indigenous Peoples
Subject: Political Science, U.S. Politics Online Publication Date: Jan 2015
DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195386653.013.17
Keywords: multiculturalism, indigenous peoples, culture, freedom, equality, democracy, justice, protective multi
culturalism, liberal multiculturalism, normative pluralism
Introduction
Philosophical engagement with the claims of indigenous peoples is often associated with
the “multicultural turn” in contemporary political theory. Multiculturalism is associated
with the partial accommodation of these claims over the past forty years, especially in
Australasia and North America. In Australia, for example, the rejection of the racist
“White Australia” migration policy, combined with limited but still significant recognition
of broader human rights norms in its approach to issues of racial discrimination, is often
linked to the emergence of multiculturalism as a public ideal (Webber 2001). However, it
is also true that political theorists, and indigenous groups themselves, have sought to dis
tinguish clearly between multiculturalism and the recognition of indigenous peoples’ land
Page 1 of 13
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
claims and self-government rights. Although connected, there are important differences
between these two approaches to cultural and political diversity.
The first approach is protective or communitarian multiculturalism. Here the basic idea is
that the central point of any form of public recognition or accommodation of a group is to
preserve the cultural integrity and authenticity of its way of life. This is often accompa
nied by a reified sense of culture, which is reduced to a discrete set of “traditional” prac
tices said to be at the heart of the group’s identity. Thus, in order to protect the individu
als, so this argument goes, we must preserve the group, and that means protecting the
Page 2 of 13
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
culture. The right to preserve one’s cultural authenticity is assumed then to preclude oth
ers from making judgments about the practices involved, including appealing to universal
standards of justice or human rights. The legitimacy of the exercise of authority within
these groups and of various internal practices is a matter for the group to adjudicate and
nobody else. This links multiculturalism closely to forms of communitarian political
thought.
The second approach is liberal multiculturalism, which has been far and away the most
prominent in recent political theory. There are many variations of this approach, but the
basic idea is that multiculturalism is justified as an approach to responding to cultural
and religious diversity, because doing so promotes and/or honors liberal values such as
equality, autonomy, toleration, and equal respect. Thus, although it may well support de
grees of cultural preservation or protectionism, this isn’t the central aim of liberal multi
culturalism. Cultural preservation and protection will be a function of the degree to which
multiculturalism promotes liberal ends.
The third approach to multiculturalism is neither protective nor liberal, and not really a
normative stance at all, but rather a critical perspective. According to this perspective,
multiculturalism is essentially a new version of the hierarchical and racialized modes of
political order that it is supposed to have displaced. It presents a critical lens through
which the various relations of power that operate via forms of liberal “government” can
be analyzed (Foucault 1991, 2007). Critics of multiculturalism are often concerned with
the limits of multicultural accommodation, especially the practical consequences of “real
ly existing liberal multiculturalism.” In particular, they point to the ways in which liberal
accommodation is essentially conditional: cultures that qualify for rights are assumed to
Page 3 of 13
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
be homogenous and bounded (even as the liberal state is pluralized); minorities are not
expected to challenge the basic legitimacy of the state and are expected to live up to pre
conceived notions of what a “good migrant” or “indigenous person” is supposed to be.
Liberal legal pluralism, on this reading, is basically a means of resubordinating marginal
groups within a legal system that leaves their substantive disadvantage intact. It might be
a subtle and less heavy-handed form of pluralism than earlier forms of colonialism, but
liberal multicultural “government” (understood in the broadest sense of the term) is basi
cally continuous with it (Day 2000; Povinelli 2002; Hage 1998). Even more broadly, inso
far as this analysis of multiculturalism puts power at its heart, it raises questions about
the way in which “minorities” and “majorities” are defined and produced in the first
place. Who is the “we” that tolerates “them,” and what are the underlying assumptions
about who or what can be accommodated, and why?
Each of these approaches picks out a distinctive strand of both the academic and public
discourse surrounding multiculturalism. There can be “harder” and “softer” versions of
all three. For example, one can find forms of protective liberal multiculturalism among
scholars for whom cultural difference is the crucial variable in addressing disadvantage.
Within this quadrant is a range of variations: some modes of protective liberalism license
greater intervention in cultural practices to promote liberal ends, others almost none,
save for the right to exit. Some liberals base their arguments on the value of autonomy,
others on toleration. An analysis of imperial liberal multiculturalism, on the other hand,
might focus on the conditions surrounding multicultural citizenship. Or it might question
the very ontology of liberal conceptions of “minorities” and “majorities” altogether.
A crucial question for multiculturalism here is: What is the proper subject of multicultur
alism—individuals, groups, cultures, or peoples (Song 2007)? In particular, any approach
to multiculturalism must account for the nature of groups and the issues they raise for
liberal democratic political theory and practice.
Page 4 of 13
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
One way to grasp these developments is through the gradual extension of citizenship
rights. If the struggle for equal citizenship throughout the nineteenth and twentieth cen
turies involved extending the rights of citizenship to encompass a greater number of peo
ple, as well as across a broader range of entitlements (civil, political, social, and econom
ic), then the demand for multicultural citizenship is simply another step along this path.
Multiculturalism is thus not a break with liberal citizenship, but rather the logical exten
sion of it in conditions of deep diversity.
Having said that, the basic claim at the heart of liberal multiculturalism, at least, is that
certain social and cultural identities deserve to be recognized, because without them, in
dividuals lack what they need for living decent lives. If human beings are always cultural
ly embedded beings, then equal respect for individuals means equal respect for the cul
tural forms they create, sustain, value, and inhabit. There are two important factors here.
The first has to do with the appeal to equality. The second has to do with the relationship
between individuals and groups.
First is the suggestion that “recognition,” or the accommodation of cultural, national, reli
gious, or ethnic difference, is connected to a rich sense of equality. Recall that according
to liberal neutrality, we treat someone equally when we respect and protect her basic
rights. Lying behind this idea is an appeal to the connection between equality and treat
ing people similarly. Of course, equality is always a matter of treating like cases alike, and
that means deciding what the relevant cases to consider are. But in the richer view, influ
enced by the work of John Rawls (1971, 1993), we treat someone equally when she has
the resources to enjoy the “fair value” of her basic rights, as well as genuine equality of
opportunity. In a culturally diverse society, members of both majority and minority groups
may well have very different capacities and needs that are relevant to judging whether
someone enjoys genuine equality of opportunity. A disabled person, for example, may
need to be treated differently than an able-bodied person in order to be treated with gen
uine “equal respect.” Both are entitled to equal civic liberties, but a disabled person may
require more resources to realize the equal value of her freedom. The interesting cases
are when this analogy is extended to cultural and national groups. Are there forms of ac
commodation or protection for minority groups that can be justified on the grounds of
promoting equality?
Page 5 of 13
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
To address positional difference, therefore, requires going well beyond “difference blind”
or neutralist liberalism. But it’s also a structural difference as opposed to a cultural one,
so focusing on cultural difference might well leave structural disadvantage inadequately
addressed. Cultural differences present another set of challenges. Here inequality can ex
ist in virtue of the relationship between the dominant “societal culture” and minority cul
tural groups. Sustaining their cultural practices can become more difficult for minority
cultural groups, and if this is mainly a result of the circumstances members face, as op
posed to the choices they make, then the situation is potentially unfair. The dominant
group can limit the opportunities of other groups to realize their ends, whether through
explicit repression or merely by growing or allowing minority practices to whither away.
Of course cultural change is not in itself something that can (or should be) prevented; the
case for sustaining minority cultural practices will depend on the connection between
their survival and the well-being of the group’s members.
Note that these two approaches to disadvantage are clearly not mutually exclusive, de
spite what some of the literature suggests. Members of a minority cultural group might
well suffer from various structural forms of inequality as well. Feminist analyses of the
situation of women and girls within minority groups, for example, bring this out very
clearly (Shachar 2001; Song 2007). However, depending on the nature of the disadvan
tage with which we are concerned, different solutions and approaches may be called for,
and tensions between different approaches can occur. Providing more autonomy for na
Page 6 of 13
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
tional minorities, for example, will require finding ways of ensuring vulnerable members
within those groups are treated equally and can exercise their freedom in meaningful
ways. Focusing on disadvantage through the lens of structural disadvantage tends to shift
discussion toward ideals of democratic citizenship that cut across cultural and national
differences. Focusing on the accommodation of cultural differences, on the other hand,
tends to shift discussion toward forms of collective autonomy and freedom. Any adequate
analysis of the challenge of diversity will require a subtle interweaving of the two.
Up until now we have been moving between ideas of what is owed to individuals and
groups, as if this relationship was relatively unproblematic. Remember that one of the
crucial factors identified above is equal respect for persons being extended to equal re
spect for cultures or groups. But we need an argument to link these two claims; one does
not follow automatically from the other. The tension is neatly demonstrated in the fre
quent slippage between talking about the “rights of minority cultures” and the “rights of
cultural minorities.” Can cultures have rights? Or are we instead really concerned only
with the rights of the individual members of those groups?
Many have criticized Kymlicka for this seemingly homogenous and bounded conception of
culture, however much he has used it to try to pluralize the nation-state (Carens 2000).
But for our purposes, it’s important to see how he thinks access to a societal culture and
freedom are connected. Providing groups with support for the preservation of their soci
etal culture not only extends a privilege larger groups enjoy, but helps promote important
liberal goods. What is being protected through self-government rights or language rights,
therefore, is not the particular content of any culture, but rather the structure within
which people exercise their freedom and through which they make sense of the world.
Kymlicka’s is not the only argument to link cultural membership with liberal values. And
indeed, many have criticized it for appealing to a value that might not be as universal as
he thinks. There are at least two other ways of linking cultural membership to liberal
Page 7 of 13
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
ends. Charles Taylor, for example, sees “recognition” as a crucial human good, given the
way it is linked to forms of personal and collective identity that enable common delibera
tion about the nature of the good in the first place (Taylor 1992). Because our sense of
self is shaped by the recognition (and indeed misrecognition) of others, the way the group
we identify with is recognized also matters. For Taylor, our identities are fundamentally
intersubjective, and this has important consequences for thinking about how we ought to
manage the deep diversity of modern societies. Joseph Raz (1998), on the other hand, ap
peals to the values of equal concern and dignity: if we take the equal worth of persons se
riously, then we need to be concerned about the well-being of the cultural groups they
value and to which they belong. Not all cultural groups provide the means for enjoying
equal concern and dignity. Only an “encompassing” group provides the kind of pervasive
cultural structure that is closely bound up with members’ self-identity and their well-be
ing and therefore deserving of protection (Margalit and Raz 1990).
So the most important forms of group membership are those that provide people with ac
cess to valuable human goods. For many people, these forms of identity are not easily
shed, but nor are they so constraining as to be necessarily incompatible with liberal free
dom. For Kymlicka and other defenders of liberal multiculturalism, the main task then is
to distinguish between ways of accommodating diversity that are compatible with liberal
ends and those that are not.
According to Kymlicka, groups that violate their members’ basic liberties or prevent them
from exercising their autonomy are not entitled to multicultural accommodation (al
though how we handle these situations in reality is a separate issue). For Raz, similarly,
the value of the equal worth and dignity of each individual constrains what cultures can
do to their members. In each case, individuals must be free to exercise a genuine right to
exit—however difficult that may be in practice (it can’t be merely a formal right). The
right to freedom of association is only really valuable if it also includes the freedom not to
associate (Shachar 2001; Song 2007).
At this point, for many critics liberal multiculturalism begins to look less multicultural and
more about defending a particular liberal way of life. As we have seen, for some liberals,
this is hardly a contradiction: the whole point of liberal multiculturalism is to transform
the way states engage with minority groups and how minorities, in turn, treat their mem
bers. But the critique of liberal neutrality also points to a deeper critique of liberalism it
self. And here we reach a critical point in the analysis of the relationship between the
claims of indigenous peoples and multiculturalism.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
self-governance (Turner 2006; Report of the Royal Commission 1996). Indigenous sover
eignty or autonomy is an assertion of autonomy that is not dependent on the grant of that
authority from any other entity. This is what Canadian theorists refer to as the “inherent
right of self-government” (Borrows 1992; Report of the Royal Commission 1996). Of
course the history of the state’s interaction with indigenous peoples—in North America
and Australasia, but not only there—is replete with conquest, colonialism, attempted as
similation, and neglect. Despite this, indigenous groups have continued to understand the
source of their rights of self-government to derive from their own practices, laws, and
constitutions, not from those of the settler states to which they have been subject.
But first of all, who counts as an indigenous people? This returns us to the challenge of
groups for contemporary political theory. There are two basic approaches to the question
of indigeneity. First, one can link indigeneity to actual first residency or occupation of a
particular territory. Contemporary indigenous peoples in this case would be descendants
of the earliest populations living on that territory. Second, one can tie indigeneity to those
peoples who lived in the territory before settlers arrived and the process of colonization
began. This relativizes the definition to prior occupation rather than first occupation
(Kingsbury 1998; cf. Waldron 2000). The first is tied most clearly to claims of first occu
pancy, whereas the second is a variable term, depending on the empire or conquering
power one is referring to, and thus to what happens to exist at that particular point in
time. Inevitably the two are mixed when invoked in relation to indigenous peoples today.
For example, James Anaya, one of the leading experts on indigenous peoples in interna
tional law, argues that the term indigenous refers to “the living descendants of pre-inva
sion inhabitants of lands now dominated by others…. They are indigenous because their
ancestral roots are imbedded in the lands in which they live… much more deeply than the
roots of more powerful sectors of society living on the same lands or in close proximi
ty” (1996, 3). However, it is also important not to restrict our understanding of the juris
diction and rights of indigenous peoples to mainly proprietary terms. Just as important is
the persistence and continuity of their legal and normative orders—their sovereignty—de
spite the extensive disruption caused by the consequences of colonialism. The assertion
of these legal and normative orders by indigenous peoples has been occurring since the
very beginning of colonization, first through practices of treaty making (Tully 1995) and
continuing until the present day in various domestic and international fora. Different
forms of aboriginal sovereignty have also been recognized in important legal cases in the
United States, Canada, and New Zealand, as well as in the recent United Nations Decla
ration of the Rights of Indigenous Peoples. (2007) Although we don’t have space to con
sider these issues here, note that an assertion of autonomy or sovereignty does not in it
self exclude other jurisdictions operating alongside or in conjunction with it (despite what
traditional conceptions of sovereignty might suggest). Nor does it follow that indigenous
forms of sovereignty need to mimic those associated with state-like structures to be legiti
mate. And these indigenous normative orders have and will continue to evolve and
change, both in light of the consequences of colonialism and as a result of the changing
practices and understandings of aboriginal communities themselves.
Page 9 of 13
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
What kind of rights are indigenous peoples’ rights that flow from these preexisting claims
of self-government and autonomy? Rights are not self-justifying. We use them to mark out
certain crucial interests or capacities of individuals and groups that deserve special kinds
of moral, legal, and political attention. A challenge facing anyone defending indigenous
rights is to make clear what work the modifier “indigenous” is doing. To what interests or
capacities do these rights refer? On the one hand, we can appeal to the historical, cultur
al, and political specificity of the interests at issue—to indigenous difference. This might
also lead us to emphasize the distinctive source of indigenous legal and moral rights—for
example, not only the hundreds of treaties that were signed between the various indige
nous nations and European settlers in the Americas from the fifteenth century onward,
but also the distinctive legal and cultural traditions in which they are embedded. The
treaties themselves, as well as the normative framework of recognition, negotiation, and
consent that they represent, offer both a legal and moral framework for justifying and
clarifying the rights of indigenous peoples. However, the danger in appealing to historical
agreements as the source of rights is that the actual agreements might be morally prob
lematic in various ways. The terms might be unfair, and the conditions under which they
were negotiated could be deeply unequal. But it also risks tying the recognition and con
tent of those rights to a sense of indigenous peoples’ radical otherness from Anglo-Euro
pean law. This can sometimes work against indigenous claims, because courts can limit
the recognition of indigenous rights to those practices or norms that were in place at the
time of European settlement, or just before (Asch 1999; Tully 2008). This can limit the
ability of indigenous peoples to extend and adapt those activities they see as integral to
their ongoing ways of life, at the same time staying true to their assertion of rights of in
herent self-government. It can also serve to depoliticize their claims, such as when courts
and governments choose to emphasize the recognition of “lifestyle rights” over more ex
plicitly political ones, such as self-government.
A second approach, therefore, is to appeal to more general rights, and especially human
rights, and to argue that indigenous rights are a species of these kinds of claims. Thus
they refer to interests or capacities that everyone, whether indigenous or not, deserves to
have protected or promoted. Reference to indigenous right, therefore, is a pragmatic
move; it is intended to extend to indigenous peoples those rights to which they have al
ways been entitled, but that have been denied for contingent historical and political rea
sons. It interweaves the emergence of human rights norms as an increasingly normative
presence in global politics and international law with the continued assertion of indige
nous normative and legal orders (with indigenous sovereignty, in other words). But this of
course returns us to some of the tensions explored above about limits of legal and politi
cal pluralism and the basis upon which those limits are justified and determined.
For example, what is the extent to which indigenous peoples’ rights include not only indi
vidual rights, but also group rights? And what should the proper balance between them
be, as well as the mechanisms for managing that balance? Do indigenous peoples have
collective rights, in the sense of a right possessed by the group as a whole, as opposed to
by just the individual members? Focusing on individual rights alone, as we saw above,
might not offer enough protection from the harms indigenous peoples have suffered from,
Page 10 of 13
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
given the history of colonialism, and might not suit the distinctive interests they seek to
protect. Indigenous land rights, for example, are conceived of as a collective right, be
cause “aboriginal” or “native” title is usually said to inhere in the group, as opposed to
the individual members (although there are individual entitlements within that underly
ing collective title). The right to self-determination is also often conceived of as a group
right, insofar as it is a right that only the group as a whole can exercise jointly. If indige
nous peoples do indeed have a moral and legal right to self-determination, and the right
to self-determination is a basic human right, then there is at least one genuinely collec
tive human right. The best justification of the right to self-determination is one that em
beds it within the constraints of a broader structure of human rights, as well as detaching
it from any necessary association with statehood—an association that historically has
been a source of continual confusion and realpolitik in international law. In fact, the polit
ical activism of indigenous peoples in global politics has helped to generate new thinking
about the nature of sovereignty and self-determination more generally.
Conclusion
The purpose of this chapter has not been to demonstrate that multiculturalism and the
claims of indigenous peoples are fundamentally at odds with each other. Rather, my aim
has been to point to important connections and differences. Paying attention to the differ
ent claims present in multicultural societies is crucial for being able to do justice to them.
In particular, in making sense of indigenous peoples’ claims in contemporary liberal
democracies, the persistence of different, contemporaneous, and complex legal and nor
mative orders is important to acknowledge and engage with, both theoretically and politi
cally. The persistence of normative pluralism is sometimes taken to be a sign of illiberal
ism and the absence of a settled constitutional and political order. However, in genuinely
multicultural and multinational societies, we should see this normative pluralism as the
starting point—rather than the terminus—of new forms of democratic community.
References
Anaya, J. 1996. Indigenous Peoples in International Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Asch, M. 1999. “From Calder to Van der Peet: Aboriginal Rights and Canadian Law, 1973–
96.” In Paul Havemann (ed)., Indigenous Peoples’ Rights in Australia, Canada, & New
Zealand. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. 428–445.
Borrows, J. 1992. “A Genealogy of Law: Inherent Sovereignty and First Nations Self-gov
ernment.” Osgoode Hall Law Journal 30: 291–353.
Day, R. 2000. Multiculturalism and the History of Canadian Diversity. Toronto: University
of Toronto Press.
Page 11 of 13
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Ivison, D. 2010. “Multiculturalism as a Public Ideal.” In D. Ivison (ed.), The Ashgate Re
search Companion to Multiculturalism. Farnham, UK: Ashgate. Pp. 1–16.
Kymlicka, W. 1989. Liberalism, Community, and Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kymlicka, W. 2002. Contemporary Political Philosophy. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Margalit, A., and J. Raz. 1990. “National Self-Determination.” Journal of Philosophy 87:
439–461.
Povinelli, E. A. 2002. The Cunning of Recognition: Indigenous Alterities and the Making of
Australian Multiculturalism. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Report of the Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples. Vol. 2, Restructuring the Relation
ship. 1996. Ottawa: Minister of Supply and Services Canada.
Page 12 of 13
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Song, S. 2007. Justice, Gender and the Politics of Multiculturalism. Cambridge, UK: Cam
bridge University Press.
Tully, J. 2008. Public Philosophy in a New Key. 2 vols. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Turner, D. 2006. This Is Not a Peace Pipe: Towards a Critical Indigenous Philosophy.
Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Young, I. M. 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univer
sity Press.
Notes:
(2) On the history of the emergence of multicultural approaches, see Kymlicka (1995,
2001, 2007b).
Duncan Ivison
Currently Dean of Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences at The University of Sydney;
Professor in the Department of Philosphy.
Page 13 of 13
PRINTED FROM OXFORD HANDBOOKS ONLINE (www.oxfordhandbooks.com). © Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights
Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in
Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).