Disproof of Bell's Theorem: Illuminating The Illusion of Entanglement (Second Edition)
Disproof of Bell's Theorem: Illuminating The Illusion of Entanglement (Second Edition)
net/publication/284283974
CITATIONS READS
7 66
1 author:
Joy Christian
University of Oxford
59 PUBLICATIONS 486 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Joy Christian on 21 November 2015.
Second Edition
Joy Christian
BrownWalker Press
Boca Raton
Contents
Preface to Second Edition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . xiii
Acknowledgements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . xv
1 On the Local-Realistic Origins of Quantum Correlations 1
1.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1
1.2 Local Origins of the EPR-Bohm Correlations . 5
1.3 Local Origins of ALL Quantum Correlations . 12
1.4 The Raison D’être of Quantum Correlations . . 17
1.5 Local Causality and the Division Algebras . . . 19
1.6 Concluding Remarks . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20
Appendix 1: A 2-D Analogue of EPRB Correlation 21
2 Disproof of Bell’s Theorem by Clifford Algebra Valued
Local Variables 29
3 Can Bell’s Prescription for the Physical Reality be
Considered Complete? 39
4 Failure of Bell’s Theorem and the Local Causality of
the Entangled Photons 49
5 Further Consolidations of the Disproof 59
5.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 59
5.1.1 Exact, Deterministic, Locally Causal Model for
the EPR - Bohm Correlations . . . . . . . . . . . 60
5.1.2 Eight Essential Requirements Satisfied by the Model 61
5.2 Operational Adequacy of the Local Beables
An (µ), and a Theory of their Measurement . . 64
5.3 Local Causality of the Model at the Level of
Microstates . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 69
5.3.1 Remote Parameter Independence in the Local Model 72
5.3.2 Remote Outcome Independence in the Local Model 74
5.4 Statistical Interpretation of the Entangled
Singlet State . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76
ix
5.5 Derivation of the Malus’s Law for Sequential
Spin Measurements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 78
5.6 Concluding Remarks . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 80
6 Disproofs of Bell, GHZ, and Hardy Type Theorems
and the Illusion of Entanglement 83
6.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 83
6.2 EPR Elements of Reality are Points of a Unit
2-Sphere, not 0-Sphere as Bell Assumed . . . . 87
6.3 Bell’s Theorem, its Variants, and their
Spin-offs are All Non-Starters At Best . . . . . 92
6.4 Topologically Correct Local-Realistic
Framework for the EPR-Type Correlations . . 96
6.5 Exact, Local, and Realistic Completions of
the GHZ-3, GHZ-4, and Hardy States . . . . . . 110
6.5.1 Exact Local-Realistic Completion of the Hardy State 110
6.5.2 Exact Local-Realistic Completion of the Four-Particle
GHZ State . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 117
6.5.3 Exact Local-Realistic Completion of the Three-Particle
GHZ State . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 124
6.6 Exact Local-Realistic Completion of Any
Arbitrary Entangled State is Always Possible . 129
6.7 Concluding Remarks . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 134
7 What Sets the Upper Bound on Quantum Correlations?141
7.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 142
7.2 Completing Bell’s Incomplete Accounting . . . 145
7.3 What Would Alice Observe at Her Detector? . 154
7.4 Upper Bound is Set by Maximum Possible
Torsion in the Set of All Possible Outcomes . . 158
7.4.1 When Codomain is an Arbitrary Manifold . . . 159
7.4.2 When Codomain is a Parallelized 3-Sphere . . 162
7.4.3 When Codomain is a Parallelized 1-Sphere . . 168
7.4.4 When Codomain is a Parallelized 0-Sphere . . 168
7.4.5 When Codomain is a Parallelized 7-Sphere . . 169
x
7.5 Concluding Remarks . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 180
8 Restoring Local Causality and Objective Reality to
the Entangled Photons 187
Appendix 2: Error Propagation Within a 3-Sphere . 204
9 Whither All the Scope and Generality of Bell’s
Theorem? 209
9.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 209
9.2 An Exact Local-Deterministic Model for the
EPR-Bohm Correlation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 210
9.2.1 A Complete Specification of the Singlet State . . . 210
9.2.2 Construction of the Measurement Functions . . . . 213
9.2.3 A Crucial Lesson from Basic Statistics . . . . . . 217
9.2.4 How Errors Propagate in a Parallelized 3-Sphere . 219
9.2.5 Derivation of Pair Correlations Among the Points
of S 3 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 228
9.2.6 Derivation of Upper Bound Exceeding the CHSH
Bound . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 229
9.3 Physical, Mathematical, and Conceptual
Fallacies of Weatherall’s Model . . . . . . . . . 234
9.3.1 What is Wrong with Weatherall’s Measurement
Ansatz? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 234
9.3.2 Why did We Lose the Strong Correlation for SO(3)? 236
9.4 Concluding Remarks . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 237
Appendix 3: Local-Realistic Violations of CHSH
Inequality as well as Clauser-Horne Inequality 238
A.3.1 Local-Realistic Violations of the CHSH Inequality
Verified in an Event-by-Event Simulation . . . . . 238
A.3.2 Computer Simulation also Confirms Local-Realistic
Violations of the Clauser-Horne Inequality . . . . 252
A.3.3 Another Explicit Simulation of the Model . . . 253
A.3.4 Exploring the World Beyond the Quantum World . 257
A.3.5 Elegant, Powerful, and Succinct Calculation of the
Correlation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 259
xi
A.3.6 What Can We Learn from Weatherall’s Analysis? . 260
10 Refutation of Richard Gill’s Fallacious Argument Against
my Disproof of Bell’s Theorem 263
10.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 263
10.2 A Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness1 . . . . . . 271
10.3 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 275
11 Refutation of Some Fallacious Arguments Against my
Disproof of Bell’s Theorem 279
11.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 279
11.2 Orientation of the 3-Sphere is Not a
Convention But a Hidden Variable . . . . . . . . 281
11.3 Handedness of the Bivectors is Not a
Convention But an Initial EPR State . . . . . . 289
11.4 Failure of Bell’s Theorem Implies
Vindication of the EPR Argument . . . . . . . . 290
11.5 The Local-Realistic Framework in Question is
Strictly Non-Contextual . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 291
11.6 Non-Commuting Standard Scores are
Merely Calculational Tools . . . . . . . . . . . . . 295
11.7 A Simply-Connected Model Cannot be
Simulated by its Discretized Imitation . . . . . 296
11.8 Counting the Number of Trivectors has No
Bearing on the Integration . . . . . . . . . . . . . 297
11.9 Twist in the Clifford Parallels Cannot be
Revealed by an Incorrect Rotor . . . . . . . . . . 298
11.10 Null Bivector is a Bivector that Subtends No
Meaningful Area . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 300
11.11 Correlation Between Raw Scores is Given by
Covariance Between Standard Scores . . . . . . 301
11.12 What is Asserted in Moldoveanu’s Preprint is Not
Necessarily What is True . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 302
11.13 Concluding Remarks . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 304
12 Replies to Critics 307
Appendix 4: The Meaning of a Geometric Product 334
xii
Preface to Second Edition
Joy J. Christian
Oxford, England
December, 2013
xiii
Chapter 9
Whither All the Scope and
Generality of Bell’s Theorem?
9.1 Introduction
209
he affirms to have been inspired by my work on Bell’s theorem
[2][3][4][5][6]. Although his analysis mainly concerns his attempted
reconstruction of my model and why the attempt fails, his preprint
has been worded in a manner that has allowed some readers to em-
brace his discussion as a criticism of my work on Bell’s theorem.
Here I demonstrate that (as he himself stresses to some extent) the
analysis Weatherall presents in his preprint has nothing to do with
my model, or with the physics and mathematics of the EPR-Bohm
correlation [7]. In fact his analysis exhibits no understanding of how
my local-realistic framework works, nor of the reasons why it explains
the origins of all quantum correlations [3][8]. I show this by first cal-
culating the EPR-Bohm correlation in a successful local-deterministic
model based on the spinor representation of SU(2), and then reveal-
ing a number of misconceptions and unwarranted assumptions in
Weatherall’s reconstruction of my model as it relates to the Bell-
CHSH inequalities [6]. I conclude that, contrary to first impressions,
Weatherall’s thinly veiled criticism of my work is entirely vacuous.
210
quantum mechanics for the rotationally invariant singlet state:
" n
#
1 X
E(a, b) = lim A (a, λk ) B(b, λk ) 6= − a · b . (9.2)
n≫1 n
k=1
211
[12][13]. Accordingly, β(r) ∈ S 2 ⊂ S 3 can be parameterized by a
unit vector r = r1 e1 + r2 e2 + r3 e3 ∈ IR3 as
β(r) := ( I · r )
= r1 ( I · e1 ) + r2 ( I · e2 ) + r3 ( I · e3 )
= r1 e2 ∧ e3 + r2 e3 ∧ e1 + r3 e1 ∧ e2 , (9.5)
A (r, λ) = + 1 or − 1 (9.8)
212
Returning to Weatherall’s analysis, it should be clear now that,
because it is based on a prescription other than (9.3), it too is a
non-starter [3]. More importantly, once we recognize that the only
way of providing a complete account of all possible measurement
results for the singlet state is by means of prescription (9.3), the sta-
tistical procedure for analyzing the correlation must be consistently
customized for the set S 3 of all unit quaternions, which Weatherall
fails to do. Since this procedure can be appreciated more readily
by studying the explicit construction of my model from my book
and elsewhere, I now proceed to reproduce the model in some detail
in the following subsections. Doing so will also dispel a persistent
but gravely disingenuous charge that my model encounters “certain
technical complications” [4][5].
(Here repeated indices are summed over.) Thus each positive di-
mensional real vector space has precisely two possible orientations,
213
which (rather suggestively) can be denoted as λ = +1 or λ = −1.
More generally an oriented smooth manifold such as S 3 consists of
that manifold together with a choice of orientation for each of its
tangent spaces.
It is important to note that orientation of a manifold is a relative
concept [14]. In particular, the orientation of a tangent space Vd of
a manifold defined by the equivalence class of ordered basis such as
{f1 , . . . , fd } is meaningful only with respect to that defined by the
equivalence class of ordered basis {f1′ , . . . , fd′ }, and vice versa. To
be sure, we can certainly orient a manifold absolutely by choosing
a set of ordered bases for all of its tangent spaces, but the resulting
manifold can be said to be left or right oriented only with respect of
another such set of ordered basis [14].
Now the natural configuration space for an EPR-Bohm type
experiment is a unit parallelized 3-sphere, which can be embedded
in IR4 with a choice of orientation, say λ = +1 or −1. This choice of
orientation can be identified with the initial state of the particle pair
in the singlet state with respect to the orientation of the detector
basis as follows. We first characterize the embedding space IR4 by
the graded basis
{ 1, L1 (λ), L2 (λ), L3 (λ) } , (9.9)
3
with λ = ± 1 representing the two possible orientations of S and
the basis elements Lµ (λ) satisfying the algebra
Lµ (λ) Lν (λ) = − gµν − ǫµνρ Lρ (λ) , (9.10)
with an arbitrary metric gµν on S 3 . Here the bivectors { aµ Lµ (λ) }
will represent the spin angular momenta of the particles, with µ =
1, 2, 3 and the repeated indices summed over. These momenta can
be assumed to be detected by the detector bivectors, say { aµ Dµ },
with the corresponding detector basis { 1, D1 , D2 , D3 } satisfying
the algebra
Dµ Dν = − gµν − ǫµνρ Dρ (9.11)
and related to the spin basis { 1, L1 (λ), L2 (λ), L3 (λ) } as
1 1 0 0 0 1
L1 (λ) 0 λ 0 0
D1 .
L2 (λ) = 0 0 λ 0 D2
(9.12)
L3 (λ) 0 0 0 λ D3
Evidently, the determinant of this matrix works out to be det(ωij ) = λ.
Since λ2 = +1 and ω 2 is a 4 × 4 identity matrix, this relation can be
214
more succinctly written as
or equivalently as
and
and
215
{ 1, Dν } has been fixed before hand [3][6]. Thus the spin bivector
{ aµ Lµ (λ) } is a random bivector with its handedness determined
relative to the detector bivector { aν Dν }, by the relation
L(a, λ) ≡ { aµ Lµ (λ) } = λ { aν Dν } ≡ λ D(a), (9.18)
where, as a direct consequence of the algebra (9.10) with gµν = δµν ,
the bivectors L(a, λ) satisfy the following identity:
L(a, λ) L(a′ , λ) = − a · a′ − L(a × a′ , λ). (9.19)
Using these relations the spin detection events (9.16) and (9.17) fol-
low at once from the algebras defined in (9.10) and (9.11).
Evidently, the measurement results A (a, λ) and B(b, λ) as
defined above, in addition to being manifestly realistic, are strictly
local and deterministically determined numbers. In fact, they are
not even contextual. Alice’s measurement result A (a, λ)—although
it refers to a freely chosen direction a—depends only on the initial
state λ; and likewise, Bob’s measurement result B(b, λ)—although
it refers to a freely chosen direction b—depends only on the initial
state λ. Let us also not overlook the fact that, as binary numbers,
A (a, λ) = ± 1 and B(b, λ) = ± 1 are still points of a parallelized
3-sphere. To confirm this, recall that a parallelized 3-sphere is a set
of unit quaternions of the form
ψ ψ
qk (ψ, r, λ) := λk cos + L r, λk sin , (9.20)
2 2
and a measurement result such as A (a, λ) = ±1 is a limiting case
of such a quaternion constituting the 3-sphere:
S 3 ∋ ± 1 = A (a, λ) = lim
′
A (a, a′ , λ)
a →a
= lim
′
{ − D(a) L(a′ , λ) }
a →a
= lim
′
{ ( − I · a)( λ I · a′ ) }
a →a
= lim { λ a · a′ + λ I · (a × a′ ) }
a′ → a
ψ ψ
= lim λ cos + L(c, λ) sin
ψ→ 2κπ 2 2
= lim { q(ψ, c, λ) } . (9.21)
ψ→ 2κπ
216
9.2.3 A Crucial Lesson from Basic Statistics
217
− D(a) is a non-random factor, independent of the orientation λ :
A (a, λ) = − D(a) L(a, λ) (9.25)
and B(b, λ) = + D(b) L(b, λ) (9.26)
Thus, as random variables, A (a, λ) and B(b, λ) are generated with
different standard deviations—i.e., different sizes of the typical error.
More specifically, A (a, λ) is generated with the standard deviation
− D(a), whereas B(b, λ) is generated with the standard deviation
+ D(b). These two deviations can be calculated as follows. Since er-
rors in the linear relations propagate linearly, the standard deviation
σ(A ) of A (a, λ) is equal to − D(a) times the standard deviation of
L(a, λ) [which I will denote as σ(A) = σ(La )], whereas the standard
deviation σ(B ) of B(b, λ) is equal to + D(b) times the standard
deviation of L(b, λ) [which I will denote as σ(B) = σ(Lb )]:
σ(A ) = − D(a) σ(A) (9.27)
and σ(B ) = + D(b) σ(B). (9.28)
But since the bivector L(a, λ) is normalized to unity, and since its
mean value m(La ) vanishes on the account of λ being a fair coin, its
standard deviation is easy to calculate, and it turns out to be equal
to unity:
v
u n 2
u1 X
σ(A) = t A(a, λk ) − A(a, λk )
n
k=1
v
u n
u1 X 2
= t || L(a, λk ) − 0 || = 1, (9.29)
n
k=1
where the last equality follows from the normalization of L(a, λ).
Similarly, it is easy to see that σ(B) is also equal to 1. Conse-
quently, the standard deviation of A (a, λ) = ± 1 works out to be
− D(a), and the standard deviation of B(b, λ) = ± 1 works out to
be + D(b). Putting these two results together, we arrive at the
following standard scores corresponding to the raw scores A and B:
A (a, λ) − A (a, λ) − D(a) L(a, λ) − 0
A(a, λ) = = = L(a, λ)
σ(A ) − D(a)
(9.30)
and
B(b, λ) − B(b, λ) + D(b) L(b, λ) − 0
B(b, λ) = = = L(b, λ),
σ(B) + D(b)
(9.31)
218
where I have used identities such as − D(a)D(a) = +1. Needless to
say, these standard scores are pure bivectors:
SU(2) ∼ S 3 ⊃ S 2 ∋ L(a, λ) = ± 1 about a ∈ IR3 , (9.32)
3 2 3
and SU(2) ∼ S ⊃ S ∋ L(b, λ) = ± 1 about b ∈ IR . (9.33)
219
Note that in this definition q(ψ) is coordinated by ψ to rotate
from 0 to 2π, whereas the conjugate q† (2π − ψ) is coordinated by ψ
to rotate from 2π to 0. Thus, for a given value of λ, both q(ψ) and
q† (2π − ψ) represent the same sense of rotation about r (either both
represent clockwise rotations or both represent counterclockwise
rotations). This is crucial for the calculation of standard deviation,
for it is supposed to give the average rotational distance within S 3
from its mean, with the average being taken, not over rotational dis-
tances within a fixed orientation of S 3 , but over the changes in the
orientation λ of S 3 itself. Note also that, according to the definition
(9.20), q(ψ) and its conjugate q† (ψ) satisfy the following relation:
220
Note that p(ψ, a) reduces to the unit bivector ± D(a) for rotation
angles ψ = 0, ψ = 2π, and ψ = 4π. Moreover, using the relations
L(a, λ) = λ D(a) and D2 (a) = − 1 it can be easily checked that the
product in (9.40) is indeed equivalent to the quaternion defined in
(9.20) for r = a. It is also easy to check that the non-random quater-
nion p(ψ, a) satisfies the following relation with its conjugate:
Consequently we have
†
q† (2π − ψ, a, λ) = {p(2π − ψ, a) L(a, λ)}
= L† (a, λ) p† (2π − ψ, a) = L† (a, λ) p(ψ, a) .
(9.44)
we have
v
u n
u1 X
σ[q(ψ, a, λ)] = t { p(ψ, a) L(a, λk ) } { L† (a, λk ) p(ψ, a) }
n
k=1
v ( )
u n
u
t 1 X k † k
= p(ψ, a) L(a, λ ) L (a, λ ) p(ψ, a)
n
k=1
p
= p(ψ, a) p(ψ, a)
= ± p(ψ, a) . (9.46)
221
The result for the standard deviation we have arrived at, namely
is valid for all possible rotation angles ψ between the detector bivec-
tor − D(a) and the spin bivector L(a, λ). For the special cases when
ψ = 0, π, 2π, 3π, and 4π, it reduces to the following set of standard
deviations:
which can be seen as such from the definition (9.20) above. Similarly,
for the conjugate of q(ψ = π, a, λ) we have
222
using some D(r), and multiply Eq. (9.21) from the left by D(r) and
from the right by D† (r), then we arrive at
A (a, λ) = lim D(r) q(ψ, c, λ) D† (r)
a′ → a
ψ ψ
= lim λ cos + L(a, λ) sin
ψ→ 2κπ 2 2
= lim { q(ψ, a, λ) }
ψ→ 2κπ
223
Substituting this and σ(B) = ± D(b) into Eqs. (9.30) and (9.31)
then immediately leads to the standard scores:
± A (a, λ) − A (a, λ)
A(a, λ) =
σ(A )
± D(a) L(a, λ) − 0
=
σ(A )
± D(a)
= L(a, λ) = L(a, λ) (9.60)
σ(A )
and
± B(b, λ) − B(b, λ)
B(b, λ) =
σ(B)
± D(b) L(b, λ) − 0
=
σ(B)
± D(b)
= L(b, λ) = L(b, λ) . (9.61)
σ(B)
This confirms the standard scores derived in the equations (9.30) and
(9.31) of the previous subsection.
So far I have assumed that randomness in the measurement
results A (a, λ) and B(b, λ) originates entirely from the initial state
λ representing the orientation of the 3-sphere. In other words, I have
assumed that the local interaction of the fixed detector D(a) with
the random spin L(a, λ) does not introduce additional randomness
in the measurement result A (a, λ). Any realistic interaction be-
tween D(a) and L(a, λ), however, would inevitably introduce such
a randomness, of purely local, experimental origin. We can model
this randomness by introducing an additional random variable, say
ra ∈ [ 0, 1], not dependent on λ. Physically we can think of ra
as an alignment parameter between the detector bivector D(a) and
the spin bivector L(a, λ), with ra = 1 representing the perfect align-
ment. Clearly, introduction of this additional random parameter will
make all the bivectors and quaternions unnormalized, and the corre-
sponding probability density function (9.34) would then represent a
Gaussian distribution—provided we also assume that the orientation
λ = ± 1 of S 3 itself is distributed non-uniformly between its values
+1 and −1. Moreover, although the measurement results would then
fall within the range − 1 ≤ A (a, λ) ≤ + 1, their mean value would
be zero for a uniformly distributed λ, since the mean value of the
product of the independent random variables ra and λ would then
224
be the product of their mean values:
± A (a, λ) − A (a, λ)
A(a, λ) =
σ(A )
± ra D(a) L(a, λ) − 0
=
σ(A )
± ra D(a)
= L(a, λ) = L(a, λ) (9.63)
σ(A )
and
± B(b, λ) − B(b, λ)
B(b, λ) =
σ(B)
± rb D(b) L(b, λ) − 0
=
σ(B)
± rb D(b)
= L(b, λ) = L(b, λ) . (9.64)
σ(B)
m(S) = a bivector
and σ(S) = a scalar. (9.65)
225
q(f )
m(A ) •
m(A ) − σ(A ) •
•
• •
q
m(S) − σ(S) m(S) m(S) + σ(S)
226
(9.34)—which can be represented by the 68% probability interval
[ m(S) − σ(S), m(S) + σ(S) ] (9.68)
as shown in the Fig. 9.1—propagate from the random bivector S to
the random scalar A , through the function f (S) = D S? To answer
this question we note that the two end points of the interval (9.68)
represent two points, say q− and q+ , of the 3-sphere, which is a
Riemannian manifold. The geometro-algebraic distance between the
points q− and q+ can therefore be defined, say, as
d q−, q+ = q− − q+ × sign q− − q+ . (9.69)
Moreover, from definition (9.67) of A and a first-order Taylor ex-
pansion of the function f (S) about the point S = m(S) we obtain
∂f
A = f (m(S)) + (S − m(S)) + . . . (9.70)
∂S S = m(S)
227
9.2.5 Derivation of Pair Correlations Among the Points of S 3
where I have used algebra defined in (9.10) and the relation (9.18).
Consequently, as explained in the paragraph just below Eq. (9.24),
when the raw scores A = ± 1 and B = ± 1 are compared, their prod-
uct moment will inevitably yield
" n
#
1 X
E(a, b) = lim A (a, λk ) B(b, λk ) = − gµν aµ bν ,
n≫1 n
k=1
(9.76)
since the correlation between the raw scores A and B is equal to
covariance between the standard scores A and B.
So far in this section we have put no restrictions on the metric
tensor, which, in the normal coordinates centered at a point of S 3
would be of the form
1
gµν (x) = δµν − R α µ ν γ xα xγ + O |x|3 . (9.77)
3
228
In other words, the algebra (9.10) we have used in the derivation
of correlation (9.76) is a general Clifford algebra, with no restric-
tions placed on the quadratic form [16]. On the other hand, if the
codomain of the measurement functions A (a, λ) is taken to be a
parallelized 3-sphere, then the above metric tensor specializes to
the Euclidean metric δµν , because the Riemann curvature tensor
of a parallelized 3-sphere vanishes, inducing a non-vanishing torsion
[6]. This case corresponds to the geometry of the group SU(2) and
specializes the correlation (9.76) to exhibit maximum strength:
229
a′ , b, and b′ , for the standard EPR-Bohm experiment. Then the
corresponding CHSH string of expectation values [3], namely the
coefficient
S(a, a′ , b, b′ ) := E(a, b) + E(a, b′ ) + E(a′ , b) − E(a′ , b′ ) , (9.82)
√
would be bounded by the constant 2 2, as discovered by Tsirel’son
within the setting of Clifford algebra applied to quantum mechanics
in general [3][17]. Here each of the joint expectation values of the
raw scores A (a, λ) = ± 1 and B(b, λ) = ± 1 are defined as
" n
#
1 X
E(a, b) = lim A (a, λk ) B(b, λk ) , (9.83)
n≫1 n
k=1
230
Using this identity we can now rewrite the CHSH string of expecta-
tion values (9.82) in two equivalent expressions,
S(a, a′ , b, b′ ) =
" n
# " n
#
1 X k k 1 X k k
lim Aa (λ ) Bb (λ ) + lim Aa (λ ) Bb′ (λ )
n≫1 n n≫1 n
k=1 k=1
" n
# " n
#
1 X 1 X
+ lim Aa′ (λk ) Bb (λk ) − lim Aa′ (λk ) Bb′ (λk )
n≫1 n n≫1 n
k=1 k=1
(9.89)
and
S(a, a′ , b, b′ ) =
" n
# " n
#
1 X k k 1 X k k
lim Aa (λ ) Bb (λ ) + lim Aa (λ ) Bb′ (λ )
n≫1 n n≫1 n
k=1 k=1
" n
# " n
#
1 X k k
1 X k k
+ lim Aa′ (λ ) Bb (λ ) − lim Aa′ (λ ) Bb′ (λ ) .
n≫1 n n≫1 n
k=1 k=1
(9.90)
Our goal now is to find the upper bound on these strings of expec-
tation values. To this end, we first note that the four pairs of mea-
surement results occurring in the above expressions do not all occur
at the same time. Let us, however, conform to the usual assumption
of counterfactual definiteness and pretend that they do occur at the
same time, at least counterfactually, with equal distribution. This
assumption allows us to simplify the above expressions as
" n
′ ′ 1 X
S(a, a , b, b ) = lim Aa (λk ) Bb (λk ) + Aa (λk ) Bb′ (λk )
n≫1 n
k=1
#
k k k k
+ Aa′ (λ ) Bb (λ ) − Aa′ (λ ) Bb′ (λ )
(9.91)
and
" n
′ ′ 1 X
S(a, a , b, b ) = lim Aa (λk ) Bb (λk ) + Aa (λk ) Bb′ (λk )
n≫1 n
k=1
#
k k k k
+ Aa′ (λ ) Bb (λ ) − Aa′ (λ ) Bb′ (λ ) .
(9.92)
231
The obvious question now is: Which of these two expressions
should we evaluate to obtain the correct bound on S(a, a′ , b, b′ )?
Clearly, in view of the identity (9.88) both expressions would give
one and the same answer [3]. Thus it should not matter which of the
two expressions we use to evaluate the bound. But it is also clear
from the discussion in subsections 9.2.3 and 9.2.4 that the correct
bound on the expression (9.91) involving the raw scores A and B
can only be obtained by evaluating the expression (9.92) involving
the standard scores A and B. Stated differently, if we tried to obtain
the bound on S(a, a′ , b, b′ ) by disregarding how the measurement
results have been generated in the model statistically, then we would
end up getting a wrong answer. By following the Bell-CHSH rea-
soning blindly Weatherall ends up making such a mistake. In the
end S(a, a′ , b, b′ ) is a functional of a random variable, and as such
proper statistical procedure tailored to my model must be employed
for its correct evaluation. This is an important point and the reader
is urged to review the discussions in subsections 9.2.3 and 9.2.4 once
again to appreciate its full significance.
With these remarks in mind we proceed to obtain the upper
bound on S(a, a′ , b, b′ ) by evaluating the expression (9.92) as fol-
lows. Since the standard scores Aa (λ) = L(a, λ) and Bb (λ) = L(b, λ)
appearing in this expression represent two independent equatorial
points of the 3-sphere, we can take them to belong to two discon-
nected “sections” of S 3 (i.e., two disconnected 2-spheres within S 3 ),
satisfying
232
and
1
T b′ b (λ) := [ Bb′ (λ), Bb (λ)] = − Bb′ ×b (λ) (9.96)
2
are the geometric measures of the torsion within S 3 . Thus, it is the
non-vanishing torsion T within the parallelized 3-sphere—the paral-
lelizing torsion which makes its Riemann curvature tensor vanish—
that is ultimately responsible for the strong quantum correlation
[3][7]. We can see this at once from Eq. (9.94) by setting T = 0,
and in more detail as follows: Using definitions (9.85) and (9.86) for
Aa (λ) and Bb (λ) and making a repeated use of the bivector identity
specialized for the metric gµν = δµν on S 3 , the above inequality for
S(a, a′ , b, b′ ) can be further simplified to
|S(a, a′ , b, b′ )|
v " #
u n
u 1 X
6 t4 − 4 (a × a′ ) · (b′ × b) − 4 lim L(z, λk )
n≫1 n
k=1
v " #
u n
u 1 X
6 t4 − 4 (a × a′ ) · (b′ × b) − 4 lim λk D(z)
n≫1 n
k=1
p
′ ′
6 2 1 − (a × a ) · (b × b) − 0 , (9.98)
−1 6 (a × a′ ) · (b′ × b) 6 +1 , (9.99)
233
is predicted by my model to respect, not the √ Bell-CHSH upper
bound 2, but the Tsirel’son upper bound 2 2, where C+− (a, b)
etc. represent the number of joint occurrences of detections + 1 along
a and − 1 along b etc.
This completes the presentation of my local, realistic, and deter-
ministic model for the EPR-Bohm correlation.
234
E (a, b)
+1
0 ηab
−1
0 90 180 270 360
quip: What Nature has joined together, let no man put asunder. By
contrast Weatherall’s codomain is disconnected between the space
IR3 ∧ IR3 of “bivectors” and the set {−1, +1} of scalars. His image
points can thus be at best either bivectors or scalars, but not both.
It is a disjoint world, more like the world of quantum mechanics.
Let us, however, be more charitable to Weatherall. Let us grant
him the codomain of his measurement functions to be the connected
real projective space IRP3 , which is homeomorphic to the rotation
group SO(3). After all, he does mention the Lie algebra so(3) in one
of his footnotes. So let us grant him the smooth one-step measure-
ment process
to reach the image subset {−1, +1}. This smooth map is well-defined
within my model, since IRP3 is simply the set S 3 of unit quaternions
[cf. Eq. (9.4)] with each point identified with its antipodal point
[6]. The measurement results ± 1 ∈ IRP3 ∼ SO(3) are thus limiting
points of a quaternion, just as in equation (9.21). The map that
takes us from S 3 to IRP3 can now be used to project the metric δµν
235
on S 3 onto IRP3 to obtain the following induced metric on IRP3 :
2
− 1 + π ηab if 0 ≤ ηab ≤ π
− Jµν aµ bν = (9.104)
2
+ 3 − π ηab if π ≤ ηab ≤ 2π .
236
equations (9.80) and (9.81) above:
This is the real reason why we lost the strong correlation for the
SO(3) case. The reason Weatherall has argued for is an artifact of
his bad choice of measurement functions. It stems from a failure
to appreciate the unified nature of the graded basis (9.102) and the
associated fact that the scalars {−1, +1} and the bivectors L(r, λ)
occur as image points within the same codomain S 3 in my model.
Thus the loss of correlation has nothing to do with the fact that
ultimately the measurement functions must map to the image subset
{−1, +1}. They manifestly do in my model [cf. Eqs. (9.16), (9.17),
and (9.21)]. The raw scalar numbers A = ± 1 and B = ± 1 mapped
to the image subset {−1, +1}—according to my model—are indeed
the numbers used by Alice and Bob for calculating the correlation
in the usual manner. And when, at the end of their experiment,
they evaluate the statistical quantity S(a, a′ , b, b′ ) involving these
numbers as
" n
′ ′ 1 X
S(a, a , b, b ) = lim Aa (λk ) Bb (λk ) + Aa (λk ) Bb′ (λk )
n≫1 n
k=1
#
k k k k
+ Aa′ (λ ) Bb (λ ) − Aa′ (λ ) Bb′ (λ ) ,
(9.108)
237
in fact identify at least six erroneous steps which engender the failure
of his model from the start:
238
predictions of quantum mechanics within our local model:
239
bivectors −L(et , λ) and L(et , λ) are projected by them onto the
detector bivectors D(a) and D(b), respectively. Then, as we defined
in Eqs. (9.16) and (9.17) above [cf. also Eq. (9.21)], we have the results
= lim { ( − I · a)( λ I · eo ) }
eo → a
= lim { +λ a · eo + λ I · (a × eo ) }
eo → a
(A.9.6)
and
= lim { ( + I · b)( λ I · eo ) }
eo → b
= lim { −λ b · eo − λ I · (b × eo ) }.
eo → b
(A.9.7)
Let me stress once again that the measurement results A (a, λ) and
B(b, λ) as defined above, in addition to being manifestly realistic,
are strictly local and deterministically determined numbers within
the 3-sphere. In fact, they are not even contextual. Alice’s measure-
ment result A (a, λ)—although it refers to a freely chosen direction
a—depends only on the initial state λ; and likewise, Bob’s measure-
ment result B(b, λ)—although it refers to a freely chosen direction
b—depends only on the initial state λ. In other words, they are
statistically independent events within S 3 .
Now, for the purposes of our calculations below, it is convenient
to make a note of the following useful identities:
240
S3
B = ±1
A = ±1
A B = ±1
and
241
Let us confirm this averaging conditions in some more detail by
explicitly rewriting equations (A.9.6) and (A.9.7) as
S 3 ∋ ± 1 = A (a; eo , λ)
= lim { + cos( ηaλeo ) + I · ca (λeo ) sin( ηaλeo )}
ηaλeo → κπ
(A.9.12)
and
S 3 ∋ ± 1 = B(b; eo , λ)
= lim { − cos( ηbλeo ) − I · cb (λeo ) sin( ηbλeo )}.
ηbλeo → κπ
(A.9.13)
C(a; eo , λ) = +1 ,
242
and similarly for C(a; eo , λ) = −1. Note that for a fixed orienta-
tion λ, say λ = +1, C(a; eo , +1) has only 25% chance of landing on
its face marked +1. But for λ = +1 or λ = −1, which is equiva-
lent to the possibilities ηaeo or π − ηaeo in the cos( ηaλeo ) part of
A (a; eo , λ), C(a; eo , λ) has further 25% chance of landing on its
face +1, because λ = +1 or λ = −1 are two mutually exclusive pos-
sibilities. Consequently, the die C(a; eo , λ) has exactly 50/50 chance
of landing on its faces +1 or −1 in general. Thus, the measurement
outcomes A = +1 or −1 observed by Alice (regardless of Bob) is
a result of a throw of the die C(a; eo , λ), which has 50/50 chance
of landing on its face marked +1 or −1, depending on the values
of ηaλeo . One can confirm these odds for C(a; eo , λ) in a computer
simulation, as has been done in the simulation described in Fig. 9.4.
Similarly, it is evident from Eq. (A.9.12) that for the occurrence of a result
A = −1 the angle ηaλeo must fall in the range [ π/2, π ] for λ = +1, and in the
range [ 0, π/2 ] for λ = −1, with the probability density remaining non-negative:
0 ≤ p(a; eo , λ) ≤ 1. Consequently, the probability of observing A = −1 is
Z π Z 2π
1 2
P (A = −1, a) = − cos( π − ηaeo ) sin( π − ηaeo ) dξyeo dηaeo
4π 0 0
Z π Z 2π
1
− cos( ηaeo ) sin( ηaeo ) dξyeo dηaeo
4π π2 0
Z π
1 2
= cos( ηaeo ) sin( ηaeo ) dηaeo
2 0
1 π
Z
− cos( ηaeo ) sin( ηaeo ) dηaeo
2 π2
π π
1 sin2 ( ηaeo ) 2 1 sin2 ( ηaeo ) 1 1 1
= × − × = + = .
2 2 2 2 π 4 4 2
0 2
243
The question now is: How do the actual values A and B of
the functions A (a; eo , λ) and B(b; eo , λ) come about within the
3-sphere when they are observed simultaneously by Alice and Bob?
To answer this question, recall that 3-sphere remains closed under
multiplication, with its points represented by quaternions of the form
(9.6), and A and B are limiting values of such quaternions. There-
fore the values A and B observed by Alice and Bob are constrained
by the value A B(a, b; eo ) of the product A (a; eo , λ)B(b; eo , λ),
which is a limiting value of the product quaternion:
S 3 ∋ ± 1 = A (a; eo , λ)B(b; eo , λ)
= lim [{ + a · eo + I · (a × eo ) } { − b · eo − I · (b × eo )}] ,
eo → ±a
eo → ±b
(A.9.15)
{ + a · eo + I · (a × eo ) } { − b · eo − I · (b × eo )}
= − (a · eo )(b · eo ) + (a × eo ) · (b × eo )
− I · { (a · eo )(b × eo ) + (b · eo )(a × eo ) − (a × eo ) × (b × eo ) }
−→ A B(a, b; eo ) = ± 1 ∈ S 3 . (A.9.16)
244
Figure 9.4: A simulation of outcome probabilities for simultaneously
occurring measurement events A = ±1 and B = ±1 within a paral-
lelized 3-sphere. The probabilistic predictions of the manifestly local
model described in the text match exactly with the corresponding
predictions of quantum mechanics [6]. The x-axis in the chart spec-
ifies the values of the relative angle ηab , and the y-axis records the
rate of simultaneous occurrences of events A = ±1 and B = ±1 as
a function of ηab . Thus, for example, the blue curve depicts the
ratio of the number of simultaneous occurrences of events A = +1
and B = +1 (or A = −1 and B = −1) over the total number of
occurrences and non-occurrences of such events. The straight line
at y = 0.5, on the other hand, depicts the number of occurrences of
events such as A = +1 at one station (with no detector present at
the other station) over the total number of occurrences and non-
occurrences of such events. The computer code for the simula-
tion is available at https://github.com/chenopodium/JCS. Further
discussion on the relevant issues can be found also on my blog at
http://libertesphilosophica.info/blog/. I am grateful to Chantal Roth
for kindly writing the code and for insightful discussions. [It is worth
noting that two other investigators have independently reproduced
the above simulation, writing codes in languages other than Java
used by Chantal Roth. Austin Smith used Excel Visual Basic to
reproduce the simulation, whereas John Reed used Mathematica.
Moreover, using Python Michel Fodje has built a different simula-
tion, which is available at https://github.com/minkwe/epr-simple/.]
245
the form (9.6):
ψ ψ
q(ψ, r) = cos + (I · r) sin
2 2
⇐⇒ C(a, b; eo ) + I · ck (eo ) S(a, b; eo ) ,
with C 2 + S 2 = 1 . (A.9.17)
or
−1 ≤ C(a, b; eo ) ≤ +1 . (A.9.20)
246
Figure 9.5: A simulation of the correlation between simultaneously
occurring measurement events A = ±1 and B = ±1 within the par-
allelized 3-sphere shown in Fig. 9.3. As we noted in the caption of
Fig. 9.4, the probabilistic predictions of the manifestly local model
described in the text match exactly with the corresponding predic-
tions of quantum mechanics [3][6][8]. The correlation generated in
this simulation is essentially an “addition” of the coincident probabil-
ities given in Eqs. (A.9.37) to (A.9.40), as computed in Eq. (A.9.41).
247
interval [−1, +1], what are the chances—as functions of the angle
ηab between a and b—for the occurrences of the events A B = +1
and A B = −1? The answer to this question can be obtained by
computing the following set of conditional probabilities:
and
where the random variable C(a, b; eo )—which (as we saw above) can
be thought of as a loaded die—is now given by
In the form of Eq. (A.9.17), this is the scalar part of the product of
the following two manifestly local quaternions:
and
where q
Na = cos2 (ηaeo + φpo ) + sin2 (ηaeo + φqo )
248
t
A = ±1 B = ±1
S3
a b
λeo
and q
Nb = cos2 (ηbeo + φro ) + sin2 (ηbeo + φso )
are normalizing factors. Needless to say, C(a, b; eo , φpo , φqo , φro , φso )
specified in Eq. (A.9.27) is the same as that specified in Eqs. (A.9.18)
and (A.9.19) apart from the phase shifts φpo , φqo , φro , and φso . These
phase shifts contribute to the rotations of the product quaternion
about the random vector ck (eo ) [which is different in general from
both ca (λeo ) and cb (λeo ) ]. They are simply numerical constants2 ,
independent of the parameter vectors a and b, or of the random
vector eo . They are thus parts of the geometry of the 3-sphere. To-
gether with eo , they form what Bell referred to as the “past causes.”
In terms of the product of the quaternions (A.9.28) and (A.9.29),
we are now in a position to express the results A (a; eo , λ) and
B(b; eo , λ), as well as their product A B(a, b; eo ), in the following
manifestly local-realistic forms:
S 3 ∋ ± 1 = A (a; eo , λ)
= lim { C(a; eo , λ, φpo , φqo ) + I · ca (λeo ) S(a; eo , λ, φpo , φqo )},
Ca → ±1
(A.9.30)
3
S ∋ ± 1 = B(b; eo , λ)
= lim { C(b; eo , λ, φro , φso ) + I · cb (λeo ) S(b; eo , λ, φro , φso )},
Cb → ±1
(A.9.31)
2 In physical terms, the constant phase shifts ensure that Alice and Bob do not
end up detecting the same particle of either spin in a given run of experiments.
249
and
S 3 ∋ ± 1 = A B(a, b; eo )
= lim { C(a, b; eo , φpo , φqo , φro , φso )
Cab → ±1
Here the vector ck (eo ) depends on both ca (λeo ) and cb (λeo ), as well
as on the other past causes. Although we do not require its explicit
expression, it can be easily worked out by evaluating the geometric
product of the quaternions q(a; eo , λ, φpo , φqo ) and q(b; eo , λ, φro , φso ).
The 3-sphere analogue of Bell’s locality condition then takes the form
{ Cab + (I · ck ) Sab } = { Ca + (I · ca ) Sa } { Cb + (I · cb ) Sb }
( with all C 2 + S 2 = 1 ),
i.e., S 3 ∋ qab = qa qb for qa and qb ∈ S 3 , (A.9.33)
and
C(b; eo , λ, φro , φso ) = { − cos(ηbλeo + φro )}/Nb ,
respectively, whereas the scalar part C(a, b; eo , φpo , φqo , φro , φso ) of
A B(a, b; eo ) is the one stated in equation (A.9.27).
As depicted in Fig. 9.3, (A.9.30), (A.9.31), and (A.9.32) are the
explicit expressions of the three points of the 3-sphere we have been
looking for. Using these expressions we can now compute the prob-
abilities for the occurrences of simultaneous events at the two ends of
the EPR experiment: P {A = +1, B = +1}, P {A = −1, B = −1},
250
P {A = −1, B = +1}, and P {A = +1, B = −1}. From the local-
ity conditions (A.9.33) and (A.9.34) it is easy to see, however, that in
the measurement limits these probabilities are causally constrained
by the respective values of C(a, b; eo , φpo , φqo , φro , φso ), as indicated in
Eqs. (A.9.23) to (A.9.26). Thus, for example, the probability of the
simultaneous occurrence of the results A = −1 and B = +1 is given
by the probability of the die C(a, b; eo , φpo , φqo , φro , φso ) landing on
its face marked −1. The results of numerical computations of such
probabilities are illustrated in Fig. 9.4. They turn out to be
1
P1+ (a) = P { Ca = +1 | no detector at b } = , (A.9.35)
2
1
P2− (b) = P { Cb = −1 | no detector at a } = , (A.9.36)
2
1 η
++ ab
P12 = P { Cab = +1 | ηab } = sin2 , (A.9.37)
2 2
1 ηab
−−
P12 = P { Cab = +1 | ηab } = sin2 , (A.9.38)
2 2
1 ηab
−+
P12 = P { Cab = −1 | ηab } = cos2 , (A.9.39)
2 2
1 ηab
+−
and P12 = P { Cab = −1 | ηab } = cos2 . (A.9.40)
2 2
As described in Eq. (A.9.5), the correlation predicted by our local
model can now be readily calculated as follows:
" n
#
1X i i
E(a, b) = lim A (a, λ ) B(b, λ )
n≫1 n
i=1
++ −− −+ +−
P12 + P12 − P12 − P12
= ++ −− −+ +−
P12 + P12 + P12 + P12
1 ηab 1 ηab 1 η 1 η
ab ab
= sin2 + sin2 − cos2 − cos2
2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2
ηab ηab
= sin2 − cos2
2 2
= − cos ηab . (A.9.41)
251
their scalar limits A (a; b; eo , λ), are intrinsically factorizable, as
shown in Eqs. (A.9.33) and (A.9.34). The values of the functions
A (a; eo , λ) and B(b; eo , λ) are thus determined by a common cause;
namely, the geometry and topology of the 3-sphere—and the local
vectors a and b. In practical terms, this common cause is translated
into the set {λeo , φpo , φqo , φro , φso }. The actual measurement results
A and B observed by Alice and Bob are thus only dependent on
these common causes and the local vectors.
For completeness, let me also note that the above correlation
gives rise to the following string of expectation values:
It is well known that the RHS of the above equation violates the
celebrated Bell-CHSH inequality for certain choices of angles [10].
252
by the rotationally non-invariant quantum states such as the GHZ
states and the Hardy state—and in fact those predicted by ALL
quantum states—can be reproduced exactly in a purely classical,
local-realistic manner [7][8][19]. Thus, contrary to the widespread
belief, the correlations exhibited by such states are not irreducible
quantum effects, but purely local-realistic, topological effects [3][6][8].
Needless to say, this vindicates Einstein’s suspicion that quantum
state merely describes statistical ensemble of physical systems, and
not the individual physical system. It is this inevitable conclusion
that Weatherall is resisting.
with respect to any fixed vector a. This suggests that the constraints
1
| cos( ηaeo )| ≥ sin2 ( θo ) ≤ | cos( ηbeo )| (A.9.46)
2
for arbitrary angles ηaeo ∈ [0, 2π) and ηbeo ∈ [0, 2π) should play a
crucial role in dictating the strength of the correlation between the
results A (a; eo , θo ) and B(b; eo , θo ) for a given angle θo ∈ [0, π/2].
According to this constraint the probability densities | cos( ηaeo )| and
| cos( ηbeo )| for observing the measurement results A (a; eo , θo ) and
B(b; eo , θo ) depend on the common angle θo , just as they depend on
the common vector eo [9]. This in turn suggests that we may treat
θo ∈ [0, π/2] as an additional random parameter, and take the set
1
Λ := (eo , θo ) | cos( ηxeo )| ≥ sin2 ( θo ) ∀ x ∈ IR3 (A.9.47)
2
253
Figure 9.7: Another explicit simulation of the correlation between
simultaneously occurring measurement events A = ±1 and B = ±1
within a parallelized 3-sphere. The code for this simulation is written
by Michel Fodje, in Python. Along with other relevant information,
it can be downloaded from https://github.com/minkwe/epr-simple/.
254
for any freely chosen vectors a and b, where eo is a random vector
on S 2 as defined before, and θo is a random angle, chosen from the
interval [0, π/2]. The correlation is then calculated quite simply as
" n
#
1X
E(a, b) = lim A (a; eio , θoi ) B(b; eio , θoi ) = − a · b .
n≫1 n
i=1
(A.9.50)
255
t
A = ±1 B = ±1
S3
a b
(eo , θo )
256
and divide the sum by the total number of non-vanishing products
(i.e., “coincidences”) they have added. The result is the correlation
" n
#
1X
E(a, b) = lim A (a; eio , θoi ) B(b; eio , θoi ) = −a · b.
n≫1 n i=1
(A.9.56)
4 The original simulation by Michel Fodje confirming the above results has been
translated by John Reed from Python to Mathematica. It can be found in PDF
format at this page: http://libertesphilosophica.info/Minkwe Sim J Reed.pdf.
257
t
A = ±1 B = ±1
S3
a b
(eo , θo , lo )
(A.9.63)
generating the strongest possible (albeit unphysical) correlation:
− 1 if 0 ≤ ηab < π/2 or 3π/2 < ηab ≤ 2π
E(a, b) =
+ 1 if π/2 < ηab < 3π/2 .
(A.9.64)
258
Special Case (3): “Quantum” Correlation—the 3-Sphere Model:
The above simulations once again confirm the fact that EPR-Bohm
correlations are local-realistic correlations among the binary points of
a parallelized 3-sphere [6]. As we saw in section 9.2, however, this fact
can be expressed more elegantly by understanding how random errors
propagate within a parallelized 3-sphere. In particular, we saw that
EPR-Bohm correlations can be derived by recognizing that the raw
scores A (a, λ) and B(b, λ) are generated within S 3 with different
bivectorial scales of dispersion, and hence the correct correlation
between them can be determined only by calculating the covariation
of the corresponding standardized variables L(a, λ) and L(b, λ):
" n
#
1X i i
E(a, b) = lim A (a, λ ) B(b, λ )
n≫1 n
i=1
" n
#
1X i i
= lim L(a, λ )L(b, λ )
n≫1 n
i=1
= −a · b, (A.9.67)
where
L(a, λi ) L(b, λi ) ≡ − a · b − L(a × b, λi )
≡ − a · b − λi D(a × b), (A.9.68)
and the standardized variables are defined as
q(ψ, a, λ) − m(q) A (a, λ) − m(A )
L(a, λ) := = . (A.9.69)
σ[ q(ψ, a, λ)] σ[ A (a, λ)]
259
Note that this definition holds for any point q(ψ, a, λ) of S 3 , and
not just for the limiting point q(ψ, a, λ) = A (a, λ) = ±1 obtained
in equation (9.21). The EPR-Bohm correlations − a · b are thus
correlations between any two points q(ψ, a, λ) and q(ψ, b, λ) of
S 3 , with the scalar points A (a, λ) = ±1 and B(b, λ) = ±1 being
only a special case.
It is also noteworthy that the correlation between the raw scores
A (a, λ) and B(b, λ) is determined in Eq. (A.9.67) by calculating
their covariance divided by the product of their standard deviations
σ[ A (a, λ) ] and σ[ B(b, λ) ]:
This product, however, is precisely the rotor that quantifies the twist
in the Hopf fibration of the 3-sphere [3][6]. As discussed in detail in
Chapter 8, its value varies from +1 for b = a to −1 for b = − a and
back, producing the correct combination of observed probabilities.
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to Lucien Hardy for several months of correspondence
which led to improvements in section 9.2.4. I am also grateful to
Martin Castell for his hospitality in the Materials Department of
the University of Oxford. This work was funded by a grant from
the Foundational Questions Institute (FQXi) Fund, a donor advised
fund of the Silicon Valley Community Foundation on the basis of
proposal FQXi-MGA-1215 to the Foundational Questions Institute.
260
References
[1] J. O. Weatherall, The Scope and Generality of Bell’s Theorem,
arXiv:1212.4854 (this preprint is now published).
[2] J. Christian, Disproof of Bell’s Theorem, arXiv:1103.1879. See
also http://libertesphilosophica.info/blog/.
[3] J. Christian, Disproof of Bell’s Theorem: Illuminating the Illu-
sion of Entanglement (BrownWalker Press, Florida, 2012).
[4] J. Christian, Refutation of Some Arguments Against my Disproof
of Bell’s Theorem, arXiv:1110.5876.
[5] J. Christian, Refutation of Richard Gill’s Argument Against my
Disproof of Bell’s Theorem, arXiv:1203.2529.
[6] J. Christian, Macroscopic Observability of Spinorial Sign
Changes under 2π Rotations, arXiv:1211.0784.
[7] J. Christian, What Really Sets the Upper Bound on Quantum
Correlations?, arXiv:1101.1958.
[8] J. Christian, On the Origins of Quantum Correlations,
arxiv:1201.0775. See also http://libertesphilosophica.info/blog/.
[9] J. S. Bell, Physics 1, 195 (1964); see also Rev. Mod. Phys. 38,
447 (1966), and Dialectica 39, 86 (1985).
[10] J. F. Clauser, M. A. Horne, A. Shimony, and R. A. Holt, Phys.
Rev. Lett. 23, 880 (1969).
[11] A. Einstein, B. Podolsky, and N. Rosen, Phys. Rev. 47, 777
(1935).
[12] C. Doran and A. Lasenby, Geometric Algebra for Physicists
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2003).
[13] D. Hestenes, Am. J. Phys. 71, 104 (2003). For more general
discussion see also http://libertesphilosophica.info/blog/.
[14] J. W. Milnor, Topology from the Differentiable Viewpoint
(Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1965).
[15] J. L. Rodgers and W. A. Nicewander, The American Statistician
42, 59 (1988).
[16] T. Frankel, The Geometry of Physics: An Introduction (Cam-
bridge University Press, 1997), p 501.
[17] B. S. Cirel’son, Lett. Math. Phys. 4, 93 (1980); L. J. Landau,
Phys. Lett. A 120, 54 (1987).
[18] A. Aspect et al., Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 91 (1982); G. Weihs et
al., Phys. Rev. Lett. 81, 5039 (1998).
[19] J. Christian, Disproofs of Bell, GHZ, and Hardy Type Theorems
and the Illusion of Entanglement, arXiv:0904.4259.
[20] J. F. Clauser and A. Shimony, Rep. Prog. Phys. 41, 1881 (1978).
261
Disproof of Bell’s Theorem:
Illuminating the Illusion of Entanglement
BrownWalker Press
Boca Raton, Florida
USA · 2014
www.brownwalker.com