Behavioral Portfolio Theory
Behavioral Portfolio Theory
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=uwash.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
University of Washington School of Business Administration is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve
and extend access to The Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis.
http://www.jstor.org
JOURNAL
OF FINANCIAL
ANDQUANTITATIVE
ANALYSIS VOL35, NO. 2, JUNE2000
COPYRIGHT
2000,SCHOOL
OFBUSINESS UNIVERSITY
ADMINISTRATION, OFWASHINGTON,
SEATTLE, WA98195
Abstract
We develop a positive behavioral portfolio theory (BPT) and explore its implications for
portfolio construction and security design. The optimal portfolios of BPT investors re-
semble combinations of bonds and lottery tickets, consistent with Friedman and Savage's
(1948) observation. We compare the BPT efficient frontier with the mean-variance effi-
cient frontier and show that, in general, the two frontiers do not coincide. Optimal BPT
portfolios are also different from optimal CAPM portfolios. In particular, the CAPM two-
fund separation does not hold in BPT. We present BPT in a single mental account version
(BPT-SA) and a multiple mental account version (BPT-MA). BPT-SA investors integrate
their portfolios into a single mental account, while BPT-MA investors segregate their port?
folios into several mental accounts. BPT-MA portfolios resemble layered pyramids, where
layers are associated with aspirations. We explore a two-layer portfolio where the low as-
piration layer is designed to avoid poverty while the high aspiration layer is designed for a
shot at riches.
I. Introduction
frontiers do not coincide; portfolios on the BPT efficient frontier are generally not
on the mean-variance efficient frontier. Mean-variance investors choose portfolios
by considering mean and variance. In contrast, BPT investors choose portfolios by
considering expected wealth, desire for security and potential, aspiration levels,
and probabilities of achieving aspiration levels.
The optimal portfolios of BPT investors are different from those of CAPM
investors as well. The optimal portfolios of CAPM investors combine the market
portfolio and the risk-free security. In contrast, the optimal portfolios of BPT
investors resemble combinations of bonds and lottery tickets.
We present BPT in two versions: a single mental account BPT version (BPT-
SA) and a multiple mental account version (BPT-MA). BPT-SA investors, like
mean-variance investors, integrate their portfolios into a single mental account;
they do so by considering covariance. In contrast, BPT-MA investors segregate
their portfolios into mental accounts and overlook covariance among mental ac?
counts. Note that BPT-MA differs from both Markowitz's mean-variance theory
(1952a) and Markowitz's customary wealth theory (1952b). For example, BPT-
MA investors might place foreign stocks in one mental account and domestic
stocks in another. They might consider foreign stocks highly risky because they
overlook the effect that the covariance between foreign and domestic stocks exerts
on the risk of the portfolio, viewed as an integrated single account.
The Friedman-Savage puzzle is a thorn in the side of conventional expected
utility theory, which is based upon concave utility functions defined over final
asset position. Von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944) developed expected utility
theory on the foundation of Bernoulli's utility theory, a theory consistent with
uniform attitude toward risk; the Bernoulli utility function is concave throughout
(see Figure 1, A). However, the Friedman-Savage puzzle is inconsistent with a
uniform attitude toward risk.
Friedman and Savage offer a solution to the insurance lottery puzzle based
on a utility function that features both concave and convex portions. The concave
portions are consistent with the purchase of insurance policies and the convex por?
tion is consistent with the purchase of lottery tickets (see Figure 1, B). Markowitz
(1952b) points out that only a few Friedman-Savage investors will buy both in?
surance policies and lottery tickets. Specifically, buyers of both insurance and
lotteries are those whose wealth levels fail in a narrow region defined by the loca?
tion of the inflection points in their utility functions. Moreover, Markowitz points
out that the Friedman-Savage utility function implies that poor people never pur?
chase lottery tickets, and middle income people never insure themselves against
modest losses. To address these points, Markowitz (1952b) modified Friedman
and Savage's function by locating one of the inflection points of the utility func?
tion at customary wealth (see Figure 1, C). Customary wealth is status quo wealth,
usually current wealth.
Economists, especially Quiggen (1982) and Yaari (1987), generalized ex?
pected utility theory to accommodate the Allais' paradoxes (Allais (1979)). Psy-
chologists, especially Kahneman and Tversky (1979), constructed prospect the?
ory on the foundation of Markowitz's customary wealth theory and Allais' work.
Lopes, in effect, built SP/A theory on the safety-first model and the work of
Quiggen and Yaari (Lopes (1987) and Lopes and Oden (1998)).
Shefrin and Statman 129
FIGURE1
Dollars Dollars
Customary
Wealth
X
Dollars
BPT. We show that BPT-SA efficient portfolios are fitter than some, but not all,
mean-variance efficient portfolios. In Section XI, we compare real life portfolios
to BPT portfolios, and in Section XII, we offer conclusions and directions for
future research.
for c > 0. In this case, expected utility takes the form E(W) -cProb{W < s}.
Indeed, Markowitz (1959) established that this is the only functional form consis-
lpThatis, the objective is to choose a portfolio featuringthe maximum wealth Wa defining the
lower 100a percentile.
Shefrin and Statman 131
tent with the principles of expected utility and Telser's version of the safety-first
problem.2
There is now a large literature demonstrating that people systematically vi-
olate the axioms of expected utility (Kahneman and Tversky (1979)). In the re-
mainder of the paper, we focus on choice theories where the axioms of expected
utility are violated.
In Lopes' framework, fear underlies the concern for security, and hope un-
derlies the concern for potential. Formally, fear affects attitude toward a risky
outcome through a reweighting of the decumulative probabilities. Specifically,
Lopes computes E(W) using the decumulative function hs(D) = Dls+q where the
subscript s stands for security. For qs > 0, this function attaches disproportionate
weight to higher values of D. As a result, D stochastically dominates hs(D), since
it effectively shifts probability weight from the right of the distribution's support
to the left.
Hope operates like fear, but it induces higher weighting of lower values of
D, the ones that attach to higher outcomes. Lopes' counterpart to hs(D) is hp(D),
where the/? stands for potential: hp(D) has the form 1 ? (1 ? D)l+qp.
Lopes argues that the emotions of fear and hope reside within all individuals,
and that each emotion serves to modify the decumulative weighting function. She
suggests that the final shape of the decumulative transformation function is a con?
vex combination of hs and hp, reflecting the relative strength of each. Specifically,
the transformation function h(D) has the form,
= -
(2) h(D) 5hs(D) + (1 5)hp(D).
In SP/A theory, the investor substitutes E(W) with Eh(W), replacing the
-
probability /?/ attached to the ith event with the difference rt = h{Di+\) /*(?>/).
SP/A departs from the expected utility framework by using a rank dependent for?
mulation, replacing D with h(D). Note that the rank ordering of states is typically
the inverse of the rank associated with the price per unit probability ratio, v///?/,
this being the pricing kernel. Note also that consistency requires that the ranking
of states by v//r/ be the same as the original ranking by v///?/.
Lopes postulates that risky outcomes are evaluated in terms of two variables.
The first variable is Eh(W), the expected value of W under the transformed de?
cumulative function h(D). The second variable is D(A), the probability that the
payoff will be A or higher. Note that these two variables are virtual analogues of
the arguments used in the safety-first model, E(W) and ProbjVK < s}. In fact, the
criterion function used to evaluate alternative risky outcomes is a monotone in?
creasing function U(Eh(W),D(A)). Note also that this conforms to the structure
suggested by Arzac-Bawa (1977), wherein individuals do not maximize E(W)
subject to a probability constraint, but instead maximize a function V(E(W),a).
Formally, the mechanics underlying the optimization in SP/A theory can be
viewed as an adaptation of the Arzac-Bawa (1977) characterization of safety-
first theory, where the major difference is in the interpretation of the variables.
Specifically, the subsistence level s is replaced by a more general aspiration level
A. The probability a is a cumulative probability, but can be east in decumulative
form 1 ? a. Finally, E(W) is replaced by Eh(W). In the special case where
qs = qp = 0, Lopes' model collapses to Arzac-Bawa's model.
Note that Eh(W) will be lower than E(W) for individuals who are strongly
driven by fear. The greater the fear, the lower the value ofEh(W). Similarly, hope
operates by increasing Eh(W) relative to E(W).
Shefrin and Statman 133
has the following form. There is a subset T of states, including the nth state sn
such that
Wi = A, for ieT\{sn},
where the summation in the previous equation is from one to n - 1, and ic is the
lowest integer for which iw>/c/?/ > a.
Proof. Note that Eh(W) is a sum of probability wealth products riW[. Consider
the unconstrained maximization of Eh(W). To maximize the sum of probability
wealth products, focus on the state that features the lowest price, per unit prob?
ability, for purchasing contingent wealth. By construction, this will be state n.
That is, vn/rn = min/{v//r/}. An unconstrained optimum for the Eh(W) maxi?
mization is the corner solution Wn = Wo/vn with W/ = 0 for all other i. In the
special case when/?n > a, the unconstrained maximum will also be a constrained
maximum. But this is not generally so. To modify the unconstrained maximum,
consider the least expensive way of satisfying the constraint. To this end, con?
sider all sets {T"} that include sn and have the property that ProbjT1"} > a, but
no proper subset T' of T" features ProbjT7} > a. To each such set, associate the
sum va(T") = AEi^T" v/. From the finite collection of sets T" so defined, choose
one, 7", that features a minimum value va{T"). Now modify the unconstrained
optimum by reallocating va(T) in value from claims that only pay in state sn to
claims that pay exactly A units of consumption for the states in T^j^}.
In the case of equiprobable states, p-x? p for all /, the minimum number of states
required to achieve the probability constraint is the first integer na larger than a/p.
Since the ratio v//r/ declines with i by construction, the cheapest reallocation from
the unconstrained optimum involves holding positive claims in the top na states,
and zero claims in the bottom n - na states. As before, claims to exactly A units
of wealth are held in the top na states, with the exception of state sn. ?
(5) Wi =
l/bll-HUvj-bWoyUvj/p^Vi/pi],
EPi{Wi-{b/2)W}),
3The equiprobableframeworkprovides the basis for moving from discrete states to continuous
states in the limit. Hence, we focus on the special case (4) ratherthanthe more general(3).
Shefrin and Statman 135
subject to the constraint Ev{Wi < Wo. To establish the theorem, use the La-
grangean technique to solve for the constrained maximum. This yields the first
order condition,
Wi = l/b[l-\Vi/Pi],
where A is the Lagrange multiplier. Solving for A from the budget constraint
EviWi < W0, yields
A = -
[Evj bW0]/Ev]/pj.
Wi =
l/b[l-{[Evj-bWo}/Evj/pj)vi/Pl],
which is a strictly concave function of Vj/pj, the probability normalized price. But
the optimal BPT-SA portfolio is strictly increasing in i and features exactly three
payoff levels, of which one is zero. ?
TABLE1
Prices of State Securities and Per Capita Endowments of State Securities (Market Portfolio)
(each state security pays $1 if the state occurs and zero otherwise)
FIGURE2
Payoffs for a BPT-SA Efficient Portfoliowith a (Low) $2 Aspiration Level
6i
4 5
State
BPT-SA efficient portfolio within the parameters of this example, one for which
A = 0.9, features strictly positive payoffs in all states. This portfolio return pattern
corresponds to the return pattern of a combination risk-free bond that pays either
A or zero, and a lottery ticket that pays Wn - A in state sn and zero otherwise.4
Figure 3 displays an efficient payoff when A = $12. In this case, there is
only one efficient portfolio, and it pays off in state 8 alone. When the aspiration
level A is sufficiently high, the only efficient portfolio resembles a lottery ticket.
4For those wishing to see an example illustratingTheorem3, considerthe following. Begin with
the parametersas they appearabove. That is, n = 8 with/?,-= 0.125 for all i. The state prices vt are,
respectively:0.37,0.19,0.12,0.09,0.07,0.06,0.05,0.04. Let qs = qP=0, A = 0.9, W0= 1, anda = 1.
The SP/A-efficient portfoliofeatures W/ = 0.9 for i < 8, and W8= 3.7. The expected returnto this
portfolio is 25.37%, and the returnvarianceis 87.56%. By setting the parameterb in Theorem2 equal
to 1.6155, we obtain a mean-varianceefficient portfolio with the same expected return,but a return
varianceequal to 9.41%. Hence, the specific SP/A portfoliois not on the mean-variancefrontier.
Shefrin and Statman 137
FIGURE3
Payoffs for a BPT-SA Portfolio with a (High) $12 Aspiration Level
30
25
20
15
10
State
Lopes (1987) illustrates the intuition underlying choice in the SP/A frame?
work through the choice of crops by farmers. She notes that subsistence farmers
often choose between two types of crops, food crops and cash crops. The prices
of food crops are low but generally stable. In contrast, the prices of cash crops
are volatile, but they offer the potential for higher wealth. Lopes notes that these
farmers tend to plant food crops to the point where their subsistence needs are
met. Farmers allocate the remainder of their land to cash crops. She suggests that
farmers gamble on cash crops because they aspire to escape poverty.
Note that there are two implicit aspiration levels in the agricultural analogue.
One is subsistence, and the other is some level above subsistence. In Lopes'
framework, the fear of falling below subsistence motivates the allocation to food
crops. This is the safety-first approach. The aspiration of escaping poverty moti?
vates the allocation ofthe remainder to cash crops.
The farmer's problem has as its analogue Friedman and Savage's observation
that people simultaneously purchase insurance and lottery tickets. As we have
argued, such simultaneity is the hallmark of efficient BPT-SA portfolios.
A mean-variance investor's preferences can be expressed by the function
? a2
p jd where d is the degree of risk tolerance. This is because attitude toward
risk in a mean-variance framework is measured by a single parameter, d. In SP/A
theory, risk is multidimensional, and is described with five parameters:
Roy (1952) used Tchebyshev's inequality to extend his analysis from the
case where portfolio returns are normally distributed. Elton and Gruber ((1995),
p. 240) indicate that, as long as the probability distribution of returns is "suf-
ficiently well behaved that the Tchebyshev inequality holds," Roy's argument
implies that optimal safety-first portfolios lie along the mean-variance efficient
frontier.
Tchebyshev's inequality is a general result, holding for all distributions with
a finite second moment. Of course, there is no mean-variance frontier for dis?
tributions lacking a second moment. Theorem 3 makes the case that an optimal
safety-first portfolio typically lies off the mean-variance frontier. If the argument
in Elton-Gruber (1991) were correct, Theorem 3 would be false.
Theorem 3 is true, which leads to the next question: where is the flaw in the
Elton-Gruber argument? In this paper's notation, Tchebyshev's inequality implies
that Prob{(W - pP)/crP < -K} < \/K2. Elton-Gruber suggest that a safety-
first optimum can be identified by setting K = (pp ? s)/ap, and then choosing a
portfolio P that maximizes K. There are several difficulties with this argument.
First, the l/K2 bound in Tchebyshev's inequality is a two-sided bound, and the
safety-first probability constraint Prob{W < s} is one-sided. Second, l/K2 is an
inequality bound. It need not hold with equality, and certainly cannot hold with
equality when K < 1.
Moreover, it may even be undesirable that the bound hold with equality.
There are cases where it is possible to find a portfolio such that Prob{ W < s} = 0,
yet maximizing K leads to inefficiency because it reduces expected wealth. This
can be seen in the numerical example presented earlier, for A ? s ? 0.9. In this
case, fiP ? 1.25, aP = 0.94, and Prob{ W < s} ? 0. For the efficient portfolio, the
corresponding value of K is 0.377, and the upper bound, l/K2, on Prob{W < s}
is seven, not only well above zero, but well above unity. Consider what happens
when we alter the portfolio by changing the state 1 payoff to 1.0614, and the state
8 payoff to 2.03. We note that this change leaves the value of Prob{W < s} at
zero, and causes the standard deviation to fall to 0.37. More importantly, the mean
payoff also declines to 1.0614, yet the value of K increases to 0.4364. Hence,
increasing K, the variable that Elton-Gruber suggest be maximized, has made the
investor worse, not better, off.
lottery ticket. If we restrict all portfolio return distributions to be normal, this pre-
ferred return pattern is unavailable. Yet, there is still something interesting to say
about the difference between the mean-variance frontier and the BPT-SA frontier.
Consider a world with two securities, X and Y, both of which feature nor?
mally distributed returns. X has an expected return of 16% with a standard devia?
tion of 20%, while Y has an expected return of 10% with a standard deviation of
15%. The correlation between the returns of X and Y is zero.
Imagine an investor with $1 of current wealth who chooses $1 as A, his
aspiration level. A portfolio consisting entirely of Y offers an expected wealth of
$1.10 along with a 25.2% probability of missing the aspiration level. Portfolio
Y is not on the BPT-SA efficient frontier since it is dominated by portfolio Z.
Portfolio Z, combining $0.50 of X with $0.50 of Y, has a lower probability of
missing the aspiration level, 14.9%, along with higher expected wealth, $1.13.
Figure 4, A shows the BPT-SA efficient frontier extending from Z to X?call this
the frontier for the low aspiration investor.
Now consider an investor with a high aspiration level, such as the Dubins
and Savage (1976) investor, who is in a casino with $1,000 and desperately needs
$10,000 by morning; anything less is worth nothing?call this the high aspiration
investor.
Dubins and Savage concluded that the optimal portfolio for this high aspira?
tion investor is concentrated in a single bet, a bet that offers a chance for a $10,000
payoff. The optimality of a single bet portfolio for a high aspiration investor can
also be illustrated in our two-security example.
Imagine a high aspiration investor with $ 1 of current wealth who defines the
aspiration level A as $1.20, a high aspiration level relative to the expected 10%
return of security Y and the expected 16% return of security X. The efficient BPT-
SA frontier for this investor contains only one portfolio, consisting of a single bet
on security X (Figure 4, B).
When returns are normally distributed and no short sales are allowed, some
optimal BPT-SA portfolios are on the mean-variance frontier. For example, mean-
variance investors with little aversion to variance, like investors with high aspira?
tion levels, choose X as their portfolio. However, not all portfolios on the BPT-SA
efficient frontier are identical to portfolios on the mean-variance efficient frontier.
The distinction is evident most when high aspiration investors and mean-variance
investors consider casino-type securities, securities with low expected returns and
high variance.
Consider securities L and M. Security L has an expected return of 2% and
a standard deviation of 90%, while security M has an expected return of 20%
and a standard deviation of 30%. Security L is a casino-type security since its
expected return is lower than M's while its variance is higher.5 A portfolio com-
posed entirely of L is not on the mean-variance efficient frontier; it is dominated
by other portfolios, including the one composed entirely of M. Given the pro-
hibition against short sales, a portfolio composed entirely of L is on the efficient
frontier for a high aspiration investor with an aspiration level of $1.30, since it pro?
vides the highest probability of reaching the aspiration level (see Figure 5). High
FIGURE4
4A. The BPT-SAEfficient Frontierfor an Investor with a (Low) $1 Aspiration Level (the frontier
extends from Z to X)
1.16
1.15
"8 1.13
1.12
1.11
1.1
1.09
0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8
Probfwealth< aspirationlevel}
4B. The BPT-SA Efficient Frontier for an Investor with a (High) $1.20 Aspiration Level (the
frontier consists only of X)
1.17
1.16
S 1-15
? 1.14
11.12
X
w 1.11
1.1
Y
1.09
0.2 0.4 0.6 0.1
< aspiration
Probjwealth level}
aspiration investors, like Dubms-Savage investors, are not risk seeking. They
choose the high risk L because it provides the highest probability of reaching the
aspiration level, not because they like risk.
The SP/A framework is similar to the value-at-risk (VaR) framework. In
both, optimization involves tradeoffs between expected wealth and probabilities
of falling short of an aspiration level. The usual aspiration level in VaR analyses
is a poverty level; the goal is to combine a low probability of falling below a
poverty level with the highest possible expected wealth. But we can think of
a VaR framework that corresponds to the high aspiration framework, where the
aspiration level pertains to riches, not poverty.
Shefrin and Statman 141
FIGURE5
The Mean-Variance Efficient Frontierand the BPT-SA Efficient Frontierfor an Investor with a
$1.30 Aspiration Level
5A. Mean-Variance Frontier
0.25 -
M
0.2
0.15
I 0.1
,x 0.05
1.25
M
1.2
1.15
1.1
1.05
L
Some investors have low aspirations and others have high aspirations, exclu-
sively. Most investors combine the two; they want to avoid poverty, but they also
want a shot at riches. Portfolios that combine low and high aspirations are often
depicted as layered pyramids where investors divide their current wealth between
a bottom layer, designed to avoid poverty, and a top layer, designed for a shot at
riches.
Mental accounting is the feature that underlies the difference between BPT-
SA, the single account version of BPT, and BPT-MA, the multiple account ver?
sion. BPT-SA investors act as if they consider covariances?they integrate their
142 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis
Us = P]^Eh{Ws)\
where Ps is the probability of falling short of the low aspiration level As ($0.20),
Ws is the terminal wealth of the low aspiration doer, and 7 is a non-negative
weighting parameter (0.1). Similarly, the utility of the high aspiration doer is
Ur = P\-$Eh{Wrf,
where P, is the probability of falling short of the high aspiration level Ap ($1.20),
Wr is the terminal wealth of the high aspiration doer, and /3 is 0.1.
The utility function of the planner combines the utilities of the low and high
aspiration doers, Us and Ur, where the weight attached to the high aspiration doer
is Kr ? 10,000, much higher than the weight attached to the low aspiration doer,
Ks = 1. We assume that the planner's utility takes the form,
(6) U =
[\+Kdr(P).-f3Eh(WrY)}KcL<[P]-<Eh{wy}.
The planner divides initial wealth W0 into two portions, WV)ofor the low as?
piration account and Wr>0for the high aspiration account. Note that the planner's
utility function (6) has a safety-first bent. The utility of the planner is zero when
the utility of the low aspiration doer is zero, but it is not necessarily zero when
the utility of the high aspiration doer is zero. This implies that the first dollar
of wealth Wo will be allocated to the low aspiration account. In other words,
achieving low aspiration, or safety comes first.
Consider a specific example. Imagine that the investor faces two securities D
and E. D has an expected return of 3% with a standard deviation of 1%, while E
has an expected return of 5% with a standard deviation of 10%. Figure 6 depicts
the utilities of each of the two doers under each feasible division of the $1 current
wealth. It also depicts the optimal portfolio of each doer. The optimal portfolio
for the planner is composed of an allocation of $0.20 for the low aspiration doer
and $0.80 for the high aspiration doer. The low aspiration doer places 93% of his
wealth in the low expected return security D, while the high aspiration doer places
100% of his wealth in the high expected return security E. The probability that
the low aspiration doer will miss his aspiration level is 5.8%, while the probability
that the high aspiration doer will miss his aspiration level is lottery-like, greater
than 99.9%.
We have excluded short sales from our analysis so far, but if short sales are
allowed, the high aspiration doer would take a short position in D to increase
his holdings of E. As a result, the planner would end up with a short position
in D in his high aspiration account, but a long position in D in his low aspiration
account. This stems from the lack of integration between the two mental accounts;
covariances are overlooked.
In summary, BPT-MA investors match mental accounts with goals. The two
mental accounts are not integrated. As a result, BPT-MA investors may take off-
setting positions, borrowing for leverage in their high aspiration accounts, while
they lend in their low aspiration accounts.
144 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis
FIGURE6
The Choice Set of BPT-MAPortfolios Available to a Planner with Two Doers and the Optimal
Portfolio of a Planner
ptimal
portfolio
Theorem 1 implies that both the low aspiration doer and the high aspiration
doer will choose portfolios formed by combining (possibly risky) bonds and a lot?
tery ticket. But the mental accounting maximum solution will push the accounts
in the layers to the extremes. That is, the low aspiration account will look more
like risk-free bond than the high aspiration account, which, in turn, looks more
like a lottery ticket.
To see why, consider the nature of the Engel curve that describes the impact
of a marginal dollar of wealth on the investor's demand for contingent claims.
For the sake of exposition, focus on the equiprobable case. Consider how the low
aspiration doer allocates successive increments of his allocation Ws$. According
to the argument used to establish Theorem 1, the low aspiration doer allocates the
first dollar to claims in state sn. Indeed, the low aspiration doer's initial allocation
WSlo would have to be at least As(vn + v?_i) before it would be worthwhile for
him to choose positive claims in two states. Choosing positive claims in two
states would lower Eh(Ws) without raising Ps. For W^o < Asvn, Us = 0 because
Ps = 0. For Asvn < WSyo < As(vn + vn_i), Us is a concave function, USyn=
pl~1E}l(Ws)1, featuring diminishing marginal utility. A low aspiration doer with
a higher allocation WSy0will find it worthwhile to hold positive claims that pay off
in states sn-\ and sn. In this case, utility is ?/Vjrt_i= (2p)l~1Eh(Ws)1. Continuing
this way, recursively define USin-j equal to ((/ + l)p)1_7Zs/j(Wv)7.
Because the low aspiration doer selects his optimal allocation by making a
choice about the number of states in which to hold positive claims, the optimal
value of Us will be equal to max{[/Vi?_7j, forj = 0 to n ? 1. This implies that
Shefrin and Statman 145
the indirect utility function ?/v(WV)o) associated with optimal allocations will be
not be concave everywhere. At crossover points where positive claims to new
states are brought in, marginal utility increases. This is because the reallocation
of wealth from state sn to a lower state both raises Ps and lowers Eh(Ws).
If state prices are low at the upper end of the state range and the aspiration
point As is low, then increasing WV)oleads to "rapid" crossovers, since increasing
the probability of reaching As by shifting the allocation from state sn to a lower
state comes at a low cost in terms of foregone ?/,(Wv). This means that the low
aspiration doer responds to increased allocation by shifting into less risky bonds.
However, further increases in WVjolead the low aspiration doer to consider states
with higher state prices. As this happens, the cost of increasing Ps in terms of
foregone Eh{Ws) mounts. Now larger absolute increments in WVjothan before are
necessary to induce crossovers.
The Engel structure of the high aspiration subproblem is the same as above,
except that Ar > As. Qualitatively, the higher aspiration point leads to a lower
sensitivity of the crossover points with respect to Wr>othan with respect to WV)o-
The difference between Engel curves shows up in the character of the portfo?
lios selected for the two layers. The low aspiration doer will tend to use additional
allocations WVjoto form a less risky bond, thereby moving the lottery component
to zero. On the other hand, the high aspiration doer will tend to use additional
allocations Wr>ofor the lottery component, focusing on the maximization of the
expected payoff Eh(Wr). Moderate levels of wealth will lead to the Friedman-
Savage insurance/lottery property when the aspiration level for the low aspiration
doer is low, and the aspiration level for the high aspiration doer is high. Such
investors choose riskless bonds in the low aspiration layer of their portfolios and
a lottery ticket for their high aspiration layer.
Just as the risk tolerance parameter d affects the choice of mean-variance
investors among portfolios on the mean-variance frontier, the BPT parameters de-
termine the portfolios of BPT investors. Recall from Section V that in BPT-SA,
risk tolerance is captured by a combination of parameters. Tolerance for risk in
BPT, both the single account and multiple account versions, is determined by the
degree of fear (which is increasing in qs), the degree of hope (which is increasing
in qp), and the strength of fear relative to hope (which is increasing in S). In?
creased fear accentuates the tendency of BPT investors to make the bond portion
of their low aspiration mental accounts risk free. Increased hope accentuates the
tendency of BPT investors to increase the maximum possible payoffs in their high
aspiration mental accounts.
Lopes discusses a special case of her model she calls "cautious optimism."
Here, fear is the predominant emotion throughout most of the domain, except
for the upper end of the range. A cautiously optimistic individual overweights
the probabilities attached to both the worst and best outcomes. That is, cautious
optimism gives rise to a weighting scheme with thicker tails than the underlying
distribution. A cautious optimist is inclined to extremes in the two layers of his
portfolio, a risk-free bond for his low aspiration account and a high expected
payoff for his high aspiration account.
146 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis
Will the planner's portfolio, obtained by combining the low and high aspira?
tion subportfolios, be mean-variance efficient? The following theorem provides
the answer.
Theorem 4. If there are at least five states that feature positive consumption in
a BPT-MA portfolio Pm, and distinct values for v///?/, then Pm is neither mean-
variance efficient nor BPT-SA efficient.
Proof. The proof is similar to the argument establishing Theorem 3. There can
be at most four distinct positive consumption values in an SP/A portfolio: AS9
Ari As + Ar, and an additional value for Wn in excess of Ar. Now any mono-
tone increasing mean-variance portfolio with positive consumption in five or more
states will feature at least five distinct values of consumption. Therefore, Pm is
mean-variance inefficient. Similarly, Theorem 1 implies that Pm is BPT-SA inef-
ficient.6 ?
X. Evolutionary Implications
As noted earlier, BPT optimal portfolios are typically off the mean-variance
efficient frontier. Does this result have evolutionary implications? In particular,
do BPT investors lose wealth to mean-variance investors over the long term? Do
they vanish?
Blume and Easley (1992) develop a general framework for analyzing the
evolutionary questions about trading. Their model implies that BPT investors
can, but need not, lose wealth to mean-variance investors over the long run. To be
sure, mean-variance portfolios are not the most "fit" from the perspective of long-
term survival. This distinction belongs to log-utility portfolios, and a log-utility
portfolio does not typically lie on the mean-variance frontier.
Consider a multiperiod model in which, at each date, state i occurs with
probability /?,-. A portfolio that is unfit loses wealth in the long run. Blume-
Easley establish that the fitness of a portfolio with payoff return (W\,..., Wn)
is determined by its budget share profile (v\W\/Wo,..., vnWn/Wo). The fittest
portfolio is one whose budget share profile coincides with the probability vector
P=(Pi)-
Consider the budget share per unit probability (v/Wi/p/Wb). Blume-Easley
show that portfolios can be ranked by fitness using the non-negative entropy func?
tion,
EpilnfaWo/viWi).
Given two portfolios, the fitter portfolio is the one with the lower entropy. Note
that minimum entropy is achieved when budget share per unit probability equals
unity across all states.
6Note that a BPT-MA portfolio is not BPT-SA inefficientjust because the former has two as?
pirationlevels while the former has one. It is straightforwardto define a version of BPT-SA with
two aspirationlevels. The majorsource of the inefficiency is the lack of integrationbetween the two
accounts. In an efficient BPT-SA portfolio, the associatedpayoff values are as follows: zero, the as?
pirationlevels, and possibly an additionalamountassociatedwith the sn. This is not what a BPT-MA
investorchooses.
Shefrin and Statman 147
Consider the budget share of the BPT-SA efficient portfolio (4) and mean-
variance efficient portfolio (5). The budget share per unit probability for the BPT-
SA portfolio is
Note that the probability to budget share ratio is infinite for the lowest states, and
that it is an increasing function for ic < i < n. Clearly, this ratio will not be the
unity function,
The budget share per unit probability for a mean-variance efficient portfolio
has the form,
- - .
(8) {(vi/bpiWo) [l ([Evj bW0)/Ev2/pj) Vi/Pi]}~1
Finally, consider what happens when the aspiration level A is tied to wealth,
and the wealth ratio A/ W remains constant. In this case, the budget shares of BPT-
SA investors do remain constant over time. Hence, the Blume-Easley entropy
function serves to rank order BPT-SA efficient portfolios and mean-variance effi?
cient portfolios by fitness. In general, BPT-SA portfolios are more fit than some
mean-variance efficient portfolios, but less fit than others.
securities that combine a secure floor, usually equal to the amount of the initial
investment, with some potential linked to an index such as the S&P 500.
Treasury bills are right for investors with very low aspiration levels, while
equity participation notes are right for investors with higher aspiration levels. In?
vestors with even higher aspiration levels choose stocks and those with yet higher
aspiration levels choose out-of-the-money call options and lottery tickets. Stocks,
call options, and lottery tickets feature many states with zero pay offs, but they
also features states with payoffs that meet high, even exceedingly high, aspiration
levels.
Cash, bonds, and stocks are the most common elements of portfolios and
they are the elements of the portfolio puzzle discussed by Canner, Mankiw, and
Weil (CMW (1997)). CMW note that investment advisors recommend that in?
vestors increase the ratio of stocks to bonds if they want to increase the aggres-
siveness of their portfolios. This recommendation is puzzling within the CAPM
since it violates two-fund separation. Two-fund separation states that all CAPM
efficient portfolios share a common ratio of stocks to bonds and that attitudes
toward risk are reflected only in the proportion allocated to the risk-free asset.
The portfolio advice of mutual fund companies illustrates the CMW puzzle.
As Fisher and Statman (1997) note, mutual fund companies often recommend
that investors construct portfolios as pyramids of assets: cash in the bottom layer,
bonds in the middle layer, and stocks in the top layer. Investors increase the
aggressiveness of their portfolios by increasing the proportion allocated to stocks
without necessarily increasing the proportion allocated to bonds.
Pyramid portfolios that are puzzling within CAPM are consistent with BPT,
where two-fund separation fails. Consider a BPT-MA framework with three men?
tal accounts in the hands of three "doers" whose aspiration levels range from low
to medium and to high. BPT-MA investors do not follow two-fund separation.
Greater aggressiveness might manifest itself by an increased portfolio allocation
to the high aspiration doer and by a corresponding increase in the allocation to
stocks in the portfolio.
XII. Conclusion
We develop a positive behavioral portfolio theory (BPT) and explore its im?
plications for portfolio construction and security design. We present our model
in two versions, BPT-SA, where the portfolio is integrated into a single men?
tal account and BPT-MA, where the portfolio is segregated into multiple mental
accounts, such that covariances among mental accounts are overlooked. BPT in?
vestors, like the investors in the Friedman-Savage puzzle, are simultaneously risk
averse and risk seeking; they buy both bonds and lottery tickets.
Portfolios within BPT-MA resemble layered pyramids where each layer (i.e.,
mental account) is associated with a particular aspiration level. We explore a
simple two-layer model with a low aspiration layer designed to avoid poverty and
a high aspiration layer designed for a shot at riches. Since BPT-MA investors
overlook covariance between layers, they might combine a short position in a
security in one layer with a long position in the same security in another layer.
150 Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis
We explore the links between BPT portfolios and mean-variance, CAPM and VaR
portfolios.
Optimal securities for BPT investors resemble combinations of bonds and
lottery tickets. The bonds for the low aspiration mental account resemble risk-free
or investment grade bonds, while the bonds for the high aspiration mental account
resemble speculative (junk) bonds. We explore the similarities between optimal
BPT securities and real world securities such as bonds, stocks, and options.
We plan to extend BPT in several ways. One extension involves the design
of securities by corporations, especially in connection with capital structure and
dividend policy. Capital structure and dividend policy are usually approached
from the supply side; dividends are regarded as information signals and capital
structure is regarded as a solution to agency problems. We think that capital
structure and dividend policy also need to be approached from the demand side;
some corporate securities fit better than others into the layered pyramid structure
of BPT portfolios. Analysis of dividend policy requires a multi-period model.
A multi-period BPT model is also useful for analyzing risk and its relation?
ship to time diversification. Proponents of time diversification argue that the risk
of stocks declines as the time horizon increases, while opponents argue that it
does not (see Kritzman (1994)). A multi-period BPT model would link time to
perceptions of risk and show, for example, how investors revise portfolios when
their original aspirations are reached.
Lastly, the road from BPT will lead to an equilibrium asset pricing model,
extending Shefrin and Statman (1994), just as the road from mean-variance port?
folio theory led to the CAPM.
References
Allais, M. "The Foundationsof a Positive Theory of Choice Involving Risk and a Criticism of the
Postulates and Axioms of the AmericanSchool." In Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais
Paradox, M. Allais and O. Hagen, eds. Dordrecht,Netherlands: Reidel (1979) (original work
published 1952).
Allen, E, and D. Gale. "OptimalSecurity Design." Review of Financial Studies, 1 (Autumn 1988),
229-263.
Arzac, E. "Utility Analysis of Chance-ConstrainedPortfolio Selection." Journal of Financial and
QuantitativeAnalysis, 8 (1974), 993-1007.
Arzac, E., and V. Bawa. "PortfolioChoice and Equilibriumin CapitalMarketswith Safety-firstIn?
vestors."Journal of Financial Economics, 4 (1977), 277-288.
Blume, L., and D. Easley. "Evolutionand MarketBehavior."Journalof EconomicTheoiy, 58 (1992),
9-40.
Canner,N.; N. G. Mankiw;and D. Weil. "AnAsset Allocation Puzzle."AmericanEconomicReview,
87(1997), 181-191.
Dubins, L. E., and L. J. Savage. "Inequalitiesfor StochasticProcesses: How to Gambleif You Must."
2nd ed. New York,NY: Dover (1976).
Elton, E., and M. Gruber. Modern Portfolio Theoryand InvestmentAnalysis. New York,NY: John
Wiley&Sons, Inc. (1995).
Fisher,K., and M. Statman."InvestmentAdvice from MutualFundCompanies."Journalof Portfolio
Management,24 (Fail 1997), 9-25.
Friedman,M., and L. J. Savage. "TheUtility Analysis of Choices InvolvingRisk."Journalof Political
Economy,56 (1948), 279-304.
Green, R? and K. Rydqvist. "Ex-dayBehavior with Dividend Preferenceand Limitationsto Short-
term Arbitrage:the Case of Swedish LotteryBonds."Journalof Financial Economics,53 (1999),
145-187.
Kahneman,D., and A. Tversky, "ProspectTheory: An Analysis of Decision Making under Risk."
Econometrica,47 (1979), 263-291.
Shefrin and Statman 151