An Approach To A Science of Administration
An Approach To A Science of Administration
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to The American Political Science Review
1124
cise causal relations which can be verified or which can serve adequately
as bases for further reasoning
It may be regarded as unwise to venture a statement of what one con-
siders the basic premises upon which a science of administration may be
built. But every body of theory is built upon fundamental assumptions,
either expressed or implied. Moreover, a body of theory is complete, and
has scientific value, only when the premises are sufficiently clear to permit
objective scrutiny and verification. Erroneous hypotheses, stated pre-
cisely, may be more scientific than vague or unexpressed assumptions;
for only the former will lend themselves to verification. In other words,
trial and error is an essential part of scientific method.
What, then, are the first steps in an approach to a science of administra-
tion? Dr. Luther Gulick recently set forth what he considered the require-
ments of a scientific approach to the social studies at the present time.
These requirements were: "(1) analysis of phenomena from which we may
derive standard nomenclature, measurable elements, and rational con-
cepts; (2) the development of extensive scientific documentation based
upon these analyses, and (3) the encouragement of imaginative approach
to social phenomena, and the publication and circulation of hypotheses
so that they may be scrutinized by others in the light of experience, now
and in future years."4
A number of essentials are suggested by the foregoing statements, but
there is involved a clear recognition of two basic methods of approach
to scientific study. Statement number "2" calls for the empirical method,
by which we collect and describe appearances in order that general con-
clusions or laws may be derived therefrom. Statement "3" suggests the
rational or deductive method, whereby we seek to determine causal rela-
tionships among the appearances which we observe. This latter method
involves the adoption of definitions, axioms, and propositions, which are
derived from empirical observations, and which are capable of serving as
premises to reasoning. Conclusions reached by the rational method must
be consistent with the appearances gathered; but, being consistent, those
conclusions, and the premises from which they are derived, may serve
as bases for other conclusions beyond the immediate reaches of em-
pirical observation. The two methods are not independent and alternative
processes of scientific study; they are mutually dependent phases of in-
vestigation, and one cannot be separated from the other without impairin
7Gulick and Urwick (eds.), Papers on the Science of Administration, pp. 91-92.
8 Chester I. Barnard, Functions of the Executive (Harvard Univ. Press, 1938),
p. 73. The presence or absence of a joint purpose is the principal basis on which
Barnard distinguishes between formal and informal organization. Op. cit., Chap. 9.
Some authorities define organization as the arrangement of personnel for the
accomplishment of a purpose. Cf. Gaus, White, and Dimock, The Frontiers of Public
Administration (1936), pp. 66-67, and L. D. White, Introduction to the Study of
Administration (1939), p. 37. While the arrangement of personnel is essential, and
while that is the center of attention in organization charts and plans, the definition
is suggestive of preparation rather than of action. No organization actually exists
except in so far as there is concerted activity.
10 This is apparently what Mr. Gulick has in mind when he says that "in the
science of administration, whether public or private, the basic 'good' is efficiency."
Gulick and Urwick, op. cit., p. 192. The idea is basic in all discourses on public
administration-even among those who object to the emphasis placed upon "effi-
II
Having stated the basic axiom, one faces the necessity of explaining the
phenomena which serve to promote or to impair coordination. An exami-
nation of published materials in the field leaves one with the impression
that most students of administration agree with Mooney, who places "the
principle of leadership and command" next in importance to his principle
of coordination. Mooney illustrates the principle by pointing out that if
two men combine their efforts to lift and move a heavy stone, one must
give a signal, such as "heave ho," in order that the two men can lift in
unison.'5 But the illustration involves the start of a new operation rather
than the continuous functioning of an organization, and therefore it seems
that Mooney has overlooked another vital factor in administrative co-
ordination.
If, instead of the two men moving a stone, one observes an amateur
tennis or volley-ball team at play, or even a store or office force at work,
one may be impressed by the fact that either work or play is coordinated
for long periods of time without any evidence of leadership. While leader-
ship is essential and important, it does not operate continuously.
But coordination is continuous in any but the most casual organizations.
This continuity of cooperative interaction is possible only when each mem-
ber of an organization has learned his task and certain vital relationships
between his own activity and the activities of those about him. In other
words, a routine of interactions has been established; the relative positions
of workers, the individual tasks, and the sequence of operations are known
because of a series of past decisions and experiences. The parts of the
organization are coordinated much the same as the muscular movements
in one's body are coordinated when one walks. No continuous conscious
effort is necessary; the organization has acquired a habit of coordination.
Definition: Organization routine is that part of any organization's
activities which has become habitual because of repetition and which is
followed regularly without specific directions or detailed supervision by
any member of the organization.
ItI
attention of leaders, and the routine has been established when the organization
carries on without conscious attention of leaders. The "dead level of mediocrity and
routine" of which P. W. Melton speaks ("Administration in a Federal Government
Bureau," in this REvIEW, Vol. 33, pp. 835, 840) apparently arises because the
executive devotes his attention to matters that should be routine and habitual;
not because recurring functions have become routine.
17 L. Urwick apparently has somewhat the same idea in mind when he points
out that "in organization there is a tendency to compensation, comparable to the
tendency found in the human organism." Gulick and Urwick, op. cit., p. 84.
where changes are intended), and with other decisions affecting the same
set of interrelations. Coordination in action is a function of coordination
in decision.
As will be pointed out later, other factors have vital influence upon the
coordination of decisions, as well as upon the rate at which coordinated
performance follows as the result of coordinated decision. However, these
factors do not invalidate Axiom II or the following axiom:
18 The term "leadership" is used here in a limited and non-personal sense. Types
of leadership or personal characteristics of leaders are not considered in this article.
19 Gulick and Urwick, op. cit., p. 9. Marshall Dimock, Modern Politics and Ad-
ministration (1937), p. 270. For views approving the idea, see also L. D. White,
Introduction to the Study of Public Administration (1939), p. 51; A. E. Buck, The
Reorganization of State Governments in the United States (1938), pp. 17-19.
20 The reader should recall that while coordination promotes efficiency, it is
only one of the factors which determine the effectiveness of an organization. (Cf.
note 12, supra.) This axiom does not lead to the conclusion that several small and
independent organizations are more efficient than one large organization. If the
same task is to be performed, integration does not increase the number of persons
involved.
IV
Propositions II and III and Axioms II and III have been set forth as
possible principles of authority, or, in the highly descriptive terminology
used by Mooney, principles of "perpendicular coordination."24 But
Mooney points out that the "principle of horizontal coordination" is
equally important. He explains that this principle operates through the
"universal service of knowledge" rather than through authority and
command.
Basically, "horizontal coordination" is little more than another phase
of the "system of communication" already referred to. It takes on special
25 Cf. Chester I. Barnard, Functions of the Executive, Chap. 14, for further defini-
tion and illustrations of the "strategic factor."