0% found this document useful (0 votes)
132 views20 pages

Unit 1 Deductive and Inductive - L2

This document provides an overview of deductive and inductive arguments. It discusses: [1] Deductive arguments have conclusions that necessarily follow from the premises, while inductive arguments have conclusions that probably follow from the premises. [2] Validity refers to the logical structure of an argument, not the truth of its statements. An argument is valid if its conclusion must be true if its premises are true. [3] Examples are provided to illustrate deductive, inductive, valid, and invalid arguments. The document emphasizes understanding the logical form of arguments over their specific content.

Uploaded by

Muskan Lonial
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
132 views20 pages

Unit 1 Deductive and Inductive - L2

This document provides an overview of deductive and inductive arguments. It discusses: [1] Deductive arguments have conclusions that necessarily follow from the premises, while inductive arguments have conclusions that probably follow from the premises. [2] Validity refers to the logical structure of an argument, not the truth of its statements. An argument is valid if its conclusion must be true if its premises are true. [3] Examples are provided to illustrate deductive, inductive, valid, and invalid arguments. The document emphasizes understanding the logical form of arguments over their specific content.

Uploaded by

Muskan Lonial
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 20

Philosophy 201: Critical Thinking

Dr. C. Klatt
Unit 1: Deduction and Induction

Once we have established that the passage in question is an argument, we


still need to evaluate whether or not it is a good argument. That is, we need to
figure out whether or not the argument actually convinces us that some belief is
worth holding as true. Before we can get to evaluating arguments, we need to go
over some technical terms to describe these argument and we also need to
consider what will make an argument a good one.

It turns out that there are two different kinds of arguments. We call them
deductive and inductive arguments. All argument have an inferential claim. That
means, that each argument uses evidence and reason to infer that some claim
(the conclusion) is true. What differs in deductive and inductive arguments is
how much we are supposed to believe that the conclusion is true.

Every argument has an inferential claim.

In a deductive argument the conclusion necessarily follows from the


premises. That is, given the evidence in the premises, we should
believe the conclusion to be true for certain.

In an inductive argument the conclusion probably follows from the


premises. That is, given the evidence in the premises, we should
believe the conclusion to be true to some degree of probability.

Here are examples of each type of argument.

Deductive Inductive

All men are mortal. This goose is white.


Socrates is a man. That goose is white.
Socrates is mortal. All geese are white

For our deductive argument, if it is true the “all men are mortal” and it is
also the case that “Socrates is a man” then it just has to be the case that

1
“Socrates is mortal”. The intent here is to convince us that “Socrates in mortal”
for certain.

Our inductive argument is different. Here I’ve given you two observations of
geese that I found to be white. From that I want to conclude that “all geese are
white”. Well, seeing two white geese gives me some reason to believe that “all
geese are white” but it doesn’t make it true for certain. In fact, no matter how
many white geese I see, the conclusion in this or any other inductive argument
will never be true for certain.

With inductive arguments it is possible to add a premise to the


argument that would undercut our belief in the truth of the premise.

This goose is white.


That goose is white.
This goose is black.
All geese are white.

With inductive arguments, we can never be sure that the conclusion is


true because there is always the possibility that an added piece of
information will change our belief in the conclusion.

The example of the inductive argument that I’ve given you is called a
generalization (this is when you take a few examples and then generalize to a
larger group) but not all inductive arguments are generalizations.

The next example is also an inductive argument but it is called an analogy. In


this case we say something is true about a number of things but then conclude
that it will also be true of one additional thing.

Hitler was a dictator and was ruthless.


Stalin was a dictator and was ruthless.
Charles Taylor was a dictator and was ruthless.
Castro is a dictator.
Therefore, Castro is probably ruthless.

2
Determine whether the following arguments are deductive or inductive.

The sun is coming out, so the rain will probably stop soon.

It’s going to rain tomorrow, so it with either rain or be clear tomorrow.

The house is a mess, so Jeff must be home from college.

Evaluating Arguments: Validity, Soundness, Strength and Cogency

It is important to determine whether our arguments are deductive or inductive


because each type of argument is evaluated on different grounds.

How do we evaluate these arguments?

Argument Type How much to believe How we evaluate the


the conclusion argument
Deductive With certainty Validity
Inductive Probably Strength

Validity

The concept of validity is a bit tricky so don’t be frustrated if you don’t get it right
away. Recall from our first lecture that arguments can be bad in at least two
different ways. The premises may be false or irrelevant or the premises might be
fine but there is a problem with the pattern of the reasoning. With validity we are
considering whether the pattern or the form of the argument is a good one.

Let’s reconsider the following argument:

All snakes are reptiles. (T)


All snakes are legless. (T)
Therefore, all reptiles are legless. (F)

Whatever the pattern is in this argument, it doesn’t seem like a good


one because we have premises that are true and the conclusion turns 3
out to be false.
We can see why it would not be a good idea to use a pattern like this. It would be
deceitful to use a pattern of reasoning where I could give you perfectly good
premises and in turn convince you of something that turns out to be false.

A pattern will be problematic the premises are true and the conclusion is false.

T
T
F

A pattern that never has this problem is called valid.

An argument is valid if and only if it is not possible for all its


premises to be true when its conclusion is false.

In other words, for a valid argument, when the premises are true the
conclusion has to be true.

If it is possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false,


then the argument is invalid.

Consider the following argument.

All whales are mammals.


All mammals have lungs.
Therefore, all whales have lungs.

If you think about these sentences, it seems that when the premises are
true, the conclusion would have to be true.

Here is an outline of the pattern or form of the argument. Notice that when we
are looking at the pattern we don’t really care what the content of the sentence
is, just how the content is related to each other.
I have used various underline patterns for the words that are the same.

4
All _______ are ………….
All ………… are ,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,
Thus, all _______ are ,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,

Consider another example.

All spiders have ten legs. False


All ten-legged creatures have wings. False
Therefore, all spiders have wings. False

All of these sentences are false. However, that doesn’t really help us when
we are trying to determine if the pattern is valid. We need to pretend that the
premises are true and see if the conclusion must be true. Okay, so imagine that
you live in a world where it is true that “all spiders have ten legs”. It is also the
case that in this world “all ten-legged creatures have wings”. If those two
sentences are true, then it seems like it would just have to be the case that “all
spiders have wings”. The truth of the premises would guarantee the truth of the
conclusion. So this argument, even when all the sentences are false in our world,
is valid.

But look! The pattern in the spiders argument is the same as the pattern in the
whale argument! The content of the sentences is unimportant. Both of these
arguments have the same pattern and they are both valid.

Once you have determined that the argument form is valid, it is always valid. It
does not matter what is substituted in the blanks.

Here is another example.

If I owned Facebook then I would be wealthy.


I do not own Facebook.
Therefore, I am not wealthy.

5
If the premises in this argument are true, is it possible that the conclusion could
be false? That is, is T T / F possible?

Here is the pattern for this argument.

If ________ then ………


Not ________
Therefore, not ………

Let’s look at the same pattern with slightly different information


inserted in the blanks.

If Drake owned Facebook then Drake would be wealthy.


Drake does not own Facebook.
Therefore, Drake is not wealthy.

We can see with this substitution that, when using this argument pattern, it is
possible to have true premises and a false conclusion. Thus, this argument
pattern in invalid.

The tricky thing to realize here is that this pattern would be invalid no
matter what the truth value of the premises and conclusion are. The pattern
would be invalid even if the premises and the conclusion all turned out to be true!
The pattern is invalid because it is possible to use this pattern and come up with
true premises and a false conclusion. That combination just needs to be
possible.

Consider this example:

All cats have ears. True


All kittens have ears. True
All kittens are cats. True

In this argument all of the statements are true. Unfortunately, knowing that the
statements are all true doesn’t actually tell us if the pattern is valid or invalid.
What we have to ask ourselves is this: is it possible to use this pattern and end
up with all true premises and a false conclusion? Is that possible? I can make

6
one small change to content to see if that is the case. Let’s change ‘kittens’ to
‘dogs’. Now I have:

All cats have ears. True


All dogs have ears. True
All dogs are cats. False

I have used the same pattern and now I have all true premises and a false
conclusion. The argument is invalid. What is important to note here is that the
argument was also invalid when I was talking about the kittens. The sentences
happened to all be true but the pattern was still invalid because T T/F was
possible.

So, our invalid arguments can have sentences with many different truth
assignments. An invalid argument could present as T T/T, T F/F, F F/F etc.
What makes it invalid is that there will be a substitution where we get T T/F. A
valid argument can also have multiple truth assignments. The valid argument
about the snakes above was F F/F but it was still valid. The only substitution
that we won’t find with a valid argument is T T/F.

Valid arguments can have any combination of truth values for the
premises and the conclusion EXCEPT true premises and a false
conclusion.

T T T T F F F F
T T F F T T F F
F T T F T F T F

Invalid arguments can have any combination of truth values for the
premises and the conclusion.

Consider a couple more examples:

My job pays well and has benefits.


My job is fun.

7
In this case there is no well-defined pattern like we’ve had with previous
examples but we can still determine the validity by following the definition. Is it
possible for the premise to be true and the conclusion false? Yes. Just because a
job pays well and has benefits, doesn’t mean that the job will be fun. Invalid.

Zachary did not make the mess.


April did not make the mess.
Only Zachary, April and Madison were home today.
Thus, Madison made the mess.

If there are only three people who could have made the mess and two of them
didn’t do it, then it would have to be the case that the third person made the
mess. If the premises are true, the conclusion would have to be true. Valid.

Soundness

It is good if our argument pattern is valid but that doesn’t guarantee that
the conclusion will be true. For example, an argument could be valid and have a
false premise so the conclusion could be false as well. A valid argument
guarantees us a true conclusion only when all of the premises are true. So, we
need our arguments to be more than just valid. Ideally, we want our arguments
to be sound.

An argument is sound if:


i) it is valid; and,
ii) the premises are true.

If a deductive argument fails on either one (or both) of these conditions then it is
unsound.

8
Determine whether the following arguments are valid or invalid,
sound or unsound.

All cats are reptiles.


All reptiles have fur.
Therefore, all cats have fur.

Some Liberals are dentists.


Some Conservatives are not dentists.
Therefore, some Liberals are not Conservatives.

Consider the following two strange cases. Are these arguments valid or
invalid?

Sam is a doctor.
Sam is not a doctor.
Therefore, I am Prime Minister.

I am Prime Minister.
The moon is made of green cheese.
Therefore, Sam is Sam.

What we can see from these two examples is that knowing an argument is
valid does not mean that the premises will convince us that the conclusion is
true. It doesn’t even guarantee that the premises are even slightly related to the
conclusion. When we know that an argument is valid, all we know is that there
will be no instance when we use that argument pattern and come up with all true
premises and a false conclusion.

Given the definitions of validity and soundness, are the following


statements true or false?

Every argument with a false conclusion is invalid.

Every argument with a false premise is invalid.

Every argument with true premises and a false conclusion is invalid.


9
Every sound argument has a true conclusion.

Every argument with a true conclusion is sound.

Strength and Cogency

Validity and soundness are ways to evaluate deductive arguments. Inductive


arguments are judged on grounds of strength and cogency. Remember that the
intent with inductive arguments is different than with a deductive argument.
With inductive arguments we are only trying to convince the reader that the
conclusion is true to some degree of probability.

An inductive argument is strong if and only if:


it is improbable that the conclusion is false given that the
premises are true.

Premise (True)
Premise (True)
Conclusion (>= 50% likely to be true)

So, when the premises of an inductively strong argument are true, the
likelihood that the conclusion is true is equal to or greater than 50%. If the
likelihood that the conclusion will be true (given true premises) is less than 50%,
we say that the argument is weak.

Notice, we haven’t really set the bar very high when it comes to strong
arguments. The conclusion doesn’t have to be very likely to be true, just more
likely to be true than false.

Consider the following examples:

10
A vase was found broken on the floor and some money was missing from
the safe. Therefore, someone must have burglarized the place.

Given the evidence that the vase has been broken and money is missing from the
safe, it seems at least 50% likely that I’ve been burglarized. That doesn’t mean
that I’ve been burglarized for certain, only that it is at least 50% likely that that is
what has gone on here.

My father likes fishing so your father will probably like fishing as well.

Now, if the only thing that these two people have in common is that they
are fathers, it doesn’t seem likely that they will both enjoy the same hobby. The
evidence just isn’t good enough to convince me that the conclusion is likely to be
true.

As we saw with deductive arguments and validity, knowing that your


inductive argument is strong doesn’t mean that you’ll have a conclusion that is
likely to be true. What we really want from our inductive arguments is for them
to be cogent. Cogency is very similar to soundness but it applies to inductive
arguments.

An inductive argument is cogent if and only if:


i) it is a strong argument,
ii) it has true premises.

Comparison of Deductive and Inductive Arguments

Deductive and inductive arguments differ on a number of grounds.

11
1) Evaluation

We judge the pattern of deductive arguments to be valid or invalid. For


inductive arguments, we determine if the evidence is sufficient to judge
the conclusion to be true to some degree of probability. If the 50%
threshold is met, we call the argument strong.

Inductive arguments are not intended to be valid so it is wrong to


criticize them for a lack of validity.

2) Adding Premises

Adding premises to an inductive argument can undercut, perhaps


completely, the support for the conclusion.

It was sunny two days ago.


It was sunny yesterday.
It will probably be sunny tomorrow.

It was sunny two days ago.


It was sunny yesterday.
It is raining today.
It will probably be sunny tomorrow.

Once we know that it is raining today, our belief in the conclusion decreases
drastically.

12
Adding premises to a valid argument has a different effect. It turns
out that once we know we have a valid argument, there are no
premises that we can add to make it invalid.

If it is raining then the picnic will be cancelled.


It is raining.
The picnic will be cancelled.

If it is raining then the picnic will be cancelled.


It is raining.
It is not raining.
The picnic will be cancelled.

We may initially think that deductive arguments are actually better than
inductive arguments because with deductive arguments you end up believing the
conclusion to be true for certain. And who doesn’t love certainty?

3) Belief in the Conclusion

However, we should not conclude that inductive arguments are


somehow inferior to deductive arguments. Here is an illustration of
why.

All geese are white. Deductive


The goose at the zoo will be white.

This goose is white. Inductive


The goose at the zoo will be white.

Consider the preceding arguments. Each argument concludes the same


thing but the deductive argument convinces us that the conclusion is true for
certain, whereas the inductive argument only convinces us that the conclusion is
true to some degree of probability.

So, why don’t we prefer the deductive argument? Well, compare the
premises. In the deductive argument the premise is that “all geese are white”.
What would I have to do to know that that statement is true? To know that “all
13
geese are white” is true, I’d have to look at all geese for all time! Whereas I can
easily know that “this goose is white” is true with a simple observation.

Deductive arguments do convince us that the conclusion is true for certain


but it can be much harder to determine if the premises in deductive arguments
are actually true. That’s the tradeoff. In fact, these two kinds of arguments are
intimately linked together. Often I know that sentences like “all geese are white”
is true but I’ve seen a lot of geese, they’ve all been white and I inductively infer
that “all geese are white”. The deductive argument often depends on inductive
reasoning to show that its premises are true.

Exercises – Determine if the following arguments are deductive or


inductive and correspondingly valid/invalid and sound/unsound or
strong/weak and cogent/uncogent.

Joe and I have similar tastes in food. Joe says that the food in the
restaurant is first-rate. So I will find it first-rate.

Social welfare is by definition a handout to people who have not worked


for it. But giving people money they have not earned through labour is
not helping anyone. It follows then that social welfare does not help
anyone.

Bachelors are unmarried. George is a bachelor. Thus, he does not have


a wife.

Bachelors are unmarried, and George acts as if he’s not married. He’s a
bachelor for sure.

14
The Counter Example Method

We have discussed what it means for a deductive argument to be valid or


invalid but we have not yet presented a method to determine validity. Our first
attempt at this will be by using the counter example method to show that an
argument pattern is invalid.

Recall that an argument form, when shown to be valid, will always be


valid (independent of the content).

All cats have fur. All bleebs are goony.


All furry things shed. All goony things are ript.
All cats shed. All bleebs are ript.

The second argument has the same pattern as the first argument so if the first
argument is valid, so is the second one (even though the words in the second
argument do not make sense).

The same can be said for INVALID arguments. As long as both


arguments have the same pattern, when we know that first argument
is invalid, so must be the second.

All dogs are furry. All whales like to eat.


All cats are furry. All mammals like to eat.
All dogs are cats. All whales are mammals.

Both of these arguments are invalid (even though the one on the right
has all true premises).

So, to prove that an argument is INVALID we:

A) determine the form of the argument.


B) substitute content into the argument form that makes the
premises obviously true and the conclusion obviously false.

15
Step 1: Get rid of all the language that is not logically necessary for the
argument.

I found it very fascinating that orcas are in fact a kind of dolphin.


Dolphins are known to be intelligent. Therefore, it is reasonable to
say that orcas are intelligent as well.

All orcas are dolphins.


All dolphins are intelligent.
All orcas are intelligent.

Get rid of all premise and conclusion indicators. E.g. because, since,
therefore. The indicator words are useful to help us place the
sentences as premises above the line or as the conclusion below the
line but once we have the sentences in place, the indicator words are
no longer needed.

Keep all logical connectors like ‘and’, ‘or’,’if … then’, ‘not’, ‘if and only
if’. For categorical statements include ‘all’, ‘some’ and ‘no’.

Example

All galaxies are structures that contain black holes in the center, so all
galaxies are quasars, since all quasars are structures that contain
black holes in the center.

All galaxies are structures that contain black holes in the center.
All quasars are structures that contain black holes in the center.
All galaxies are quasars.

Step 2: Determine the form (i.e. pattern) of the argument. Take out
the sentence content and replace with letters.

All G are B.
All Q are B.
All G are Q.

16
Step 3: Replace the content of the argument so that the premises are
obviously true and the conclusion is obviously false.

Hint: Try to make the conclusion false first.

G = ducks, B = swimmers, Q = fish

All ducks are swimmers. (T)


All fish are swimmers. (T)
All ducks are fish. (F)

The argument is invalid (because T T/F is possible). This means that the
argument with the galaxies (that has the same pattern) is invalid as well.

What is wrong with the following substitution?

All surfers are good swimmers.


All jet-skiers are good swimmers.
All surfers are jet-skiers.

The substitutions must be made in a way that the premises are


OBVIOUSLY TRUE and the conclusion is OBVIOUSLY FALSE.

Exercises

If taxes are increased then consumer spending will decrease.


If consumer spending does not decrease then more people will be
employed.
Therefore, if more people are employed then we will increase taxes.

Hint: An if … then is false when the antecedent is true and the


consequent is false.

17
If children fail to eat a good breakfast then they will be unable to
concentrate in school.
Children are unable to concentrate in school.
So, children are failing to eat a good breakfast.

Hint: In this case the conclusion doesn’t have much logical


structure to it (it is just one sentence) so true to make one of the
premises true. To make an if ..then statement true pick a
necessary relationship between the antecedent and the
consequent.

Special Case:

All bachelors are persons. All B are P.


All unmarried men are persons. All U are P.
Therefore, all bachelors are unmarried men. All B are U.

This argument looks like it has an invalid form but the argument pattern is
actually valid because the conclusion is always true. What has gone wrong here?
The counter example method will work as long as the pattern you write down
accurately reflects what is going on in the argument. Our mistake here was
giving different letters to “bachelors” and to “unmarried men” when they are
actually the same. The argument should have been written as:

18
All B are P.
All B are P.
All B are B.

There is no substitution that can make the premises true and the conclusion
false.

Question: Can we use this method to prove an argument valid?


That is, if we find a substitution instance that makes the premises
and the conclusion obviously true, do we know that the argument is
valid?

No. An argument with true premises and a true conclusion may be


either valid or invalid. Only an argument with true premises and a
false conclusion can be proven invalid. So, the counter example
method can only be used to prove that an argument pattern is
invalid. We will find a method later on that can help us prove that
an argument pattern is valid.

Exercises

Some farm workers are not persons who are paid decent wages,
because no illegal aliens are persons who are paid decent wages, and
some illegal aliens are not farm workers.

19
If animal species are fixed and immutable, then evolution is a myth.
Therefore, evolution is a myth, since animal species are not fixed
and immutable.

All community colleges with low tuition are either schools with large
enrollments or institutions supported by taxes. Therefore, all
community colleges with low tuition are institutions supported by
taxes.

20

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy