Cultural Constraints On Grammar in Piraha A Reply
Cultural Constraints On Grammar in Piraha A Reply
net/publication/215992069
CITATIONS READS
29 884
1 author:
Daniel L. Everett
Bentley University
82 PUBLICATIONS 2,598 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Daniel L. Everett on 20 January 2014.
Daniel L. Everett
Linguistics, Anthropology, and Biological Sciences
Illinois State University
March, 2007
Abstract: In Everett (2005b) I argued that Pirahã culture constrains its grammar. This
paper is a response to a recent critique of Everett (2005b) by Nevins et al. (2007, MS). I address
the criticisms raised in Nevins et al. paper and I continue to argue that Pirahã presents problems
for the notion of a Universal Grammar. I further argue that the methods traditionally used in the
Generative Grammar tradition are flawed and do not meet the scientific standards accepted
across different fields in science, thereby making it difficult to assess the validity of the claims
made by Nevins et al.
1. Introduction2
Here is a question most linguists do not ask: How much grammar does a language
need? For example, we all know that successful communication is underdetermined by
language. And language is underdetermined by grammar. Consider well-known examples
like the following:
1
An update to this paper will be posted to this website in a few weeks, after additional experimental
studies on recursion (Eugenie Stapert, Michael Frank, Ted Gibson, Evelina Fedorenko, and D.
Everett) and numbers (Frank, Everett, Fedorenko, and Gibson) are complete, along with links to
these papers.
2
For useful comments on this reply, I would like to think Ted Gibson, Mike Frank, Ev Fedorenko, Jeanette
Sakel, Mark Liberman, Geoff Pullum, Steve Sheldon, Tom Headland, Geoff Sampson, and Paul Postal. I
especially want to thank Linda Wulfman for her encouragement and advice.
information for a stand-alone interpretation. It can provide a range of interpretations, in
the case of ambiguity of different types, or no particular interpretation, in the case of
vagueness (as in (5)). Or the communication can only partially rely on language, as in (6).
This raises the question as to just how much grammar is needed in a successful
human communication system and the role that grammar and language together play in
such a system. Everett (2005b) was a beginning attempt to answer this question. Everett
(2005b) situates itself within the deep traditions of American Descriptive Linguistics (not
to be confused with Structuralism) of Franz Boas, Edward Sapir, on the one hand, and the
philosophical tradition of American Pragmatism, represented by Peirce, James, and
Dewey on the other. This is taken up more in the final section of this paper, where I argue
that the Pirahã facts support a 'Pragmatist Linguistics' and continue to present severe
problems for Chomskyan or other theories committed to a Universal Grammar.
Now, Nevins, Pesetsky, and Rodrigues (2007), henceforth NPR, have written a
long rebuttal to that attempt. They are concerned about nearly every point that I made in
Everett (2005b), but seem particularly exercised by my claim that there is no evidence in
Pirahã for recursion, a property predicted to be the single most important property of
human languages in recent work by Chomsky and others (more on this below). I will
clarify more here what I mean by the proposal that Pirahã lacks recursion since it was not
as clear as it might have been in Everett (2005b), partially due to the fact that there is no
clear, widely accepted definition of recursion in the literature. Everett (2005b) argued
further, that the Pirahã data show an architectonic effect of culture on the grammar of
Pirahã and this too is not predicted by Chomskyan linguistics. I see nothing in NPR that
leads me to reconsider these main points, though I will clarify some details.
There are two reasons why it is unsurprising and appropriate that NPR offer this
rebuttal. First, as I have said many times over the years, no research results should be
taken at face value. Results, especially from challenging field situations like the work I
have engaged in with the Pirahãs for over 28 years – a monolingual situation requiring
long months of language-learning before detailed or in-depth research can even start (on
the monolingual method, see Everett (in preparation a), Everett (2004), and Everett
(2001)), need to be examined carefully. Research results must of course bear scrutiny.
Second, it is appropriate that these particular authors take up this task, because they are
all trained in and deeply committed to a particularly strong set of hypotheses of
Generative Grammar. All three of them adopt the well-known Chomskyan position that
all languages share a set of core structural constraints variously known as Universal
Grammar, the Language Organ (on the latter see Everett (2005a; 2006b) for serious
criticisms), etc.
This paper is a response to the criticisms of NPR of the case made in Everett
(2005b). I owe NPR a debt of gratitude for allowing me the occasion to further
substantiate the claims of Everett (2005b). In this additional argumentation and
documentation, I am going to argue that the paper by NPR is wrong on just about every
single point – not only about Pirahã but also about how to do linguistics more generally.
This reply is organized as follows. I will first respond to the criticisms of Everett
(2005b)'s claim that Pirahã lacks recursion, as well as the discrepancies between that
work and my earlier work, Everett (1983/1986). I begin this by examining a later and
slightly revised statement of the thesis of Everett (2005b), published as Everett (2006a).
In this section, I examine the arguments in the work by NPR against parataxis, looking
2
carefully at their analysis of nominalization, Wh-questions and movement, indirect
speech, and so on. In every case I conclude that NPR's counterproposals are incorrect. I
then discuss other components of Everett (2005b) that NPR take issue with (e.g.
quantifiers, color words, numerals, etc.). In the final section, I offer a general criticism of
Generative Grammar and explain why the Pirahã facts continue to be such a devastating
indictment of the Generative theoretical framework. In this section, I also outline an
alternative approach to the study of human language that is not based on Universal
Grammar. I suggest that other languages like Pirahã no doubt exist, many in fact, but that
a Whorfian effect on linguistics research often impedes the discovery of such cases.
I want to make clear from the outset that this reply to NPR is not meant to be
either a stand-alone paper or publishable article. It is simply meant to supply some of the
reasoning behind Everett (2005b) and answer the criticisms of NPR. Therefore, the reader
may need a copy of NPR to follow my arguments. Experimental work is in progress and
more detailed studies of Pirahã syntax are underway by the author and by various other
researchers who have conducted field research on Pirahã.
It is important to realize there are two sets of claims here and in Everett (2005b):
(i) that culture exercises an architectonic effect on grammar; (ii) that the observations by
Everett (2005b) on Pirahã's lexical, cultural, and syntactic features are correct. The
former could be wrong and the latter correct or vice-versa. They are separate sets of
hypothesis.
1. The criticisms
According to NPR they have three principal reasons for writing this paper. First,
my work has received a lot of attention from the popular press and they feel that it is
incumbent upon them to evaluate the analyses that have attracted so much attention.
Second, Pirahã looks to NPR to be 'just a language' like any other and this is, to them and
the Generative Enterprise as well, 'just as exciting'. Third, they want to encourage further
research on Pirahã. I am also interested in this, so this is also a goal of the present paper.
A list of researchers previously and currently engaged in research on Pirahã through my
own efforts is given in section 7 below.
On page 6, NPR says that they base their arguments on Everett (1986), rather than
Everett (2005b). They say on this page:
"... since we have not yet done independent fieldwork on Pirahã, we cannot
independently verify the descriptions offered in this earlier work of Everett's.
Nonetheless, we are impressed with its comprehensiveness, perspicacity and
consistency. These properties suggest that this earlier work is a reliable guide to
basic properties of Pirahã, as well as to those complex properties of the language
that it discusses in depth. As we also noted above, in the two decades between the
publication of DISS and HAL and the appearance of CA, Everett (1987a) appears
to be the only significant additional contribution to the study of Pirahã syntax
besides the on-line texts cited above."
3
Everett (2005b). They thus conclude that Everett (1986) is a more reliable guide to Pirahã
than Everett (2005b). Interesting. I would find the opposite troubling, i.e. that a
researcher never changed their mind or found errors in their earlier work.
I am going to begin this discussion with a restatement of the Immediacy of
Experience Principle (IEP) in Everett (2005b), the revised and fuller statement in Everett
(2006a), along with a summary of how this version of the IEP predicts the facts that
Everett (2005b) focused on and which NPR attempt to reanalyse.
I claim that this predicts the following unusual convergence of properties in Pirahã
grammar and culture:
(2) a. A --> BC
b. B--> DE
c. C --> AF
3
Mark Liberman (email of March 22, 2007) comments that "... if a language has pronouns or nouns like
'fact' or 'situation' that can refer to the content of another clause (previous or upcoming), then any recursive
structure of the form
1. (A (B C))
2. (B C). (A that).
In connected discourse, the same sort of cross-reference may also be assumed with any explicit referring
expression."
Once again, however, my claim is not that the Pirahã cannot think recursively, but that their syntax is not
recursive. This is an argument about thinking and interpreting, not about syntax proper.
4
(3) A --> AB
(4) Coordination:
English a. [NP John and Bill] came to town yesterday.
b. [S [S I saw [NP Mary, Sue, and Willy] [PP in town and at the
mall] and [S I saw some other people too]].
(5) Disjunction:
a. Either [NP Bob or Bill] will come.
b. I had [NP chicken or pork], some white meat.
(7) Embedding:
a. I doubt [S whether they will come].
b. John says [S that Bill thinks [S that Mary will agree [S that Sue should come
too]]].
NUMBER & NUMERALS: These are skills that have both immediate application and
wider application, ranging beyond immediate experience. Since the latter uses would
violate the cultural principle in (1), however, these are not available in the grammar.
Moreover, since, as Wiese (2003) argues the recursivity of the number system is
borrowed from recursion in human languages, the absence of recursion in a human
4
In this paper, I will represent low tone on examples by zero marking and high tone by an acute accent
following the vowel.
5
language predicts that that language should also lack a numerical system with counting.
RELATIVE TENSES: These involve assertions defined in terms other than the moment
of speech. So when I say in Pirahã 'When you arrive, I will go', as I show in Everett
(1993), both 'arriving' and 'going' are defined relative to the moment of speech, (however,
one could argue that relative tenses involve recursion and so are for this reason
unavailable). More complex tenses would violate (2).
KINSHIP TERMS: The set of Pirahã kinship terms omits words for relations that
exceed Pirahã life expectancy (about 40 years). That is, they name relationships that the
Pirahã can have with living people, in accordance with the IEP, relations that can be
witnessed directly. Also, supporting the lack of recursion in Pirahã grammar, none of
their kinship terms are recursive, i.e. defined in terms of other relations (e.g. grandfather,
grandson, etc.). The general simplicity of the system apart from the lack of generational
depth may or may not follow from the IEP and/or from other cultural principles.
COLOR TERMS AND QUANTIFIERS: Color terms and quantifiers can identify
immediate experiences, as can numbers, but, like numbers, are avoided by the grammar
because they also entail generalizations ranging beyond immediate experience. See below
for more on this.
MYTHS AND FICTION: These violate the evidentiality constraint in (1).
NPR fail to consider carefully many of the facts I called attention to in Everett
(2005b) (ignoring entirely for example, the very important points in (4) - (6) above).
Nevertheless, I will consider the points that they do address and then discuss these other
points.
Problems of translation
As another methodological preliminary, however, let me say something about
glossing of examples in Everett (2005b). On page 7 of NPR, the authors say in effect that
the more recent glosses of Everett (2005b) are inferior to the glosses of Everett (1986)
because they are too detailed (!):
'A few notes about the presentation of data in our paper. Everett in DISS and HAL
presents Pirahã examples in the standard manner familiar in linguistics, with
dashes and spaces separating morphemes judged to be independent, and with
glosses and translations offering a fair approximation of the meaning of Pirahã
rendered into Portuguese (DISS) and English (HAL). Similar data as presented in
CA has a rather different character. Morpheme division is more extreme, and
many glosses appear to reflect etymology rather than current meaning. For
example, CA offers the gloss 'cloth arm' where HAL has 'hammock', and insists that
the Pirahã rendering of 'all' actually means 'big'. As Wierzbicka (2005) notes in
her commentary on CA, "in using such glosses, Everett exoticizes the language
rather than identifying its genuinely distinctive features. To say that ti ’ogi means,
literally, 'my bigness' (rather than 'we') is like saying that in English to understand
means, literally, 'to stand under.' To deny that hi’ogi means 'all' is to make a
similar mistake."'
6
This quote seems to be based on what Everett (2005b) refers to as the Universal
Translation Fallacy, that is, that all languages translate fairly well into one another (and
for a much more developed argument against universal translatability, see Grace (1987)).
There are two reasons for the much greater detail in the morpheme glosses of
Everett (2005b). First and foremost is the simple fact that I have learned a lot about the
morphology that I did not know in (1986). If anything, I would say that the
morphological breaks in Everett (2005b) are not detailed enough. As I work more on the
language, I expect to make even finer and more accurate breaks. Contra NPR and
Wierzbicka (whom I already answered in Everett (2005b) and about which I have more to
say below), a more detailed representation of Pirahã morphological structure is not an
'exoticization' of the language. NPR are correct that in some compounds that I have
glossed literally, the speakers do not seem to think about the literal meaning of the
individual components. But I chose to represent the literal meanings and etymologies for
two reasons. First, it is no longer so clear to me that these are not interpreted literally,
contra Everett (1986). Second, it is worth informing the reader a bit about the complexity
of Pirahã morphology in the context of discussing the simplicity of its syntax. At the
same time, the semantic shifts typical of some compounds is not a characteristic of the
inflectional morphology that I have been able to understand better over the years. (And
NPR should be aware of the difference between inflectional and derivational
morphology.) Of course, to loosely translate hi'ogi as 'all' would indeed make Pirahã
sound like languages that NPR are familiar with. But it would be an inaccurate analysis
of the phrase because, as I discuss again below, there is no word in Pirahã with the
meaning of the English word 'all'.
2. Recursion
NPR's discussion (p9ff) of embedding is partially beside the point because they
have not bothered to interact with my more recent, published restatement of the effect on
recursion of the Immediacy of Experience Principle (IEP) (given in (1) above), from
Everett (2006a). Further, NPR claim, erroneously, that I am arguing that Pirahã lacks
discrete infinity. No, I am claiming that it lacks recursion. I have no opinion about the
former (with regard to the former, NPR say that discrete infinity is responsible for the
fact that languages do not make sentences of 4.5 words. But discrete infinity has nothing
to do with the absence of '.5 of a word' because there is no such thing as half a word!).
One should not rush to condemn NPR for their confusion, however, because the Hauser,
Chomsky, and Fitch (2002) article on which they rely provides no clear definition of
what is meant by recursion in the first place. In fact there is no definition of recursion
widely accepted. Recursion as a property of human languages is problematic at our
current level of understanding. For that matter, so is 'discrete infinity'. Both of these
notions could be accused of making the incorrect prediction that languages are actually
infinite when of course they are not. There is no infinite language, nor could there be one
spoken by humans. So recursion and discrete infinity are to a degree just metaphors. This
vagueness in claims of recursion is the main reason that I have organized the first-ever
conference on Recursion in Human Languages (RECHUL), to be held at Illinois State
University on April 27-29 (http://www.foreignlanguages.ilstu.edu/rechul/). And as some
typologists have noted (Marianne Mithun will be speaking on this as an invited speaker at
RECHUL), languages vary tremendously in the degree to which they manifest recursion
7
in speech. I suspect in fact that in addition to Pirahã, many other languages, e.g. the so-
called non-configurational languages that Ken Hale called attention to, could turn out to
be better understood as non-recursive languages. I hope that my work will stimulate more
research on this important topic.
(10) a. No numerals or counting (since these are built on recursion, as per Wiese
(2003).
b. No auxiliary verbs (something that Everett (1986) brings out and that I
forgot to list as a confirmed prediction in Everett (2005b). Thanks to G.K. Pullum
(p.c.) for bringing this to my attention).
c. No stacked possessors.
d. No conjunction.
e. No disjunction.
"To pick an example of particular relevance to Pirahã, we can note that English
allows prenominal possessive noun phrases to embed other possessives — but
5
NPR also say that part of my explanation of the lack of prenominal possessor 'stacking' is that every
Pirahã knows every other Pirahã. This is a fact that I believe facilitates the interpretations of such
structures, but I do not believe that it explains or predicts the fact. This is what the IEP is proposed to do.
8
German does not (Krause (2000a, 2000b)); Roeper and Snyder (2005)). As Roeper
and Snyder put it: "the English possessive is potentially recursive [(3a)], while the
Saxon genitive [its counterpart in German] is not [(3b)]" (compare (4a-b)): "
Since a German speaker can do the "Mary thinks that... trick" as well as an English
speaker can, no one could rationally imagine (even if so inclined) that the
unacceptability of recursion in prenominal possessors is due to some global
absence of recursion in German. Likewise, we imagine that that it is beyond
dispute that the culture of the German-speaking regions of Europe allows for
creation myths, artwork, counting and discourse not bound to the "here and now".
It thus seems unlikely that one would attribute the absence of recursive prenominal
possessors to any pattern of cultural gaps like that claimed by Everett for the
Pirahã. Instead, there must be some provision available to human languages
(usually called a "parameter") that "turns off" the possibility of recursion within
possessive phrases. The switch itself might be fairly abstract in nature.
But as Manfred Krifka points out (email to Everett, 12 March, 2007), this seems
incorrect:
"I don't think that German prenominal possessives are not recursive. We find, for
example, many examples of the phrase seines Bruders Hüter on the Web (not only
as the title of a German translation of a book of Stanislaus Joyce's book about his
brother James Joyce). In addition, we also find examples like Peters Bruders
Harley (http://www.tautoo.de/galerie.html), Peters Vaters Auto (http://www.itp-
arcados.net/leben/human.faces2000db.html), Peters Mutters Auto
(http://myblog.de/rene.ueber.alles). It is true that examples like ??Peters Autos
Motor is quite bad, but this seems to be due to the fact that prenominal genitives
are restricted to names and kinship terms in contemporary German (?des Lehrers
Auto)."
So NPR do not appear to get the facts right about German possessors. And if
Krifka is on the right track with his conjecture that prenominal possession could be
limited to names and kinship terms, then German prenominal possessor restrictions seem
at least as likely to be accounted for by a cultural constraint as by a 'parameter'.
Therefore, contra NPR, German not only presents no problem at all for my analysis, but it
potentially offers additional support for my suggestion that culture affects grammar. Of
course, it is not my hypothesis, contra the quote above from NPR that the same cultural
constraint fits all cultures. That would make little sense.6
6
Geoff Sampson reports potential cultural differences in English as well on prenominal possessors: "The
point about the apostrophe-s genitive being restricted is one of the differences between American and
British English which seems not to be well known but which is quite significant in actual usage. I would
9
Moreover, the NPR answer misses a crucial fact. The German -s possessive may be
only somewhat recursive. But German also has another possessive which is fully
recursive (the latinate route, using "of", e.g. "the daughter of the father of my cousin").
Hence, Germans can express recursive possession by some conventionalized route. As
far as I can tell from my data, there is no conventionalized route for Pirahã speakers to
express recursive possession. This is a fundamental difference between the languages.
Just a few examples of nested "von" plurals from the web include: von den vater von
meine frau; der Liedertext von Die Mutter von James Bond von Elsterglanz; zur lage von
die sprache von Peter Kohler.
On page 10, NPR say that they cannot understand how the lack of embedding
follows form the IEP. As I have stated it in (1) this should now be obvious (though that of
course does not make it correct). Let me restate it: in order to avoid non-assertions in
declarative utterances, prohibited by the IEP, Pirahã has to avoid embedding. It does this
by simply not having recursion. This also predicts the lack of multiple prenominal
possessors and, as we see directly, potentially even the lack of numbers and counting
(and if this is correct this lack is predicted both by the IEP directly and indirectly by the
IEP's prohibition on recursion). So I must admit that I cannot understand their lack of
understanding of this point (that they might not agree is another matter entirely).
never say a phrase like "John's car's motor", and I think it unlikely that I would spontaneously say even "the
car's motor", because the apostrophe-s genitive has a strong preference for being used with people rather
than inanimate objects; if I did use the phrase "the car's motor" I would have a feeling of
anthropomorphizing the car a bit, like sailors calling a ship she. I know that Americans seem to use the
apostrophe-s genitive much more freely, so they sometimes put it even on nouns for abstractions, where it
sounds really bizarre to me."
10
no –sai in either clause:
(12) (hi) 'oba'axa'i' (hi) kahai'-kai -bai
he sees well (he) arrow-make -intensive
'He makes arrows well.'
d. etc.
Now it is true that Everett (1986) analyses the –sai as a nominalizer. It does
commonly (but not obligatorily) go on new expressions, e.g. (15), to indicate their
function as a noun (the translation before the / is the preferred reading, according to tests
with native speakers):
I actually was the first person to apply the expression in (16) to a propeller years
ago when the Pirahãs asked me what the propeller on a plane did. They liked my
'invention' and use it now as a name for propellers. The –sai commonly appears when the
expression is used as a noun, but is not obligatory – another problem for the 'nominalizer'
analysis of Everett (1986).
One of the first bits of evidence that led me to question my analysis of –sai as a
nominalizer were examples of the addition of this suffix to morphologically simple nouns
as in (15). Why would a noun take a nominalizer? This appears at first blush to be
unlikely. But it is likely that –sai can attach to nouns when these nouns express old
11
information in a text, such as the topic. This insight, along with my readings in the
growing research on information structure eventually led me to abandon the analysis of –
sai as a nominalizer and look more carefully at the morphologically properties of what I
had thought until then were embedded clauses.7 I came to the conclusion that –sai is in
fact not a nominalizer at all but a marker of old information (see VanValin and Everett
(in preparation) for more details). If this hypothesis is correct, it predicts that –sai can be
used in a much wider range of structures than those in my thesis or the description in the
Handbook of Amazonian Languages. Subsequent examination of texts and, more
recently, experimental work conducted with Ted Gibson and Mike Frank in a Pirahã
village support this.
So –sai is not like the nominalization patterns discussed by Koptjevskaja-Tamm
(1993), as cited by NPR cite. Moreover, contra Everett (1986), as seen in the examples
above, both sentences can be fully inflected, leading me to ultimately abandon my
analysis of these as embedding in favor of the simpler and superior analysis of parataxis.
"The constituents that we (in agreement with HAL) would identify as complement
clauses look quite ordinary from a cross-linguistic perspective. [emphasis on 'look' mine,
DLE]" Let's think about this statement for a bit. Apparently, the methodology implied is
just this. First, you 'look' at a structure in language x. If it 'looks' like a structure from
language y, for which there is an analysis accepted in the Generative Grammar literature,
then you may assume that this example from language x further supports the conclusions
drawn from language y. We can label this the methodology of 'eyeballing'.
I would suggest an alternative method, one common to the American
Descriptivists. Each construction in each language should be studied in its appropriate
linguistic and cultural contexts before drawing any conclusions about it. This is one
reason I almost agree with a statement that I overheard from a field linguist a few years
ago that no one should be allowed to write an article about a language before they have
written an entire grammar of the language. Only after writing a grammar of a language
can you contextualize your understanding of how structures and constructions and
meanings work in that language. NPR is rife with the eyeballing methodology and, as we
see directly, this leads them not only to their embarrassing speculations about Pirahã, but
erroneous and equally misinformed analyses of languages as well-known as German.
Superficial similarities between languages count for next to nothing in mature analysis,
except to fuel initial hunches. That is, they are fine if used abductively, but very bad
when used deductively, as they are in NPR. To conclude this section, just as the example
from my HAL description that NPR cite approvingly as parataxis on their page 14 is a
7
As a matter of potential historical interest, I did wonder about my own analysis as early as 1984. Everett
(1986) was actually written in 1982 in Portuguese, appearing initially as Everett (1983) and later as Everett
(1990). So since I was a Visiting Scholar at MIT during this time, I talked to Chomsky about my idea that
there seemed to be very little evidence for embedding of any kind in Pirahã, apart from these –sai examples
which I was beginning to question. We discussed it briefly and Noam gave me some ideas for further
testing the idea. Mark Baker, writing his PhD under Noam at the time, mentioned to me one day as we were
having lunch that Noam was really intrigued by the idea that a language might not have embedded (Mark
said something like 'You really got Noam's attention with what you told him about Pirahã', or some such).
In any case, though I had a growing suspicion that my 1982 analysis was wrong, based as I say here, on
artificially and exclusively elicited data, I didn't have the time (I was then working mainly on phonology)
nor the courage to develop these ideas further – not until 2004 at the Max Planck in Leipzig, did I have the
occasion to reconsider in detail all of these ideas and begin to formulate a radically different analysis.
12
solid example of juxtaposition, so are the examples with –sai. NPR's example (10) is
repeated here as (17):
These, NPR say, are good examples of parataxis because the sentences are fully
inflected and there is no –sai in them. But just as the other examples that have –sai do not
obligatorily take it, so (17a) can in fact take –sai:
(17b) cannot take –sai because it is in fact a mix of Portuguese and Pirahã (the
Pirahã was trying to make himself intelligible to me, because this was recorded when I
was just learning the language, so he put in what Portuguese he was able to help me along
– though notice that he uses Pirahã grammar). But the point is that these examples are no
different in relation to –sai in principle than any others.
To sum up, -sai marks old information and is not a nominalizer. The sentences in
(11)-(15) can manifest –sai on either clause, contra Everett (1986) or on neither clause, so
both clauses can be fully inflected, also contra Everett (1986).
The evidence given here for parataxis is stronger than that given in Everett
(2005b). One especially weak argument for parataxis in that paper was the evidence I
provided for the absence of overt WH-movement across multiple clauses. I concede that
that argument for parataxis was weak. Of course, the argument that remains is that there
is no evidence for covert WH-movement across clauses either. But I will not enter into
the murky world of covert movement, since the arguments given in this section are
sufficient to estabilsh that the 'embedded clauses ' of Everett (1986) cited by NPR are not
embedded clauses and that –sai is neither a nominalizer nor a subordinator.
8
NPR add to my gloss "[lit. 'Martinho pays little. Xoogiái pays better. - authors]". NPR once again change
my Pirahã translation based on no more evidence than that it sounds better to them. But this does not mean
'better' in Pirahã. Pirahã lacks comparatives. The 'clumsier' translation in Everett (2005b), literally in the
gloss in this example, is the only one that corresponds to the facts of the Pirahã language. In fact, since the
Pirahã speaker here is using Portuguese, we can ask why he did not use the Portuguese comparative
'melhor'. Work in progress by Jeanette Sakel addresses the limited use of Portuguese by Pirahã speakers,
including the degree to which the Pirahãs use Pirahã grammar when speaking Portuguese. (And there is no
inconsistency with saying that they use bits of Portuguese here and there and that they are monolingual.)
Again, I am bemused as to why people who have never learned a single word of a language feel at liberty
to suggest translations for it, based on nothing more than their expectations from other languages. This is
semantic eyeballing to match the syntactic eyeballing seen elsewhere.
13
The clarification-parataxis analysis thus accounts for many facts that the –
sai/nominalization/subordination analysis does not account for. Let me summarize this in
(18):
These data are predicted by the analysis in Everett (2005b), i.e. that the
relationship between the two clauses is parataxis.
This revised analysis of –sai as a marker of old information also predicts its
occurrence on the verb 'to say' gai' in quotatives, i.e. on what would normally be
expected to be the main clause (e.g. hi gai'-sai tiobahai kabiiga 'He says-sai there is no
child here.') 'He says NPR on p21ff strain and heave to offer an account of this
distribution of –sai in their framework, but the 'old information' analysis predicts it
straightforwardly, since the content of what is said is generally the new information, not
the saying of it, which is the old information. But –sai, again, is not required even here
(as data from Everett , which NPR cite, (1986) show)
It is correct that Everett (2005b), as NPR point out, says that the crystallized form
of the verb 'to say', gai (with a low tone on the a and a high tone on the i), always seems
to be accompanied by -sai. This is likely nothing more than a construction in the sense of
Construction Grammar. But of course other forms of the verb 'to say' can be inflected, as
can the content of the quote. As NPR show, I illustrated such forms in Everett (1986).
Of course they are right about the English in (18). But their interpretation of (19),
is wrong:
9
The additional reading that Everett (1986) offers for (19) is 'I will not let you make an arrow.' But this is
only a loose pragmatic reading and is generally not present, i.e. most speakers do not get this reading. To
prohibit someone from doing something, one uses the prohibitive suffix –saha'ai, as discussed in Everett
(1986, section 18).
14
The main assertion of the pair of sentences in (20) is 'I am not ordering you.' This
is the main assertion because serves as an assurance in the context that another Pirahã
value is not being violated, i.e. the value that no one should command anyone else (at
least not one adult to another, though children are often ordered, but not always, by their
parents). The following, independent clause in (18) adds a clarification. A free translation
of the entire clause would be something like (21):
(21) I am not ordering you. (That is, that you) make an arrow.
The presence of the old information marker –sai supports this analysis, since the
clarification would be old information in most cases. But the –sai is not necessary. One
can just as easily find in conversation or texts examples like (from conversational
exchange, November 1991):
On the issue of direct vs. indirect speech, Everett (1986) again was wrong,
because the analysis was based on elicitation with only a couple of men and my
interpretation of their judgments was incorrect. Only the direct speech translations are
possible. This is additional data that led me to question my original analysis and to
abandon the idea of embedding as part of the analysis of Pirahã clauses.
hi xoba'axa'i'
he see well
-sibiga
15
-deductive
Moreover, -sai can appear on either clause, modulo the information structure of
the discourse:
-bai' -sibiga
-intensive -deductive
-bai' -sai
-intensive -old information
So why does the interrogative clause come first in (34) if these are not a single
sentence? Just because of the type of speech act this is. The principal speech act is a
question and the additional clause is, again, clarifying information (and clarification
clauses and postposed constituents are discussed in Everett (1986)), thus usually old
information, thus more frequently marked by –sai.
Temporal clauses
NPR then proceeds on an excursus on temporal clauses of a type we have already
seen, namely, the eyeballing approach where decontextualized sentences are pried loose
from other languages and declared to be similar to Pirahã as though this alone constituted
an argument about the analysis of Pirahã. So, for example, to NPR the 'temporal marker'
–so/-ao, discussed on page 33 of NPR, seems to be a subordinator because of
English/Indo-European bias. In fact, this marker can appear on independent clauses. So,
for example:
16
eat-continuative I you talk -want
'(You) are about finished eating/you just finished eating. I want to talk to you.'
This can also be interpreted as a conditional (e.g. 'If it rains, I won't go'), but need
not be. This arises just in case the conversation is about raining and one adds information
about their plans. But there is no evidence for subordination apart from the English
translation.
Correlatives
NPR's discussion of my analysis of correlatives (p34ff) again fails to account for
the facts. Consider one of the examples they cite (without the brackets):
'I want the hammock. You showed me that hammock, the same one.'10
The goo' here is often an interrogative. It literally means 'that there'. The second
clause in (30), as I said in the cited earlier work, would indeed most often be interpreted
as an interrogative. But not always. Further evidence on the meaning of goo' is given in
(31):
10
NPR claim that they have not found –sigiai on a 'main clause' in Pirahã. Well, here is an example for
them: Pao'ai 'aisigiai –aaga 'It is Dan, the same one.' (meaning, not someone else named Pao'ai, which is
my name in Pirahã).
17
(31) a. hi igaha'oi ogiogihi'
he with want
Before I offer the actual translation of these examples, I ask the reader to consider
what might motivate people who have never even met a Pirahã and do not even know
how to pronounce or understand a single word of the language to offer a translation of a
11
I should add a clarification about the data here. NPR cite the source of their example as Filomena
Sandalo, apparently having collected a text in 1998 by the Pirahã woman 'itaibigai about Steve Sheldon. In
fact, 'itaibigai died around 1982 and this text was collected, transcribed, and translated by Steve Sheldon in
1970 or thereabouts. Filomena Sandalo did accompany me as an undergraduate student to the Pirahãs in
1985 and again as a PhD student some years later. However, she abandoned her plans to do a PhD on
Pirahã because she was unable to learn to speak the language. All texts she collected in the field were
translated by me.
18
complicated example of this language. The actual translation of this example, since the
verb gai has a range of quotative introductory meanings, is:
'Steve talks about bananas. He will look for bananas another day.'
So there is no evidence either from the translation for extraction of any kind. And
the repetition of the word for banana in both clauses rules out extraction (to the degree
that anything can really be ruled out in a copying theory of extraction).
As for the other examples in (39), I say, as they note in the footnote that these
examples are rare. In fact, they are non-existent. By this I mean that they never occur
outside the artificial elicitation context in which they were created in 1980. They were
uttered in another one of those completely inappropriate elicitation contexts that I and
other fieldworkers have occasionally lapsed into with ill effects.
(10) a. No numerals or counting (since these are built on recursion, as per Wiese
(2003).
b. No auxiliary verbs.
c. No stacked possessors.
d. No conjunction.
e. No disjunction.
NPR curiously either fail to discuss these facts (they only discuss a & b) or they
fail to even mention that they are predicted by my account and coincidental by their
account (if they even exist by NPR's account).
19
then if a language lacks recursion in its grammar, it ought to lack a numeral system. This
is another correct prediction of my analysis that, so far as I know, no other analysis is
able to make (and this does not require any appeal to Whorf, etc. though I return to this
directly).
Recent experiments by Michael Frank, Dan Everett, Evelina Fedorenko, and Ted
Gibson have strongly confirmed the absence of numerals and counting of any kind in
Pirahã. (We are currently working on a paper to report these results.) I will therefore have
nothing to add as a response to NPR's speculations/remarks on number.
So I move to discuss NPR's discussion of Pirahã quantifiers and their fierce
'pragmatic wind'. Simply put, there are no quantifiers in Pirahã because there are no
words that ever meet the truth conditions of quantifiers. NPR lists on p37, ex (45), a
number of 'quantifiers' from Everett (1986). Yes, folks, I did think that those were
quantifiers 25 years ago. But I do not now. Why? For one thing, back then Lisa
Mathewson (2004) had not written her beautiful article on the methodology of semantic
field work and I failed to examine the truth-conditions of the words in (45). The words in
NPR's (45) are in fact translated as:
My reasoning in Everett (1986) was pretty much like NPR's: (i) these words
overlap in some contexts with English quantifiers; (ii) the best free translation, the least
exotic translation, is as quantifiers. So they must be quantifiers, right? No. Considerations
like (i) and (ii) are irrelevant for the final analysis.
The fact that Everett (2005b) no longer considers or translates these as quantifiers,
rendering the free translation of them more awkward in English, does not mean that I am
trying to 'exoticize' the language (contra the remarks cited by Wierzbicka, which I
already responded to in Everett (2005b) and the similar remarks by NPR). I would be
failing to express the richness and distinctness of Pirahã if I were to overtranslate just so
that the free translation could look less strange to a small set of linguists who have a
vested interest in finding these quantifiers in all languages (e.g. NPR and Wierzbicka).
NPR's tactic in this section is basically 'We can understand these examples better as
quantifiers so we will so analyse them.' This is eyeballing, once again, not analysis,
though it does have a long pedigree in some models of linguistics. However, as I have
said repeatedly, and as I exemplify in Everett (2005b), these words never manifest the
truth conditions of quantifiers. This is a matter that NPR and Everett (1986) fail to give
sufficient consideration to. Of course it is true, as NPR mention on page 40, that a
'pragmatic wind' (citing Lewis (1986, 164)) can alter the truth conditions of quantifiers in
some contexts. So the child who says to her mother 'But everyone is going!' probably
does not mean that the residents of Beijing and Delhi will be in attendance. She just
means lots of her friends will be there. This is to use the word every as though it meant
'many', 'most', or a 'large amount'. If this were its only use, however, then it would not
mean 'every'. All words, not just quantifiers, can be semantically altered by context, i.e by
20
a 'pragmatic wind'. Surely NPR doesn't think I am unaware of this fact? The point is that
there are no words in Pirahã that have the truth conditions of universal or existential
quantification or any other form I have been able to discover. That is, Lewis's 'pragmatic
wind' is always blowing in Pirahã. So there are no quantifiers, folks, and NPR's reasoning
doesn't alter this fact. Now I may be wrong. But that is why colleagues are going to the
field to run experiments on quantification in Pirahã. That is, by the way, the proper way
to test my claims. Not arm-chair speculation. Let us now turn to a discussion of color
terms.
Color words
The words Everett (1986) lists as colors are all phrasal descriptions, a fact I was
unaware of at the time. So translations for NPR's (49) from my PhD are in fact incorrect.
The correct translations are (Everett's (1986) translations in parentheses):
(36) a. bii'-sai (occasionally bii-si and often just bii) 'blood' (red)
b. xahoasai 'immature'
(green/blue)
c. kobiai 'see though it'
(white/clean)
d. kopai'ai 'see up to it'
e. tixoho'i' 'small (purple)
bug'
f. tioai 'shaded/out of the sun'
(dark)
"Again I would say that two factors are in play here. One I was not able to set
things up so that each person replying had not had information about what
others had said. Secondly, as I have followed Everett's later analysis on
colors, I have come to believe that his statements are in fact a more accurate
statement about colors and Pirahã." (Steve Sheldon, email to Everett March 11,
2007. Written to be cited here.)
On the other hand, it would be useful to repeat all of the Berlin & Kay color
experiments with the Pirahãs. For this reason, I have had extensive discussions with
Brent Berlin and Paul Kay and on a recent trip to Berkeley Kay gave me an entire set of
the color sides, protocol, etc. to run the experiments again. We discussed ways to control
the experiments more effectively, given Sheldon's difficulties. This will be done in a year
or less. It is true that Berlin & Kay no longer claim that all languages will have
morphologically simple color words.12
12
We ought to observe, however, though the original hypothesis that color terms should be
morphologically simple has been abandoned in favor of the reasoning cited from Kay by NPR on their page
41, this abandonment is a serious weakening of that hypothesis, an abandonment in effect of the linguistic
21
However, although colors definitely are part of our immediate experience – and
so in that sense would not violate the IEP – the naming of them is a different thing
altogether and would violate the IEP as stated in (1). There is a relatively large literature
on the linguistics, anthropology, psychology, physics, and philosophy of colors and color
naming (none of which is referenced by NPR). One particularly pertinent work is Lyons
(1995), who observes that color is 'not grammaticalised across the languages of the world
as fully or centrally as shape, size, space, time' (223). He therefore concludes that colors
are the product of language under the influence of culture. One reason for the disparity in
grammaticalization of color terms is that they require generalizations across the color
spectrum that are different from the immediate experience, phenomenology, of shape,
size, etc. This is why the IEP rules out the non-immediate experience-based naming of
colors, though not the description of them. Colors are not straightforward adjectives in
almost anyone's theory. The fact that there are no color nouns in Pirahã follows from this
but is not the primary fact, contra NPR and is neither here nor there for the IEP's
predictions regarding the lack of color words.
Pronouns
In discussing my claim that Pirahã lacks distinctions in number in its pronouns,
NPR juxtaposes some Mandarin forms alongside forms from Steve Sheldon's earlier
work on Pirahã. The forms by Sheldon are not translated correctly, however, and the
Mandarin forms are irrelevant. The use of Mandarin here is just another example of the
paratactic, eyeballing linguistics that NPR find so appealing. The 'aitiso particle that
Sheldon mistakes for a plural marker is accurately glossed in NPR's (50) from Everett
(1986) and marks a secondary discourse participant. As to their citation from Sheldon,
Sheldon's analysis confused, in my opinion, the function of topicality with number in the
gloss of 'aitiso. Sheldon offered the following comments for citation here after reading
NPR (in an email to Everett on March 21, 2007). He first quotes NPR and then offers a
comment below this:
"Everett (HAL 281) notes that Stephen Sheldon views such forms as tixaítiso as
constituting a single word, and indeed Sheldon (1988,16 fn. 1) offersthe following
pronominal paradigm for Pirahã (orthography adapted to HAL's
conventions):(51) Pronouns in Pirahã (per (1988,16 fn. 1))
SING PLURAL
1 ti tixaítiso
2 gí gíxaítiso
3 hi hixaítiso
This was my understanding at the time. Any early analysis must always subject to
modification. I have not followed closely the discussion on pronouns. I have,
however, modified many of my earlier thoughts on how Pirahã works. My 70's
analysis of the language has changed as I have followed the work of Everett. I
component of their original hypothesis. What remains is the idea that the cognition of color follows a
restricted set of patterns. I do not believe that Pirahã is a counterexample to that.
22
would be very reluctant to state emphatically today that my earlier analysis on the
pronouns is correct. My cursory look at his analysis leads me to agree with his
current views." 13
Relative Tense
Since a relative tense entails an assertion about a point in time that is not the
moment of speech (the Reichenbachian 'R' – see Everett (1993) for detailed discussion),
by (1) above, perfect tenses are not permissible in Pirahã. Everett (1993) accounts for this
by arguing that the three 'ingredients' of the calculus of temporal deixis in the Hornstein
(1993)/Reichenbach (1947) system (E(vent); R(eference Point); S(moment of speech)),
13
With regard to the present paper's data, Sheldon goes on to say the following: "I especially looked
carefully at the examples. I am always pleased to see that I understand well the examples given. I did not
find anything I felt was wrong."
23
Pirahã only manifests E and S. This eliminates all perfect tenses and follows directly
from the IEP.
Now let us turn to that aspect of Pirahã on which NPR are least qualified to opine,
but which they take up in detail nonetheless – Pirahã culture.
4. Culture
NPR's data come largely from the work of Dr. Marco Antonio Gonçalves, a
leading Brazilian anthropologist, a friend of mine, and one of the many people (see
below) that I have introduced to Pirahã studies. Before beginning this discussion, let me
give some historical background.
The Pirahã narrative about spirits and creation from Gonçalves's text, cited by
NPR on their p44 & 45 is not a Pirahã text. It is pieced together from the Pirahã's pidgin-
like Portuguese and Gonçalves's pidgin-like Pirahã (and that is Gonçalves's own
description to me of how he worked). There is no such text in the Pirahã language. All
existent Pirahã texts are on file at the University of Manchester, under the control of
Eugenie Stapert, Nigel Vincent, and Jeanette Sakel. No such text exists. And if there were
a Pirahã text on these subjects, Gonçalves would be the first to admit that he would need
help in translating it. In this text there are certainly many elements that are Pirahã and
many that are not. Next to none of this is found in Pirahã texts, though what Gonçalves
says about the different kinds of spirits I have observed as different Pirahãs have become
'possessed' (and this is more or less how they describe it) and said that they are one or the
other of the spirits Gonçalves describes, with many of the very properties he attributes to
them in his writings. But there are no counterexamples in any of this to the IEP. This is
because, as I have said many times, the Pirahãs actually see these spirits and they see the
on-going creation too! For example, one Pirahã explanation for illness is when a spirit
has brought an object from their hole under the ground or their hole in the sky and placed
it on a Pirahã path. A Pirahã will inadvertently step on this and become ill. The Pirahã
can show you these leaves, the holes, etc. These are to them real experiences and seeing
spirits to them is as real as seeing macaws. There is no violation of the IEP in any of this.
24
that, at least for the subjects she has worked with so far, their 'Portuguese' is Pirahã
grammar with a small lexicon of Portuguese. Her on-going research will undoubtedly
force me to revise some of my views on this matter, but there are no Pirahãs who speak
more than a little bit of Portuguese, using Pirahã grammar.
There is an interesting anecdote about the Pirahã's monolingualness. In February
1985, the Brazilian National Indian Foundation (FUNAI) contacted me while I was a
Visiting Scholar at MIT and asked me if I would be able to join an expedition to identify
the lands used traditionally by the Pirahãs, in order to eventually demarcate a reservation
for them. FUNAI paid for my travel from the US to the Pirahãs in order to serve as
interpreter, because the Pirahã are monolingual and I was one of only a handful of
people who can speak Pirahã (the others being Keren Everett, Steve Sheldon, and Arlo
Heinrichs) and the only one known to FUNAI. When I arrived to join the FUNAI team at
the mouth of the Maici, they had been attempting to communicate with the Pirahãs for
three days, without success. They said, once I arrived and started talking to the Pirahãs,
"OK, now we understand why we had to wait for a gringo to come help us."
25
2001 (with Sarah Grey Thomason) 'Pronoun Borrowing', Proceedings of the Berkeley Linguistics Society,
Volume 27, invited plenary address.
1996 Why There Are No Clitics, Summer Institute of Linguistics and the University of Texas at Arlington
Series in Linguistics, Dallas, TX (188pp).
1993. 'Sapir, Reichenbach, and the Syntax of Tense in Pirahã', The Journal of Pragmatics & Cognition,
1:1, pp 89-124.
1992 A Lingua Pirahã e a Teoria da Sintaxe, Editora da UNICAMP (400pp).
1988 'On Metrical Constituent Structure in Pirahã Phonology,' Natural Language and Linguistic Theory
6, pp 207-246.
1987 'Pirahã Clitic Doubling,' Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 5, pp 245-276.
1987 'O Diálogo e a Seleção de Dados para uma Gramática,' In: Marcelo Dascal (ed.) Encontro
Internacional de Filosofia da Linguagem, Cadernos de Estudos Lingüísticos, 11, 21-38.
UNICAMP.
1986 'Pirahã,' In: Desmond Derbyshire and Geoffrey Pullum (eds.) Handbook of Amazonian Languages
I, Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp200-326.
1986 'Pirahã Clitic Doubling and the Parametrization of Nominal Clitics,' In:Naoki Fukui, Tova Rapoport,
and Elizabeth Sagey, (eds.) MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 8, Department of Linguistics and
Philosophy, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 85-127.
1986 'Ternary Constituents in Pirahã Phonology,' In: Desmond Derbyshire (ed.) Workpapers of the
Summer Institute of Linguistics - University of North Dakota 30, SIL, Dallas, pp 13-41.
1985 'Dialogue and the Selection of Data for a Grammar,' In: Marcelo Dascal (ed.) Dialogue: An
Interdisciplinary Approach, John Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp 251-267.
1985 'The Parametrization of Nominal Clitics in Universal Grammar,' Glow Newsletter, February, pp 36-
38.
1985 'Syllable Weight, Sloppy Phonemes, and Channels in Pirahã Discourse,' In: Mary Niepokuj et.al.
(eds.) Proceedings of the Berkeley Linguistics Society 11, pp 408-416.
1984 (with Keren Everett), 'Syllable Onsets and Stress Placement in Pirahã,' In: Michael Wescoat, et. al.
(eds.) Proceedings of the West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics III, Stanford Linguistics
Association, Stanford University, pp 105-117.
1984 'Sociophonetic Restrictions on Subphonemic Elements in Pirahã,' In: A. Cohen and M.P.R. van den
Broecke (eds.) Proceedings of the X International Congress of Phonetic Sciences, Foris,
Dordrecht, pp606-610.
1985 O Desenvolvimento da Teoria Chomskyana: Uma Discussão Epistemológica, RLEE, Lima, Peru.
1984 (with Keren Everett), 'On the relevance of Syllable Onsets to Stress Placement,' Linguistic Inquiry
15, pp 705-711.
1983. A Lingua Pirahã e a Teoria da Sintaxe, ScD Thesis, Universidade Estadual de Campinas.
1982 'Phonetic Rarities in Pirahã,' Journal of the International Phonetics Association, December, pp 94-
96.
1979. Aspectos da Fonologia do Pirahã, unpublished MA Thesis, Universidade Estadual de Campinas.
14
As though one paper by some armchair linguists who wouldn't be able to pronounce a single Pirahã word
is the place to begin.
26
Students: 2 UNICAMP undergraduates (of which Filomena Sandalo was one – all of her
data come from me or were translated by me); 5 UNICAMP graduate students; 3
University of Pittsburgh graduate students, and the following researchers with specific
research agendas:
Researchers:
Marcelo Dascal: Professor of Philosophy and Dean of Humanities, Tel Aviv University.
Dascal went to collect data on Pirahã metaphors and their cosmology.
Peter Gordon: Professor of Psychology, University of Pittsburgh (now at Columbia
University), went to test my claim that the Pirahã did not count. His results confirming
my claims were published in Science
Peter Ladefoged: Professor of Phonetics, UCLA (deceased) – went to check my claims
about Pirahã stress and segmental phonetics.
Tecumseh Fitch: Professor in the School of Psychology, St. Andrews University,
Scotland – went to conduct research on Pirahã recognition of finite-state vs. non-finite
state grammars.
Jeanette Sakel, Research Associate, University of Manchester – has begun on-going
investigations into the Pirahãs' use of Portuguese and general claims about the Pirahã
grammar, e.g. whether or not it has recursion.
Eugenie Stapert, PhD student, University of Manchester – has begun field research for a
dissertation on the role of recursion in Pirahã grammar.
Edward Gibson, Professor in Brain and Cognitive Sciences, Massachusetts Institute of
Technology – has begun research on Pirahã recursion, counting, memory, and a range of
other psycholinguistic tasks.
Michael Frank, PhD student, Massachusetts Institute of Technology – has begun
research on Pirahã recursion, counting, memory, and a range of other psycholinguistic
tasks.
Evelina Fedorenko, PhD student, Massachusetts Institute of Technology – has begun
research on Pirahã recursion, counting, memory, and a range of other psycholinguistic
tasks. (Did not go to the Pirahãs but contributed several experiments for our research
team and is currently co-authoring a paper on Pirahã.)
Leo Wetzels, Professor, Free University of Amsterdam – went to consider possible work
on Pirahã phonology.
MarcoAntonio Gonçalves, Anthropologist (as per discussion above).
27
language, i.e. the human brain interacting with the environment. This idea is further
developed in Everett (in preparation b) and also characterizes various productive research
programs, e.g. the work of Michael Tomasello at the Max Planck Institute for
Evolutionary Anthropology in Leipzig, Germany, among many other research programs.
There are alternatives to Universal Grammar and the fact that NPR insists on
characterizing the issue as though there were no alternatives, although typical, is either
ignorant or purposely misleading.
They come by this naturally, however, since the originator of the idea of
Universal Grammar insists on characterizing it in a similar fashion. In what follows I
summarize some recent emails from Chomsky. (If anyone would like to see these emails,
just contact me.)
Chomsky says in an email to me on April 07, 2006, that every linguist has at least
tacitly supposed some version of UG, no matter how much they deny it. Yet in the same
message, Chomsky denies that it is possible to define UG precisely.
But this is little more than sloganeering. The idea that every linguist presupposes
UG seriously confuses the general human capacity for language, our brains (which every
linguist does presuppose), with a hypothesized specific human capacity for language
mentioned in the first part of the quote (which perhaps a minority of linguists presuppose
but which has never been shown to have any similarities in organization or dedication
similar to the visual system). But NPR doesn't even get that part about UG right.
Moreover, even if we were to suppose something as baroque as a Universal Grammar, it
makes no predictions that I can see. And Chomsky agrees with me on this in further
emails of April 2006, in which he argues that UG is a field of study, not a hypothesis. He
further argues that the only alternative to UG would equate his granddaughter with a
kitten. Chomsky believes that denying UG loses the ability to explain the banal fact that
his granddaughter learns language but kittens do not.
Well, Chomsky and I agree on one thing: UG makes no predictions. Chomsky's
tack, i.e. to characterize UG as a field of study, e.g. biology, is ludicrous. But the really
crucial sleight of hand in the quote from Chomsky is to think that if I do not believe in a
language-specific genetic endowment, I must believe that his granddaughter is a kitten.
That is to take the utterly predictable, wearying, and rhetorically fudging tactic that is
typical of Chomsky and his followers that there just is no alternative to his proposals.
There are alternatives. One is quite obvious: kitty cats don't have human brains. Whatever
the general properties are that distinguish human brains from those of other species, those
might well be investigated before coming to the conclusion that there is a module in the
brain or a language organ dedicated strictly to language. For more on this see Everett
(2005a, 2006) a still unanswered criticism of one proposal for the notion of language
organ. Part of any serious exploration of alternatives to UG is to look at a wider range of
possibilities than UG predicts, e.g. the fact that languages might lack intertranslatability,
have different degrees of expressive power, lack this or that 'crucial' component of
language, or that culture impinges on the form of the entire grammar to a degree not
predicted by UG. And that is what Everett (2005b) tries to do. It might be wrong. But it is
not misguided or in need of a remedial course in what UG is.
In other words, they were committed, long before Everett (2005b) came on the
scene, to the idea that all languages are, to paraphrase the authors, 'just languages', i.e.
that there is no significant grammatical deviation from whatever the current set of
28
principles and parameters are for Generative Grammar. Their theoretical orientation is
thus very clear and the tack that they take in all of their writings, this one included, is to
defend a vested interest in the Chomskyan framework. If I, Sapir, Boas, or anyone of a
large number of other linguists in the American descriptivist tradition are correct,
however, languages emerge from a complex symbiosis of culture, general cognitive
constraints, and the general properties of communications systems. In this tradition, there
is no need for a Universal Grammar, in fact, it makes the wrong predictions, and the
variation and relationships between languages and cultures are much richer and more
diverse than Chomskyan theory contemplates. Cultures are free to shape languages
subject to the limits of general cognition and communication, in radically different ways.
Even some modern syntacticians in the theoretical tradition have begun to call for a move
away from the largely deductive approach to grammar represented by Chomsky and the
authors of 'Pirahã Exceptionality'. One important and very convincing set of proposals is
found in Culicover and Jackendoff (2005), which NPR do not mention.
For example, if I am correct that Pirahã lacks recursion and that this is a result of
culture, the one could make a case that the entire Chomskyan research program is largely
in error. This is the case that I in fact do make in Everett (in preparation b).
In developing my views I have been strongly influenced by American Pragmatism
and the Pragmatism-influenced work of Franz Boas. Boas believed, among other things,
that 'cultural phenomena are of such complexity that it seems to me doubtful whether
valid cultural laws can be found.' I am inclined to agree. This view has always been
controversial, though, because it violates the ideas that many people have of what science
should be about, i.e. generalizations. So, for example, one critic of Boas, Leslie White,
(White 1943, 355) claimed that Boas's philosophy was a 'philosophy of planless hodge-
podge-ism'.
Boas, trained in physics, was aware of the epistemological significance of what he
was doing, however. He became convinced nevertheless that what we need in
anthropology and linguistics is to abandon the search for laws, at least as the principal
goal of our fields. He called the law-seeking approach to knowledge the 'nomothetic'
view. For Anthropology and Linguistics he advocated instead the 'idiographic' (historical-
narrative) approach to linguistics and culture. To tell contextualized stories of how
languages and cultures fit together, for example, realizing that what we say about one
language may not fix the next one we look at, is idiographic. This is also in keeping with
the important philosophical work of Richard Rorty in contemporary intellectual life.
How can we explain the fact that if Everett (2005b) is correct, Pirahã seems to be
so rare or, to use NPR's words, so 'exceptional'? I believe that the answer is provided by
Benjamin Lee Whorf. The exceptionality is a problem of language, the linguist's
theoretical language. Linguists learn words from theories that lead them to categorize
their world in a certain way. They go to their research armed with these categories. They
are prepared to find and fit things into these categories and also to overlook things that do
not fit into these categories. This is the way of all science, in fact. Discoveries and
breakthroughs emerge from the researcher's ability to invent new categories and
unshackle themselves from the categories prevalent in their field. Not that we should
avoid categories or theories, etc. Not at all. We ought just not to take them too seriously.
They are not Truth. The concept of Truth does not do anything useful for us, at least not
29
according to the American Pragmatists (see also Everett (in preparation b) for the initial
statement of a Pragmatist or Jamesian Linguistics).
9. Conclusion
The claims made by Everett (2005b) most certainly need to be tested and retested
by additional field research. As is clear from the above list of scholars and students that I
have taken to the Pirahãs, there have been and continue to be serious efforts to do this
testing. One can only wonder why, if NPR are so interested in Pirahã, they have made no
effort to do field research there of their own. Rather, they have limited their efforts to
bibliographic research. Moreover, their research also shows (especially clear in their
erroneous analysis of German) an overreliance on printed sources (a type of logocentrism
and penchant for decontextualized examples that is so reminiscent of the notion of divine
inspiration of texts and proof texts common to many fundamentalist religions. In fact, in
Everett (in preparation b) I explicitly compare Chomskyan Generative Grammar to a type
of fundamentalism across several parameters).
This raises the question of how any discipline could produce the kind of
eyeballing, armchair linguistics that NPR engage in. The answer seems to go back to how
linguistics as a discipline has been professionalized since the early 20th century. It has
moved out of language and anthropology departments, where I believe it belongs, into
isolated departments of linguistics where language is pursued less as a natural
phenomenon and more as a mathematical, logical system, at least in some departments,
producing a methodology that gives more attention to rigor in talking about data than to
rigor in gathering data, relying more on subjective intuitions of speakers. John Searle
(2006) notes a similar problem in modern philosophy of language. The methodology of
Linguistics has arguably fallen behind that of standard social science research in many
respects. So, for example, NPR fails to propose experiments or research to test my
claims, but merely uses the library. This can only lead to the kind of pseudo-research that
we see in this paper. On the other hand, this does not explain the more egregious attacks
on my character at the end of NPR. I am only going to say about this that NPR has made
an enormous effort to discredit my linguistics research and, for some reason, to also
insinuate – again from contrived and decontextualized examples, that I have a prejudiced
view of the Pirahãs. This is a sociological problem that I take up in greater detail in
Everett (in preparation b).
30
References
Culicover, Peter and Ray Jackendoff 2006. Simpler Syntax, Oxford University Press.
Cristofaro, Sonia. 2003. Subordination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Everett, Caleb. 2006. Patterns in Karitiana: Articulation, Perception, and Grammar,
unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, Rice University.
Everett, Daniel L. In preparation a, Linguistic Field Work: A Student's Guide, under
contract to Cambridge University Press.
Everett, Daniel L. In preparation b Don't Sleep, There are Snakes: Lessons on Life,
Language, and Thought from the Amazon (Pantheon Books (hardback),
Vintage Books (paperback), after Summer 2007)
Everett, Daniel L. 2006a. – 'Discussion On Cultural Constraints on Pirahã Grammar',
other discussants were Valentina Bambini, Claudio Gentili, and Pietro Pietrini
Current Anthropology: 47:1, 143-145.
Everett, Daniel L. 2006b. 'Reply to Anderson and Lightfoot', Journal of Linguistics,
July (response to a reply by S. Anderson and D. Lightfoot, to item (2) of this
section).
Everett, Daniel L. 2005a. 'Biology and language: a consideration of alternatives', Journal
of Linguistics, 41, 157-175.
Everett, Daniel L. 2004. 'Coherent Fieldwork', In: Piet van Sterkenberg, ed., Linguistics
Today, John Benjamins Publishing, 141-162.
Everett, Daniel L. 2001 ‘Monolingual Field Research’, In: Paul Newman & Martha
Ratliff (eds.), Fieldlinguistics, Cambridge University Press, pp166-188.
Everett, Daniel L. 1985 'The Parametrization of Nominal Clitics in Universal Grammar,'
Glow Newsletter, February, pp 36-38.
Everett, Daniel L. 1981 'Tom, Acento e Silabação,' Anais V do GEL, Araraquara, São
Paulo, pp105-115.
Everett, Daniel L. 2002 'From Threatened Languages to Threatened Lives',
commissioned article for the site, Yourdictionary.com
(http://www.yourdictionary.com/elr/everett.html)
Grace, George W. 1987. The Linguistic Construction of Reality, London, New York,
and Sydney: Croom Helm. [ap]
Hauser, Mark, Noam Chomsky, and W. Tecumseh Fitch. 2002. 'The faculty of language:
What is it, Who has it, How did it evolve', Science, 1569-1579.
Hornstein, Norbert. 1993. As Time Goes By: Tense and Universal Grammar, MIT
Press, Cambridge.
Koptjevskaja-Tamm, Maria. 1993. Nominalizations. London: Routledge.
Lyons J. A. 1995. 'Colour in language'. In Colour: Art and Science. T. Lamb and J.
Bourriau (eds) Cambridge University Press.
Matthewson, Lisa. 2004. 'On the Methodology of Semantic Fieldwork', International
Journal of American Linguistics 70:4, 369-415.
Nevins, Andrew, David Pesetsky, and Cilene Rodrigues. 2007. 'Pirahã Exceptionality:
A Reassessment', available at: http://ling.auf.net/lingBuzz
Reichenbach, Hans. 1947. Elements of symbolic logic. McMillan, New York.
Searle, John. 2006. 'What is Language: Some Preliminary Remarks?' unpublished ms,
University of California, Berkeley, Department of Philosophy.
VanValin, Robert and Daniel L. Everett. In preparation. 'Information Structure in Pirahã'.
31
White, Leslie. 1943. 'Energy and the Evolution of Culture, American Anthropologist,
45:335-356.
Wiese, Heike. 2003. Numbers, Language, and the Human Mind, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
32