5) Structural Properties of Utility Functions
5) Structural Properties of Utility Functions
Outline:
• Desirability: Monotonicity, Non-satiation
• Convexity, Concavity, Quasi-concavity
• Common Utility Functions and preferences
1
From
From Last
Last Class
Class
Definition
The utility function u : X ! R represents the binary relation % on X if
x % y , u(x) ≥ u(y ).
Theorem (Debreu)
Suppose X ⊆ Rn . A binary relation % on X is complete, transitive, and continuous
if and only if it admits a continuous utility representation u : X ! R.
NOTATION:
From now on, assume X = R n .
If xi ≥ yi for each i, we write x ≥ y . 2
Monotonicity
Monotonicity says more is better.
Definitions
A preference relation % is weakly monotone if x ≥ y implies x % y .
A preference relation % is strictly monotone if x ≥ y and x 6= y imply x ≻ y .
Question
What does monotonicity imply for the utility function representing %?
Example
Suppose % is the preference relation on R2 defined by
x %y if and only if x1 ≥ y1
% is weakly monotone, because if x ≥ y , then x1 ≥ y1 .
It is not strictly monotone, because
(1, 1) ≥ (1, 0) and (1, 1) 6= (1, 0)
but
not [(1, 1) ≻ (1, 0)]
since (1, 0) % (1, 1).
4
Strict
StrictMonotonicity:
Monotonicity: An
An Example
Example
5
Monotonicity
Monotonicity and
and Utility
Utility Functions
Functions
Definitions
A function f : Rn ! R is
nondecreasing if x ≥ y implies f (x) ≥ f (y );
strictly increasing if x ≥ y and x 6= y imply f (x) > f (y ).
Proposition
If u represents %, then:
1 % is weakly monotone if and only if u is nondecreasing;
2 % is strictly monotone if and only if u is strictly increasing.
For any consumption bundle, there is always a nearby bundle that is strictly
preferred to it.
Definition
A utility function u : X ! R is locally nonsatiated if it represents a locally
nonsatiated preference relation %; that is, if for every x 2 X and " > 0, there exists
some y such that ky − xk < " and u(y ) > u(x).
Proof.
Let x be given, and let y = x + n" e, where e = (1, ..., 1).
Then we have yi > xi for each i.
Strict monotonicity implies that y ≻ x.
Note that v
u n % &
uX " 2 "
||y − x|| = t = p < ".
n n
i =1
9
Indifference sets
Note: strict
monotonicity implies
that indifference curves
are negatively sloped.
10
oof. By Debreu’s Theorem there continuous u(x) that represents %. Almost by
exists a Preferences
Convex
finition we have Convex Preferences
Definitions C% (A) = arg max u(x)
A preference relation % is x2A
✓⇢ ◆
convex if =u 1 max u(x) .
x2A
x % y ) αx + (1 − α)y % y for all α 2 (0, 1)
en we are maximizing
strictly convex aifcontinuous function on a nonempty compact set. By the Extreme
lue Theorem, the set of maximizers is nonempty. Compactness (which, in Rn , is equiv-
x % y and x 6= y ) αx + (1 − α)y ≻ y for all α 2 (0, 1)
nt to closedness and boundedness) follows from the boundedness of A, the closedness of
e singleton set {maxx2A u(x)}, and the continuity of u.
Convexity says that taking convex combinations cannot make the decision
2 Structural properties of utility
maker worse o§.
Strict convexity says that taking convex combinations makes the decision
maker
re are some better o§.that were not really covered in lecture. Throughout this part we
definitions
Definition:
e assuming = Rn . Recall
thatAXpreference relation is convex
the (partial) if for
vector every bundle
ordering Rn , x y if
x, itsinupper
convention
Question
ycounter
i for all set
i = is
{1,convex.
2, ..., n}.
What does convexity imply for the utility function representing %?
Definition:
efinition 2.16. C ✓ X is convex if, 8 x, y 2 C and ↵ 2 [0, 1], we have ↵x + (1 ↵)y 2 C.
Geometrically, this means that any line segment whose two end points are in
C lies completely
ometrically, this means inside
that C.
any line segment whose two endpoints are in C lies com- 11
Convex Preferences
12
Strict convexity says that taking convex combinations makes the decision
Convex Preferences: An Example
maker better o§.
αx + (1− α) y ~ z
14
Convex Preferences
What does convexity of preferences
mean?
1. Taste for diversification: an
individual with convex preferences
prefers the convex combination of x
and y rather than x or y.
Quasiconcavity
17
Convexity and Quasiconcave Utility Functions
Convexity and Quasiconcave Utility Functions
Convexity is equivalent to quasi concavity of the corresponding utility function.
Proposition
If u represents %, then:
1 % is convex if and only if u is quasiconcave;
2 % is strictly convex if and only if u is strictly quasiconcave.
18
QuasiconcaveUtility
Quasiconcave Utility and
and Convex
Convex upper
UpperContours
Contours
Proposition
Let % be a preference relation on X represened by u : X ! R. Then, the upper
contour set is a convex subset of X if and only if u is quasiconcave.
Proof.
Suppose that u is quasiconcave.
Fix z 2 X , and take any x , y 2% (z).
Wlog, assume u(x ) ≥ u(y ), so that u(x ) ≥ u(y ) ≥ u(z), and let α 2 [0, 1].
By quasiconcavity of u,
u(z) ≤ u(y ) ≤ u(αx + (1 − α)y ),
so αx + (1 − α)y % z.
Hence αx + (1 − α)y belongs to % (z), proving it is convex.
Now suppose that % (z) is convex for all z 2 X .
Let x , y 2 X and α 2 [0, 1], and suppose u(x ) ≥ u(y ).
Then x % y and y % y , and so x and y are both in % (y ).
Since % (y ) is convex (by assumption), then αx + (1 − α)y % y .
Since u represents %,
u(αx + (1 − α)y ) ≥ u(y )
19
Thus u is quasiconcave.
Convexity
Convexity and
and Induced Choices
Induced Choices
Proposition
If % is convex, then C% (A) is convex for all convex A.
If % is strictly convex, then C% (A) has at most one element for any convex A.
Proof.
Let A be convex and x, y 2 C% (A).
By definition of C% (A), x % y .
Since A is convex: αx + (1 − α)y 2 A for any α 2 [0, 1].
Convexity of % implies αx + (1 − α)y % y .
By definition of C% , y % z for all z 2 A.
Using transitivity, αx + (1 − α)y % y % z for all z 2 A.
Hence, αx + (1 − α)y 2 C% (A) by definition of induced choice rule.
Therefore, C% (A) is convex for any convex A.
! !
Now suppose there exists a convex A for which C% (A)! ≥ 2.
!
Then there exist x , y 2 C% (A) with x 6= y .
Since x % y and x 6= y , strict convexity implies αx + (1 − α)y ≻ y for all
α 2 (0, 1).
Since A is convex, αx + (1 − α)y 2 A, but this contradicts the fact that
20
y 2 C% (A).
Quasiconcave Utility
Bundles x and y lie on the same indifference curve (IC), so u(x) = u(y).
For the strictly convex IC’s, u(.) For the linear IC’s, u(.) satisfies
satisfies strict quasiconcavity quasiconcavity but not strictly.
21
Relationship btw quasiconcavity and concavity
Concavity ⇒ Quasiconcavity
Quasiconcavity ¬⇒ concavity
( ) ( )
f αx + (1− α) y ≥ αf (x) + (1− α) f ( y) ≥ min{ f (x), f ( y)} for any α ∈ 0,1
22
Quasiconcavity
• A concave u(.) exhibits diminishing marginal utility
• That is, for an increase in the consumption bundle, the increase in
utility is smaller as we move away from the origin.
• A convex u(.) exhibits increasing marginal utility
• That is, for an increase in the consumption bundle, the increase in
utility is largeras we move away from the origin.
Concave and quasiconcave u(.) (3D) Convex but quasiconcave u(.) (3D)
23
Quasiconcavity
6 6
4 4
• Utility function v(x1 , x2 ) = x1 x2 is a strictly increasing transformation of
1 1
4 4
u(x1 , x2 ) = x1 x2
25
Common Utility Functions
• Marginal Utilities: ∂u ∂u
>0 >0
∂x1 ∂x2
αAx1α−1 x2β αx2
• A diminishing MRS: MRS1,2 = = decreasing in x1.
βAx1 x2
α β−1
βx1
• Hence, IC’s become flatter as x1 increases.
26
Common Utility Functions
Perfect Substitutes
• Two goods: x1 and x2,
u(x1 , x2 ) = Ax1 + Bx2
where A, B > 0.
• Characterized by constant MRS, since marginal utilities are also
constant
∂u ∂u A
=A =B MRS1,2 =
∂x1 ∂x2 B
• Examples:
• v(x1) = a lnx1
• v(x1) = ax1α, a>0 and
α ≠ 1.
30
Common Utility Functions
• For u(x1 , x2 ) = v(x1 ) + bx2 , the marginal utilities are
∂u ∂v ∂u
= =b
∂x1 ∂x1 ∂x2
which implies ∂v
∂x1
MRS1,2 =
b
31
Quasi-linear Utility
Quasi-linear Utility
Definition
The function u : Rn ! R is quasi-linear if there exists a function v : Rn−1 ! R
such that u(x, m) = v (x) + m.
1 Given two bundles with identical goods, the consumer always prefers the one
with more money.
2 Adding (or subtracting) the same monetary amount does not chage rankings.
3 Monetary transfers can always be used to achieve indi§erence.
Proof:
Proof. part of HW4 32
Proof.
Let v (x) + m and v 0 (x) + m both represent %.
Given any x0 2 Rn−1 , for all x 2 Rn−1 there exists nx such that
(x, 0) ∼ (x0 , nx ). (by (2) and (3) of the previous Proposition.)
Since the utility functions both represent % we have
v (x) + 0 = v (x0 ) + nx and v 0 (x) + 0 = v 0 (x0 ) + nx
Thus nx = v 0 (x) − v 0 (x0 ). Therefore
v (x) = v (x0 ) + v 0 (x) − v 0 (x0 )
| {z }
=n x
Definition
The preference relation % on X is homothetic if for all x, y 2 X ,
x ∼ y ) αx ∼ αy for each α > 0
Proposition
The continuous preference relation % on Rn is homothetic if and only if it is
represented by a utility function that is homogeneous of degree 1.
Proof:
Proof. part of HW4
Question 1d. Problem Set 3, due next Monday.
34