Timothy Pawl - The Incarnation (Cambridge Elements)
Timothy Pawl - The Incarnation (Cambridge Elements)
The Incarnation
The Incarnation
to it.
Timothy J. Pawl
all the central topics in the philosophy of Birmingham
religion. It offers balanced, comprehensive
coverage of multiple perspectives in the
philosophy of religion. Contributors to the
series are cutting-edge researchers who
approach central issues in the philosophy
of religion. Each provides a reliable
resource for academic readers and
develops new ideas and arguments from a
unique viewpoint.
Cover image: Eerik/ iStock / Getty Images Plus Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to ISSN 2399-5165Core
the Cambridge (online)
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341 ISSN 2515-9763 (print)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
Elements in the Philosophy of Religion
edited by
Yujin Nagasawa
University of Birmingham
THE INCARNATION
Timothy J. Pawl
University of St. Thomas
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
University Printing House, Cambridge CB2 8BS, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
314–321, 3rd Floor, Plot 3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre,
New Delhi – 110025, India
79 Anson Road, #06–04/06, Singapore 079906
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781108457521
DOI: 10.1017/9781108558341
© Timothy J. Pawl 2020
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without the written
permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published 2020
Nihil Obstat Imprimatur
Reverend George Welzbacher The Most Reverend Bernard Hebda
Censor Librorum Archbishop of Saint Paul and Minneapolis
November 5, 2019 November 5, 2019
The Nihil Obstat and Imprimatur are official declarations that a book is free of doctrinal
error. No implication is contained therein that those who have granted the Nihil
Obstat and Imprimatur agree with the content, opinions, or statements expressed. Nor
do they assume any legal responsibility associated with publication.
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
ISBN 978-1-108-45752-1 Paperback
ISSN 2399-5165 (online)
ISSN 2515-9763 (print)
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of
URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication
and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain,
accurate or appropriate.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation
DOI: 10.1017/9781108558341
First published online: September 2020
Timothy J. Pawl
University of St. Thomas
Author for correspondence: Timothy J. Pawl, timpawl@stthomas.edu
Abstract: The doctrine of the Incarnation, that Jesus Christ was both truly
God and truly human, is the foundation and cornerstone of traditional
Christian theism. And yet this traditional teaching appears to verge on
incoherence. How can one person be both God, having all the
perfections of divinity, and human, having all the limitations of
humanity? This is the fundamental philosophical problem of the
Incarnation. Perhaps a solution is found in an analysis of what the
traditional teaching meant by person, divinity, and humanity, or in
understanding how divinity and humanity were united in a single
person. This Element presents that traditional teaching, then returns to
the incoherence problem to showcase various solutions offered to it.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
Contents
1 Introduction 1
2 The Person 5
8 Conclusion 54
References 55
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 1
1 Introduction
The doctrine of the Incarnation is the teaching that Jesus Christ, the human
crucified under Pontius Pilate, was truly God, one person of the Blessed Trinity.
That doctrine, affirmed by the orthodox statements of faith from the early church
through the later Catholic, Orthodox, and Protestant doctrinal statements, teaches
that this person, while truly God, became truly human, a human like other humans
in all ways except sin, for the sake of saving humans from their sins and bringing
them to perfect union with God. This doctrine is a fundamental part of any
traditional Christian teaching – if it is false, so is traditional Christianity.
While we may have become accustomed to it, the doctrine of the Incarnation
is a shocking claim. How could God become human? How could one person be
two seemingly incompatible types of things at the same time? If God is
conceptualized in the traditional sense as immutable, impassible, and simple,
how could such a person become changeable, affectable, and complex, as all
humans are? And why? Why would God do such a thing as to become human?
1.1 Methodology
The Incarnation has been analyzed from multiple perspectives. For instance, do
the Christian Scriptures imply that Jesus is true God, one in being with the
Father?1 Does the historical record give justification for belief in the existence
of the flesh-and-blood human named “Jesus,” son of Mary? Do the early
theologians affirm the doctrine? And so on. All of these scriptural and historical
questions are worthy of analysis. This short Element, situated as it is in a series
on the philosophy of religion, does not address these questions. Rather, it
focuses on the philosophical questions surrounding the doctrine. Such philo-
sophical analysis no doubt assumes some findings of these other methods of
assessment. For instance, it assumes, for the sake of argument, that the human,
Jesus, did exist.2 But it does not and could not, given length constraints,
responsibly enter into the other discussions.
While this Element focuses exclusively on the philosophical questions con-
cerning the Incarnation, its work cannot be done in a historical vacuum. The
doctrine of the Incarnation was formulated in a series of ecumenical councils –
the context of the statements of those councils must be taken into account to
understand the meaning they had for those speakers. This Element makes
1
The biblical justification for the doctrine of the Incarnation is vitally important. This Element is
not the place to enter into that vast literature. It is impossible to provide a brief set of paradigmatic
references to the ocean of literature on the biblical case for the doctrine of the Incarnation.
I suggest the reader start with Bird et al. (2014), Loke (2019), and Tilling (2015) and follow the
footnotes into the wider literature.
2
For scholarship on the historical case for the existence of Jesus, see Ehrman (2013).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
2 Philosophy of Religion
3
For helpful reflection on the concepts of “orthodoxy” and “heresy,” see Stump (1999).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 3
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
4 Philosophy of Religion
4
This Element focuses on the metaphysics of the Incarnation. Those interested in the atoning work
of the Incarnation should see Stump (2019) and, in this same Elements series, Craig (2018). For
discussion of epistemic questions concerning the acceptance of doctrine, including the
Incarnation, see McNabb (2018) from this same Elements series.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 5
2 The Person
The traditional doctrine of the Trinity teaches both that there is only one God
and that there are three divine persons: the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit.
Only one of these three persons, the Son, became incarnate. This Element
focuses exclusively on the Second Person of the Trinity, the one who, according
to Scripture and council, became human.
The focus on this person should begin at the outset with a discussion con-
cerning the term “person.” Once the traditional meaning of that term is clarified,
I discuss the terms used to name that person, as confusion on those terms can
spell havoc for our conceptual clarity in these discussions.
What, though, is meant by these terms, “hypostasis” and “person,” such that
Christ counts as exactly one hypostasis and exactly one person?
Elsewhere (Pawl 2016d, 32), I have followed the work of Marilyn McCord
Adams (2005, 37) and Alfred Freddoso (1986, 49) in analyzing the term “hypos-
tasis” (in the Latin translation, “supposit”), following the Medievals, to mean:
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
6 Philosophy of Religion
The first clause of the right side of the biconditional is intended to preclude parts of
supposits from being supposits themselves – my hand is not itself a supposit, to use
Aquinas’s example (ST III q.16 a.12 ad.2).5 Wholes, not parts of wholes, are
supposits. The second clause is included for technical Trinitarian reasons. In
brief, the question arose whether the divine nature itself is a hypostasis, in addition
to the three divine persons. The answer had to be “no” for traditional Christianity,
since there are only three, not four, persons. This second clause is meant to
safeguard that “no” answer. To be communicable by identity is for the very same
thing to be both had by one thing and given to another without the former ceasing to
have it. Things that are communicable in such a manner aren’t themselves suppo-
sits. The third clause is meant to preclude anything accidental from counting as
a hypostasis. This was a worry, since some views of the Eucharist claim that
accidental forms could exist without inhering in substances.6 Such non-inhering
accidents are not supposits in their own right. The fourth is most relevant to our
purposes. The Medievals intended the notion of being “sustained” here to preclude
the human nature of Christ, which is sustained by the person, from itself counting as
a hypostasis.7 That human nature exists in the Word, depending on the Word for its
existence. Things that depend upon others in the way that the human nature
depends upon the person are not supposits in their own right.8 One can find similar
understandings of hypostasis throughout the Christian tradition.9
With this notion of hypostasis in hand, forming a notion of personhood is an
easy matter. A person, on the traditional understanding of the term, is
a hypostasis that has a rational nature.10 All supposits have some nature or
other. Dogs have their own natures, slugs have their own, humans have their
5
This citation ought to be read: Aquinas’s Summa Theologica, third part, question 16, article 12,
response to objection 2.
6
For discussion of this point, see Pawl (2012).
7
See also de Aldama and Solano (2014, 42–53) on this point.
8
It is true that, in another sense, everything created is sustained in existence by God on the
traditional Christian view. That is a different sense of the term “sustained.” The Medievals were
not saying that nothing created is a supposit.
9
See, for instance, Carlson (2012, 129, 259), Geddes (1911), Gorman (2000b; 2017, chap. 1),
John of Damascus (1958, 20, 56), Pohle (1911, 222), Rebenich (2002, 73), Salano and de
Aldama (2014, 42–43), and Tanner (2001, 32).
10
To see other discussions of this traditional conception of “person”, see Adams (2005, 23–24),
Aquinas (2012, 13), Carlson (2012, 204), Cupitt (1977, 135), Ferrier (1962, 81), Flint (2012,
189), Geddes (1911), Gorman (2011, 430), Lonergan (2016, 387–389), Pawl (2016d, 32–33;
2019b, 22), Pohle (1911, 224), Sturch (1991, 269–274), Turcescu (2005), Twombly (2015,
57–60), Wesche (1997, 95, 126), and C.J.F. Williams (1968, 517).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 7
own, etc. But only some of those natures are rational. And so only some
supposits count as persons.
Interestingly and importantly, the notion of person used in these discus-
sions is not a modern notion of personhood, called by some in the debate
a Lockean notion of personhood (Cf. Pohle 1911, 226). Such a notion has it
that personhood is, as Carlson (2012, 204) defines it, “An individual who
manifests the developed traits and abilities associated with human, personal
life (e.g. self-awareness, deliberate choice and action).” The reason this
modern definition will be insufficient for the Christological (and
Trinitarian) contexts becomes more explicit in the discussion of the humanity
of Christ in Section 4. In brief, though, the traditional view is that Christ had
a human element – a body/soul composite – that some argue fulfilled the
conditions for being a person in this modern sense of the term. This may lead
some to believe that there are two persons – “persons” in the sense relevant to
the doctrine – in the Incarnation, something the conciliar texts and traditional
Christian orthodoxy adamantly deny. This is just one example of how ignor-
ance of the historical meaning of the technical terms can cause confusion
concerning the traditional doctrine. In Section 2.3, we see another instance of
confusion over terms.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
8 Philosophy of Religion
Concerning the history, the term “human person” was used to mean merely
human person. As such, speaking in this way was viewed as problematic by
orthodox proponents of the Incarnation. Philosophers will rightly note that
“human person” doesn’t logically entail “merely human person” by itself. But
philosophers will do well to remember that, in matters of preaching and
teaching, conversational implicature is at least as important as logical
implicature.
Concerning the traditional prudential maxim from Christological debates, the
idea was not to speak as the opponents spoke, for fear of leading astray the laity.
Aquinas, for instance, notes that while it is true that Christ is impassible in his
divine nature, one ought not to say so unqualifiedly, as it may appear to be
a word in favor of the view of the Manicheans, who thought that Christ had no
real body (ST III q.16 a.8 ad.2). The same prudential maxim would lead the
orthodox proponents of the Incarnation not to speak in ways that appear to
support the view of the Arians, who thought Christ was not a divine person in
the same sense the Father is. To make explicit that they were affirming neither
a Manichean nor an Arian view of Christ, some thinkers in the tradition took to
calling Christ a “Theandric” person. The English word “theandric” comes from
two Greek roots, which in the nominative are theos, for God, and anēr, for man
(which is andros in the genitive case).11
a contingent entity, not itself a person, but that has a person as a part (see section
5.3 for more on this view, there called “Model A”).
In this Element, I use the terms “Jesus Christ,” “Word,” “Second Person,”
“the Son,” and all the rest as co-referring personal terms. They refer, in my
usage, to one and the same person. I have argued for this usage of the terms
elsewhere on conciliar grounds (Pawl 2016d, 46–47), grounds Flint (2011,
81n.17) shares. Against the first view, that “Jesus” names the human nature
alone, we do well to recall that the councils call Jesus “true God” and “one of the
Holy Trinity” (Tanner 1990, 127). No human nature, though, is one of the Holy
Trinity or truly God. Against both the first and third views, the councils call
Jesus a hypostasis and a person, as we saw in Section 2.2. The Word too, though,
is a person. If we look back to the truth conditions for being a hypostasis in
Section 2.1, we see that no hypostasis can have a distinct hypostasis as
a component, since each hypostasis is a complete being in its own right. And
so the Word and Jesus cannot be related to one another as component to whole,
since they are both referred to by “person” and “hypostasis.” There must be two
distinct persons, then, or the names must refer to the very same thing. If distinct
persons, we have a nonorthodox view sometimes labeled “Nestorianism.” If the
terms co-refer, then the naming convention I use in this Element is the correct
one.14
It is true that the name “Jesus Christ” is bound up with the Incarnation, such
that had the Word not become incarnate, he wouldn’t have had that name.
Presumably, “the Second Person” is not contingent upon the Incarnation in
the same sense. Even so, that doesn’t show that the two terms do not co-refer.
2.4 Conclusion
In summary, the Word, the Son, the Second Person of the Trinity, is a person –
a hypostasis of a rational nature. That very person became human and is the one
and only divine person to have become incarnate.15 As I use the term in this
Element, “Jesus Christ” is the name of a person, and that person is the very same
person as the Word.
14
See Section 5.3 for more discussion of the relation between Jesus and the Word.
15
It is an interesting question whether the other two divine persons could have become incarnate.
For more on that question, see Adams (1985; 2005; 2006, 198–199; 2009, 241;), de Aldama and
Solano (2014, 63), Aquinas (ST III q.3), Arendzen (1941, 161), Baker (2013, 47), Bonting
(2003), Brazier (2013), Craig (2006, 63), Crisp (2008; 2009, chap. 8), Cross (2005, 230–232),
Cuff (2015, 366–371), Davies (2003), Fisher and Fergusson (2006), Flint (2001, 312; 2012,
192–198), Freddoso (1983; 1986), George (2001), Gondreau (2018, 145–150), Gorman (2016),
Hebblethwaite (2001; 2008, 74), Jaeger (2017), Kereszty (2002, 382), Kevern (2002), Le
Poidevin (2009a, 183; 2011), Mascall (1965, 40–41), Morris (1987, 183), O’Collins (2002,
19–23), Pawl (2016a; 2016c; 2019b, chaps. 2 and 3), Pohle (1913, 136), Schmaus (1971,
241–242), Sturch (1991, 43, 194–200), and Ward (1998, 162).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
10 Philosophy of Religion
On one understanding, the divine nature has the attributes of classical theism.
On this theory, the nature is impassible and so unable to be causally affected.
The nature is immutable and so unable to change. It is atemporal and so outside
of time. And it is simple so without any ontological complexity.
Parts of this view receive support from the conciliar texts.17 For instance,
concerning immutability, the Council of Ephesus teaches that Christ “is
unchangeable and immutable by nature” (Tanner 1990, 51). The same council
teaches that “those are quite mad who suppose that ‘a shadow of change’ is
conceivable in connexion with the divine nature of the Word” (Tanner 1990,
72). Concerning impassibility, Chalcedon says that it is an error to claim that
“the divine nature of the Only-begotten is passible” (Tanner 1990, 84).
Moreover, Chalcedon “expels from the assembly of the priests those who dare
to say that the divinity of the Only-begotten is passible” (85–86).
Evidence for atemporality in the councils is less clear. Leo writes in his Tome
to Flavian, part of the accepted documents from Chalcedon, that “whilst
16
See Hasker (2019) for a recent discussion of the divine nature.
17
To see the conciliar evidence in much greater detail, as well as evidence from later Catholic,
Orthodox, and Protestant sources, see Pawl (2016d, chaps. 8, Section II).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 11
remaining pre-existent, [the Son of God] begins to exist in time [ante tempora
manens esse coepit ex tempore]” (Tanner 1990, 79). The Second Council of
Constantinople includes an anathema that declares accursed those who will not
say that the Son has a nativity from the Father achronos, that is, outside time.
Neither of these texts proves that the divine nature is atemporal. But they do
give some reason to think that the Son is atemporal, and he clearly is not
atemporal due to his human nature. So there is reason to think that it is due to
his divinity itself that he is atemporal. Concerning simplicity, there is no explicit
affirmation from the first seven councils that the divine nature is simple. Later
councils and confessional statements, though, Catholic, Orthodox, and
Protestant, include the divinity’s simplicity as a teaching.18
There are various ways one might understand the divine nature such that it
doesn’t have the robust attributes classical theism ascribes to it. One standard
term for the most-attested contemporary school of thought concerning the
divine nature that is contrary to classical theism is “theistic personalism.”
I avoid that term here, primarily because the rivalry between these two
approaches to God spills out into other topics besides the divine nature, for
instance, how God creates and whether God is a person or merely personal.19
Those topics aren’t germane to the purposes of this Element and so would be an
unnecessary rabbit trail to follow.
Another theory that may appear relevant here is kenotic Christology, which is
the topic of Section 7.3.4. Briefly, kenotic Christology claims that Christ
emptied himself of some of his divine attributes when he became incarnate.
For instance, he went from being omniscient to being limited in knowledge, or
omnipresent to being located only at a certain place. Such a view has an oblique
relation to the theory of the divine nature, for such a view requires that
omniscience is not an essential feature of divinity. Were it essential, Christ
would cease being divine when he lacks knowledge during the Incarnation.
Thomas Morris draws out the implications for divinity explicitly when he notes
that to be divine, on the kenotic view, wouldn’t require omniscience, but rather
omniscience-unless-incarnate.20 Likewise for other attributes that cause
18
For examples, see the Catholic Fourth Lateran Council (Tanner 1990, 230–232), the first three
decrees of the Orthodox Third Hesychastic Council, and the Reformed Belgic Confession of
Faith, Article 1.
19
For a discussion of the distinction between classical theism and theistic personalism, and to see
where the latter term was coined, see B. Davies (2004, chap. 1). For more on whether God is
a person or personal, see Page (2019)
20
See Morris (1987, 99); see also Forrest (2009, 130–131).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
12 Philosophy of Religion
Incarnational worries – they all get an “unless” modification. Even still, one
might think that the divine nature itself has the attributes of classical theism,
even if the persons can freely choose to be empty of those attributes, and so
kenotic Christology does not imply that the divine nature itself is not simple,
atemporal, immutable, and impassible.21
The main alternatives to classical theism seldom reject the listed attributes
wholesale. For instance, many keep the language of divine eternity, but under-
stand eternity as implying everlastingness, and not atemporality.22 Or one might
deny that God is unchanging metaphysically speaking, but retain that God is
unchanging morally speaking.23 Likewise, God might be causally affectable,
but unable to be caused to suffer psychologically.
These are common alternatives in the philosophical discussion of the
Incarnation. They do not, though, sit easily with the conciliar texts. If Christ
was already existing in time everlastingly, in what sense could he go from being
preexistent to beginning to exist in time, as we saw Chalcedon teach in Section
3.2.1? Moreover, we can tell the sense the councils give to the attributes by
seeing the work they intend the attributes to do. They use immutability, for
instance, to preclude ontological change in the divine nature, not merely to point
out moral constancy (Tanner 1990, 51).24
21
Such a view would hold that while the self-emptying of the person requires change in the person,
it doesn’t require change in the divine nature. I leave the spelling out of the mechanics of such
a view to its proponents.
22
See Deng (2018) and Mullins (2016). 23 See Dorner (1994) and Swinburne (1993, 219).
24
For a much fuller discussion of the use of immutability in the conciliar texts, see Pawl (2016d,
107–114).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 13
3.4 Conclusion
This section explicated various views of the attributes of the divine nature.
According to Conciliar Christology, that nature is immutable and impassible.
A case could be made for its atemporality from those texts too, but such is not
explicit, as are impassibility and immutability. The section also discussed how
the rival conceptions of divinity affect the problems that face a philosophy of the
Incarnation.
25
For an excellent, prolonged discussion of this question in the medieval context, see Adams
(1999).
26
For discussions of these two views of nature, see Crisp (2007b, 41), Dalmau (2016, IIA:68),
Dubray (1911), and Plantinga (1999, 184). For a discussion of the historical reception of the term
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
14 Philosophy of Religion
Readers will note that the abstract and concrete views of human nature are as far
apart, ontologically speaking, as two views can be. An abstract nature like
Humanity is typically viewed as shareable by many individuals, not located in
space or time, unable to enter into causal relations, and possessed by substances
“nature,” and a listing of which thinkers thought what about natures, see Pawl (2016d, chap. 2
section II.b; 2019b, chap. 1 IV.b).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 15
27
See Pawl (2016d, chap. 2 section II.b; 2019b, chap. 1 IV.b). In the following arguments I make an
assumption that either the concrete view or the abstract view is correct. These two views are
surely the two dominant views in the literature.
28
Both those who think the human element is wholly immaterial and those who think it is wholly
material will need to explain conciliar passages that refer to it as having both a body and soul.
29
See also Hasker (2016, 434–435), Leftow (2004, 278), and Marmodoro and Hill (2008, 101).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
16 Philosophy of Religion
Both abstract theorists and concrete theorists posit a human element for Christ.
Another – traditional – name for that human element is “human nature.” So, for
the remainder of this Element, I use the term “human nature” to refer to the
human element of Christ. If the need arises to refer to the abstract nature, in
order to avoid equivocation, I refer to it as “Humanity.”
For we do not say that the nature of the Word was changed and became flesh,
nor that he was turned into a whole man made of body and soul. Rather do we
claim that the Word in an unspeakable, inconceivable manner united to
himself hypostatically flesh enlivened by a rational soul, and so became
man and was called son of man. (Tanner 1990, 41, emphasis added)
30
For discussion of this or similar views, see Arcadi (2018, 4), Crisp (2009, chap. 7), Jaeger (2017),
Leftow (2015), Lim (2019), Merricks (2007), Turner (2017) and van Horn (2010).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 17
Similarly, Leo says in his Tome, “the Word is not the same thing as the flesh”
(Tanner 1990, 81). Both views, then – that Christ lacked a body and that he was
transformed into a human being – are precluded by Conciliar Christology.
The soul of the human nature of Christ is the second person of the Trinity, the
Logos. The human nature of Christ is composed of the Logos and a human
body. (Harris and Craig n.d.)
What ought one to make of these views, where the divine person is the human
soul of Christ?
The main objections to such a view are the following. First, the soul is that
which makes a human to be human. Lacking a human soul, then, Christ
wouldn’t be truly human. Second, consider the maxim of St. Gregory of
Nazianzus that what is not assumed is not healed. Were there no assumed
human soul, then, there would be no healing of our human souls by the
Incarnation. For these and other similar reasons, Apollinarianism was declared
a heresy at the second ecumenical council, the First Council of Constantinople
in AD 381, and reaffirmed as a heresy many times over in later councils.
Concerning whether Neo-Apollinarianism is distinct from Apollinarianism
in anything more than name, note how a church council in Rome in AD 382
condemned Apollinaris’s view:
We pronounce anathema against them who say that the Word of God is in the
human flesh in lieu and place of the human rational and intellective soul. For,
the Word of God is the Son Himself. Neither did He come in the flesh to
31
Rea (2011, 149–150) presents without endorsement such a view.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
18 Philosophy of Religion
replace, but rather to assume and preserve from sin and save the rational and
intellective soul of man. (as quoted in Sollier 1907)
[T]he difference of the natures [is] made known in the same one subsistence
in that each nature wills and performs the things that are proper to it in
a communication with the other; then in accord with this reasoning we hold
that two natural wills and principles of action meet in correspondence for the
salvation of the human race. (Tanner 1990, 129–130)
Here the traditional texts teach that there are two natures, and they are known
because each has its own, distinct will. As such, even if one worries that two
wills implies two persons, the response of denying two wills is not an open
option for the proponent of Conciliar Christology.
Some have attempted to read this passage as consistent with Christ having
a single will that counts as both divine and human. In this attenuated sense,
though numerically one, Christ has two wills. Such a reading would allow the
proponent of traditional Christology to avoid the two-person worry and yet
maintain consistency with the councils. Crisp (2007b, 59–60) and I (Pawl
2016d, 19–20) argue that this reading is inconsistent with other claims the
councils make concerning Christ’s wills. The divine will leads the human
will, which is subjugated to it; each nature has a will and operates through it,
etc. Such claims are difficult to parse if there is only one will.
32
For more on the topic of a double union, see Pawl (2016d, 48–50).
33
For more on the topic of whether two minds or wills implies two persons, see Pawl (2016d, chap. 9).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 19
Given that Conciliar Christology does teach the unity of the person, along
with the duality of natures, each with its own will and operation, how does the
Christian avoid the objection that there are, in fact, two persons in Christ?
34
For more on the enhypostatic/anhypostatic distinction, see Crisp (2007b, chap. 3).
35
For more on these two schools, see Hipp (2001, 471–518) and Pawl (2016d, 68–70).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
20 Philosophy of Religion
The Human Nature in Christ is complete and perfect as nature, yet it lacks that
which would make it a person, whether this be something negative, as
Scotists hold, namely the mere fact that a nature is not assumed by a higher
person, or, as Thomists assert, some positive reality distinct from nature and
making it incommunicable.
One view, often associated with St. Thomas Aquinas, is that being a person
requires a certain component part. Christ’s human nature, on this view, lacks
that ontological component, and so fails to be a person.36
What exactly the part is differs in different views. Some call it a mode, others
an individual act of existence, others still something else. For the purposes of
responding to the charge that the human nature of Christ is a person in its own
right, the ontological category that the thing falls under is not as important as the
method of response. Christ’s human nature lacks an ontological component that
it would need to have in order to be a person, and so it fails to be a person.
The Scotistic view posits a negative condition for personhood. For a nature to be
a person, it has to be unassumed. Since Christ’s human nature fails that condi-
tion, since it is assumed, it does not count as a person. This view does not require
the supposition that your or my nature has a certain ontological doodad in virtue
of which we are persons. Instead, it merely requires our natures to be unassumed
for us to count as persons.
36
Textual evidence indicatess, though, that Aquinas held a view much closer to the Scotistic view
discussed later in this Element. See Pawl and Spencer (2016, 148–149).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 21
37
For more recent work on this question, see (2019), McFarland (2008), King (2015), McCall
(2019, chap. 4), and McFarland(2008)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
22 Philosophy of Religion
fallenness requires Original Sin, others that it merely requires not having all the
preternatural gifts that Adam had. How much of a fall is required to count as
a fallen human nature is a question we need not answer at this point.
We find others drawing these distinctions in the understanding of fallenness
as well. Immediately before offering pages of quotations verifying the claim,
Alfeyev writes:
He goes on in the same section to claim that, for the Orthodox, Christ did not
have personal sin, sinful inclination, or Original Sin.38
4.6 Conclusion
This section explored various divisions in the conceptualization of Christ’s
human nature. One might think of it as abstract or concrete. If concrete, then
there are further choices to be made about the number of parts it has, and the
person’s relation to that nature. If the nature is concrete, with both a rational soul
and a body (as Conciliar Christology teaches), then the question of whether it is
a person must be addressed. Two reasons for denying the nature’s personhood
that this section canvasses are that it lacks some component part necessary for
38
Alfeyev (2012, 285) notes that the notion of “Original Sin” in Western contexts isn’t the same as
in Eastern contexts, and in neither sense did Christ have Original Sin.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 23
39
For a more detailed discussion of the hypostatic union in the conciliar texts, see Pawl (2016d,
20–23).
40
For more on the meaning of ineffability, see Pawl (2020, sec. 2). For more on mystery and
philosophical reflection on the incarnation, see Pawl (2016d, 88–91; 2019b, 5–6).
41
For more on whether the human relatum is properly characterized as the full human nature or the
parts of the human nature, see Pawl (2019b, 109–113).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
24 Philosophy of Religion
115). The two natures are united, in the traditional language, in the person of the
Word, but the person of the Word is not, technically speaking, one of the relata
of the relationship. (The term used for the relation of the Word to the human
nature is assumption.) It is important that the union does not take a person on the
human side of the relation, as discussed in Section 4.3. Were it to do so, there
would be two different persons in the Incarnation, rather than one person who is
both God and human, as the Nicene Creed claims.
It is this fact – the fact that there is one person who is both divine and human,
having both divine and human natures – that grounds the Communication of
Idioms.
42
For more on the Communication of Idioms, see de Aldama and Solano (2014, 170–171), Cross
(2019), Pawl (2016d, 23–27, 54–55, 62–65; 2019b, 17–19), and Pohle (1913, 186).
43
I am using the term “apt” to mean correctly assertible of. Some thinkers say a term is true of
a subject. That language is acceptable, too, but I prefer to avoid it, as I take truth to be a feature of
a complete proposition, not a feature of a term in a proposition.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 25
Here Cyril, in a text accepted at the Council of Ephesus, asserts that the
expressions ascribed to Christ as human are ascribed to the very same subject
as the expressions ascribed to him as God.
It should be clear that the Communication of Idioms doctrine as spelled out
here does not imply that a predicate truthfully said of one nature is thus
truthfully assertible of the other nature, or that a predicate truthfully said of
the person is thus truthfully assertible of either nature.44 From Christ’s being
crucified, we cannot derive that his divine nature was crucified. From Christ’s
human nature being pierced on the wood of the cross, as Chalcedon teaches (see
Section 4.1.3), we cannot derive that the divine nature was pierced.
Likewise, the Communication of Idioms does not undergird either of the
following two theses:
1. Any predicate truly said of either nature of Christ is also truly said of the
person of Christ.
2. Any predicate truly said of the person of Christ is truly said of at least one
nature of Christ.
Neither of these is true, we can see, since they have counterexamples. Christ’s
human nature is truly said to be “identical to a human nature,” and there is a time
before which it did not exist, but neither of these predicates is truly said of the
person of Christ. The person of Christ is not “identical to the human nature,” and,
though there was a time before he was human, there was no time before which
that person did not exist (the original Nicene Creed precludes such a claim with its
final anathema). Likewise, the second claim is subject to counterexample. One
predicate truly said of the person of Christ is that he is “one person in two
natures.” But neither the divine nor the human nature is “one person in two
natures.” We find, then, that neither of these theses survives scrutiny.
In fact, the notion of “communication” may be misleading here, even if it is
the traditional language. It is not that the term goes from the nature to the person,
as a migratory bird might go from one location to another. Rather, it is that the
incarnate person fulfills the ontological conditions that are needful in typical
cases to satisfy the predicate, and that very same incarnate person can be
44
Though some Lutheran theologians have taught such communication from nature to nature; see
Pohle (1913, 194–195) for one discussion of this.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
26 Philosophy of Religion
referred to by terms that refer to him in virtue of his other nature. So we can use
a subject term from one nature, since the very person referred to by that term
satisfies the truth conditions for the predicate. It should not be thought of as
a predicate or a property migrating from one subject, whether linguistic or
ontological, to another. Rather, it should be thought of in terms of fulfilling
truth conditions or not.
In becoming human, the Son or Word of God (whom I’ll label W) takes on
CHN as a part. This assumption results in a Son who combines both his
original divine substance (D) and his created human nature (CHN). (Flint
2011, 71)
On Model T, the Word comes to have an additional part (or part-like thing): the
human nature.
On the second model, Model A:
The Son unites himself to CHN in the Incarnation. But the composite thus
formed is not the Son. The Son remains simply one part of the composite entity
that results from his assuming a human nature. That composite entity, which
(following Scotus and Leftow) we can call Christ, is a contingent thing,
composed of another contingent entity (CHN) and of a necessary one (the
Son). (Flint 2011, 79)
45
For discussion of these two compositional models of the Incarnation, see Crisp (2011; 2016,
chap. 6), Flint (2015), Hasker (2015), Leftow (2011, 321), and Turner (2019 n 5).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 27
person of the Son, not the divine nature, as one of the relata, while Model T has
the natures as the two relata. Score one for Model T.
Second is a reason from the nature of personhood. On Model A, a whole (the
contingent composite, Christ) has a person (the Word) as a part. But on the
traditional view of personhood, explicated in Section 2.1, a person cannot be
a part of a larger whole. Thus, Model A sits uneasily with the traditional notion
of personhood.46
We might also ask about helpful analogies in addition to models. The
Athanasian Creed (Denzinger 2002, para. 40) and the Council of Ephesus
(Tanner 1990, 52) both use the analogy that as a man’s soul indwells his body,
so likewise the Word indwells the human nature. Katherin Rogers (2010; 2013)
offers an analogy based on virtual realities. A child can play a video game and in
doing so enter and act in a virtual world through the character in the game;
similarly, the Son, through taking up a created human nature, can enter and act
in the created world.47
5.4 Conclusion
This section presented an account of what the hypostatic union is not, then some
discussion of what the union does. The main theological work the union does is
ontologically undergirding the union between the two natures in one person, and
so providing an explanation for the Communication of Idioms. The union has
been modeled in myriad ways, including models based on a mereological
understanding of the union, a union of body and soul, and multiple sci-fi
analogies.
Having discussed the ontology of the person, the natures, and their union,
now we move on to discuss the activities of that person.
46
For a reply to these objections to Model A, see Crisp (2011, 52–56).
47
Hasker (2017) gives a similar example in terms of the sci-fi movie Avatar.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
28 Philosophy of Religion
questions about what each will can do and their interrelations. Was each will
free? Or, perhaps put differently: was the one Christ free with respect to each
will? Moreover, given that Christ had a human will, could he sin by means of
that human will? If not, as was traditionally believed, what implications does
that inability to sin have on his being tempted? In this section, I consider each of
these questions.
The consensus in Christian thinking has been that Christ has two volitional
powers, a divine one and a human one, and that he can will freely with each
will.48 Such an answer has led to two types of objections: objections from the
interrelation of the wills and objections from volitional activities and
personhood.
Considering objections from the interrelation of the wills, one might well
wonder here what the relations are between the two wills of Christ. The texts of
Conciliar Christology are not silent on this issue. For instance, the Third
Council of Constantinople (681) says:
We proclaim equally two natural volitions or wills in him and two natural
principles of action which undergo no division, no change, no partition, no
confusion, in accordance with the teaching of the holy fathers. And the two
natural wills not in opposition, as the impious heretics said, far from it, but his
human will following, and not resisting or struggling, rather in fact subject to
his divine and all powerful will. (Tanner 1990, 128)
Here the human will is said to follow, be subject to, not resist, and not struggle
against, the divine will. As Richard Swinburne (1994, 198–199) and Garrett
Deweese (2007, 133), among others, wonder: how can a will be free in such
a state?49
The main question at this point is how strong the subjugation is. My
children might follow my will in a certain thing, say, cleaning their rooms,
without resisting or struggling. (I imagine that this is possible.) In doing
so, they don’t render themselves unfree. What is needed for the objection
to succeed is some reason to think that Christ’s human will is subjugated
48
See Pawl (2019b, 119–123), Pawl and Timpe (2016), and Wessling (2013) for more discussion of
this issue.
49
See Pawl (2019b, 126–131) for a detailed discussion of this objection and a reply. For a critical
discussion of Swinburne and Deweese, see Pawl (2016d, 219–220). For other discussions of
Christ’s freedom, see Gaine (2015b, chap. 7), Hebblethwaite (2008, 68), Hick (2006, 56),
Kereszty (2002, 392–396), McFarland (2007), McKinley (2015), Rogers (2016), and Sturch
(1991, 29, 167).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 29
The consensus answer to the question of whether Christ could sin with either of
his wills is “no.” One might wonder how the inability to sin is consistent with
the freedom of both of Christ’s wills. Moreover, one might also wonder how he
could be tempted, if willing something sinful was impossible for him.
Concerning whether Christ could sin, contemporary literature has featured
extended discussion. The traditional teaching is that Christ is not only sinless
but also impeccable.52 If he is impeccable, does that render him not omnipotent,
owing to the fact that there is something – that is, sinning – which Christ cannot
do?53 Typically, the answer is “no”: being able to sin is not its own power,
50
For an argument for strong subjugation from a different starting point, see Werther (2005).
51
A reader might accuse this response of defining away the problem, rather than facing it head on.
Such a reader does well to remember that the concept of “person” I employ here is the traditional
understanding of it in these contexts. If the objector understands personhood differently, and so
sees this as a devastating objection, it is the objector who is defining terms advantageously.
I consider this worry at length in chapter 9 of Pawl (2016). See also Murray and Rea (2008,
82–84).
52
On the historical affirmation of impeccability, see Bavinck (2006, 314), O’Collins (1995, 281),
Pohle (1913, 214), Schmaus (1971, 259), and Weis (2003).
53
On the question of whether God can sin, see, for instance, Adams (2006, 75–79), Brümmer
(1984), Carter (1985), Funkhouser (2006), Garcia (1987), Gellman (1977), Leftow (1989),
Morris (1983) and Stump (2005, 102–7)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
30 Philosophy of Religion
a power had by you but lacked by God.54 To sin is to use a power poorly, but
sinning is not its own power, and so, the typical answer goes, God’s inability to
sin is not the lack of some power had by others. As T. J. Mawson (2018, 42) puts
the point, the ability to sin is a liability, not a power, and so not a lack of power if
it is missing. God, as a perfect being, has all powers and no liabilities.
Concerning whether Christ could be tempted, again, the discussion is vast.55
The traditional view is that Christ could be tempted, as Scripture (e.g., Hebrews
4:15) and the councils say, yet Christ could not sin. How can one make sense of
such a conjunction of claims?
One might attempt to explain the temptation of an impeccable person in
various ways. First, one might distinguish between internal and external temp-
tation. Christ could be externally tempted – the devil might wave a good in front
of his nose – yet neither feel the internal, sinful impulses toward that temptation
nor be able to succumb to them.56 In such a case, it would be true to say he is
tempted (in the external sense) and such a temptation would not require his
ability to sin.
A second response is known as the epistemic response. To be tempted, on
this view, does not require the actual ability to sin; it merely requires that one
believe that one has the actual ability to sin.57 You might be duped into
thinking that you have the launch button for the Russian nuclear program.
And you might feel sorely tempted to make use of that button, even though you
don’t, in fact, have the ability to launch the missiles. This response requires
that Christ not know of his divine status and mission, such that he mistakenly
thinks that he is a person able to sin. Such a view is precluded by traditional
views of Christ’s knowledge, as we see in Section 6.2.1. Nevertheless, this
remains an open option for those not wed to the traditional views of Christ’s
knowledge.
A third response is to conceptualize temptation such that it doesn’t require
either the ability to sin or even the belief that one can sin. Rather, following
54
For more on this point, see McKinley (2009, 258), Morris (1986, 167), and Pawl (2019b,
151–153) and the works in the previous footnote.
55
On the questions of temptation and sin, see Canham (2000, 95), Couenhoven (2012, 406–407),
Crisp (2007b; 2007c), Davidson (2008, 395), Erickson (1996, 562), Fisk (2007), Gaine (2015b,
168–172), Hart (1995), King (2015, 73–76), McKinley (2009; 2011), Morris (1987, chap. 7),
Murray and Rea (2008, 82–90), O’Collins (1995, 283–284), Pawl (2019b, chap. 6), Pelser
(2019), Sturch (1991, 19–20), Swinburne (1994, 204–207), Ware (2013, chap. 5), Wellum
(2016, 459–465), and Werther (1993; 2012).
56
Both Aquinas (2013, bks. 4, lecture 1, pg 101) and Crisp (2007c, 178) argue that Christ’s
temptations have an external source. See Murray and Rea (2008, 86) and Pawl (2019b,
150–151) for more discussion of this view.
57
For discussions of this view, see Bartel (1995, 154–55), Hart (1995, 41), McKinley (2009,
239–243), Morris (1987, 147–148), O’Collins (1995, 283–284), and Pawl (2019b, 139–143).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 31
Here, the affectively charged “pull” of temptation need not take something
sinful as its object. It might be the pleasure of the taste of a chocolate cake that
is in focal attention, yet that good is seen to conflict with a distal goal – the
goal, say, of losing weight via dieting. On this view, Christ could have the pull
toward food in the desert, or away from the discomfort of crucifixion, and yet
judge such pleasure or lack of discomfort as contrary to his goal of fasting or
his plan of atonement for sinful humanity. On this psychological view, then,
neither the ability to sin nor the belief that one can sin is a necessary condition
for temptation.
The tradition makes a distinction between “natural and innocent” passions
and those that are not.59 Some passions, such as fear, hunger, thirst, aversion,
sadness, and so on are blameless and natural to humans. These are passions
Christ might have, and they are a blameless basis for temptation, when under-
stood as outlined in this section. Other passions, as discussed by Oliver Crisp
(2007a, 176), are evil in themselves. Such vicious passions (e.g., urges to
sexually assault others) show an imperfect character. The view under discussion
here has it that Christ never had any such passions or appetitive pulls, and so no
internal temptation toward them.
58
See Hoffman et al. (2012, 1319), Kavanaugh, Andrade, and May (2005, 447), and Milyavskaya
et al (2015, 678) for relevant psychological discussion. See Pawl (2019b, 143–51) for a detailed
explication of the psychological view of temptation. Something similar to this view of tempta-
tion is at work in Aquinas’s thought as well; see Gondreau (2018, 359).
59
See Alfeyev (2012, 283) and John of Damascus (1958, 323–324).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
32 Philosophy of Religion
60
For discussions of Christ’s knowledge, see Denzinger (2002, 2184–2185, 2289), Gaine (2015a,
2015b, chap. 6;), Green (2017), Loke (2013), Margerie (1980), Moloney (2000), Rosenberg
(2010), Scarpelli (2007), and Wellum (2016, 454–459).
61
For more on the mode of beatific knowledge, see Aquinas’s Compendium of Theology, 216, ST
III q.9 a.3 ad.3, and ST III q.10 a.4 resp.
62
Marge.
63
For discussion of this controversy, see Weinandy (2004; 2014) and White (2005; 2016, chap. 5).
64
These are both sketches of arguments that Aquinas gives. See ST III. q.9 a.2 resp.; Comp. Theol.
216.
65
See ST III. q.9 a.3 sed contra.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 33
Recall that, on the traditional doctrine, Christ has a created human soul, the same
in type as yours or mine. Now, your soul and mine has natural activities, some of
which are intellectual. Were Christ to lack all acquired knowledge, a standard
activity and perfection of a human soul would be lacking in him. It would be
there, but “offline,” so to speak. This appears unfitting to many thinkers. So, like
typical humans, Christ could use his intellect to know things.
How can we explain the biblical passages that seem to require ignorance of
Christ, then? Consider, for instance, these two passages:66
Luke 2:52: And Jesus increased in wisdom and in stature, and in favor with
God and man.
Mark 13:32: [Jesus said,] “But of that day or that hour no one knows, not even
the angels in heaven, nor the Son, but only the Father.”
Historically, there are three main ways to deal with such passages.
First, a recent way of responding has been to suppose that Christ was really
ignorant of things like when he would return. Kenotic thinkers can claim that
Christ in no way knew when he would return, owing to the fact that he emptied
himself of his divine knowledge.
Second, some can claim that when Christ claimed lack of knowledge, he
meant that he lacked knowledge in his human intellect, not that he lacked
knowledge full stop.
Third, and more traditional, is the attempt to deny that such passages really
require ignorance. We find this variety of response in Cyril of Alexandria,
Gregory the Great, John Chrysostom, Augustine, Maximus the Confessor, and
Thomas Aquinas, to name just some thinkers who support this method of
response.67 Concerning the passage from Luke, Christ grew in appearance of
or renown for wisdom and favor with God, and also in acquired knowledge. This
growth in acquired knowledge is not a change from ignorance to knowledge;
rather, it is coming in a new way to know something already known. Concerning
the passage from Mark, these authors distinguish between the state of knowing
and the revelatory act of making known. Christ here, they claim, intends to say
that he does not make known the hour. As a parallel, some, like Aquinas (Comp.
Theo. 242), note that God says to Abraham after the potential sacrifice of Isaac,
66
See Archer (2017), Gaine (2015b, chap. 6), and Moloney (2000, 28–32) for additional discussion
of these passages.
67
For Cyril, see Bartel (1991, 35). For Augustine, see De Trinitate I.12.23. For Aquinas’s reference
to Chrysostom, see ST III q.10 a.2 ad 1. For Gregory, see Denzinger (2002, paragraph 248). For
Maximus, see Moloney (2000, 46). For Aquinas’s response, see his Compendium of Theology,
242. For Aquinas’s discussions of Luke 2:52, see: QDV q.20 a.1 sed contra; Comp. Theol. 216;
ST III q.7 a.12 obj 3 and ad 3; ST III q.12 a.2 sed contra, resp, and ad 3; his Commentary on John,
1:14, no. 264. For a critical discussion of Aquinas’s approach, see Maritain (1969, 50–54).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
34 Philosophy of Religion
“Now I know that you fear God” (Gen. 22:12). Aquinas argues that this does not
mean that God went from ignorance to knowing that Abraham feared him.
Rather, God was declaring it made known that Abraham feared him.
68
For more on this point, see Pawl (2019b, chap. 7). For recent discussions of the Eternity Solution,
see Cobreros (2016), Leftow (1991; 2009), Rota (2010), Stump and Kretzmann (1981; 1991),
and Zagzebski (1991). For recent discussions of open theism, see Hasker (1998), Oord, Hasker
and Zimmerman (2011), Rhoda (2007; 2008; 2011), Sanders (1998), and Tuggy (2007).
69
To see this response worked out in more detail, see Pawl (2019b, chap. 7)
70
For more on the freedom of the blessed in heaven, see Brown (2015), Cowan (2011), Henderson
(2014; 2016), Pawl and Timpe (2009; 2013; 2016; 2017), and Tamburro (2014).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 35
71
For a discussion of the problem of deliberation, see Pawl (2014c; 2019b, chap. 8).
72
For more discussion of the problem of explanatory priority, see Pawl (2014b; 2019b, chap. 8).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
36 Philosophy of Religion
nature, that which the component parts undergo can still rightly be said of
Christ. So, for instance, it is true that he was buried, since his human body was
buried. And it is true that he descended into hell, at least on these medieval
accounts and on the traditional view of the earlier theologians, since his human
soul descended into hell. At the resurrection, those parts of the human nature
were knit together again, and so Christ was an integrated human being again
thereafter.73
6.4 Conclusion
This section has charted the current discussions on the activities of Christ in
analytic philosophy of religion. As noted, various areas remain underdeveloped
in these literatures. The main areas of discussion concern Christ’s knowing,
willing, and death. On the traditional view, he was free with respect to both
wills, though he could not sin. Traditionally, he knew everything with the divine
intellect and all created things with his human intellect, though this did not
negatively affect his freedom or ours. His death has traditionally been explained
as the separation of his body and soul, and his resurrection explained as their
being rejoined.
Christ is immutable and mutable, impassible and passible, filling all creation
and located at the bosom of Mary, etc. How could one make sense of such
claims?74
73
For current discussion on this issue, see Jaeger (2017), Jaeger and Sienkiewicz (2018), Nevitt
(2016), and Turner (2017; 2019).
74
A brief sampling of other discussions of this problem includes: Adams (2006, 121–123; 2009,
242–243), Arcadi (2018), Davis (2006, 116), Dawson (2004, 161–162), Evans (2006a, 13),
Feenstra (2006, 142–144), Gordon (2016, 64), Gorman (2000a; 2011; 2014; 2016; 2017,
chap. 6), Hebblethwaite (2008, 60), Hick (1989, 415; 2006, 66–70), Hill (2012, 3), Kelly
(1994), Klima (1984), Labooy (2019), Leftow (2011, 316), Le Poidevin (2009b, 704), Loke
(2009, 51; 2011, 493–494), Macquarrie (1990), Moreland and Craig (2003, 597), Morris (1987,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 37
All the properties of the human, just as of the Divine Nature, may be
predicated equally of Christ. Hence Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii, 4)
that “Christ Who [is] God and Man, is called created and uncreated, passible
and impassible.” (ST III q.16 a.8 ad.2)
Finally, and perhaps most forcefully for those interested in affirming the
orthodox faith concerning the Incarnation, the Fourth Council of
Constantinople says of the seventh ecumenical council:
We also know that the seventh, holy and universal synod, held for the second
time at Nicaea, taught correctly when it professed the one and same Christ as
both invisible and visible lord, incomprehensible and comprehensible,
chap. 1; 2009), Pawl (2014a; 2015; 2016b; 2016d, chaps. 4–7; 2018), Riches (2016, 5, 166),
Senor (2002, 221), Spence (2008, 16), Stump (1989; 2004; 2005, chap. 14), Sturch (1991, chaps.
2, 12), Vallicella (2002), Van Inwagen (1998, secs. 2–4), and Wellum (2016, 446–455).
75
Here I present the argument as I did in Pawl (2015) and summarize the findings from that article
and from chapters 4–7 of Pawl (2016).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
38 Philosophy of Religion
76
Let “standard logic” name classical logic plus an absolute identity relation.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 39
false. But logic is such that we cannot derive from that contradiction just
anything. This view rejects the validity of the Law of the Excluded Middle.
Such a response allows the contradiction but precludes the spread of the
contradiction. The work of Jc Beall (2019) is the best place to look for this
strategy.77
The relative identity strategy contends that some – often all – identity claims are
incomplete without a sortal, a type, under which the two things are identical.
“Clark Kent is Superman” is an incomplete claim it is similar to “Edith is to the
left of.” What is needed in each case is another term: Clark is the same person as
Superman; Edith is to the left of Agnes. Importantly for the relative identity
theorist, two things can be the same x without being the same y. In addition, as
Peter van Inwagen (1998) shows, Leibniz’s Law fails if relative identity is true.
That is, A and B can be the same x and A have a feature without B having that
feature. This is relevant to the Fundamental Problem, since the human-natured
thing can be passible, and the human-natured thing can be the same person as
the divine-natured thing, without the divine-natured thing being passible.
Thus, the inference to 5, which says that one and the same thing is both
passible and impassible, is fallacious, given relative identity. Some people
claim that relative identity is necessary for the doctrine of the Trinity – the
Father and the Son are the same God, but they are not the same person.78 If this
is so, then by accepting the relative identity solution here the Christian does not
incur any additional costs, as they will already have been paid for the doctrine of
the Trinity.79
77
I discuss this strategy and objections to it in more detail in Pawl (2019a). I thank Beall for his
helpful discussion on this strategy.
78
The logic of this solution is difficult. To see it worked out carefully, see Baber (2015; 2016;
2019), Conn (2012), and Jedwab (2015; 2018). To see some objections to relative identity in
a Trinitarian context, see Rea (2003).
79
My thanks to Joseph Jedwab for his patient help in understanding the relative identity response to
the Fundamental Problem.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
40 Philosophy of Religion
use of some inference forms that Luther and Beall (for different reasons) would
want to preclude from the Christological domain.
In what follows, I employ classical logic. I again point the reader to the work
of Beall (2019), though, to see how one could answer the Fundamental Problem
by revising logic (or, perhaps as he would say, by realizing the proper extent of
logic). I also assume an absolute identity relation.
The logic of this maneuver is similar to the logic of the previous response. Such
a thinker denies 4, due to denying the second conjunct, that Christ is human. If
all specifically human predicates are denied, then “human” is denied of Christ,
and so the second conjunct of Premise 4 is false. In such a case, Christ only
80
See Hick (2006) for more on this approach.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 41
This type of response has many advocates today. The idea can be pictured as
follows. One can make a list of all of the pairs of allegedly contradictory
attributes that a God-man would have. Then, one goes through each pair,
crossing off one or the other of the two attributes, such that no pair has both
predicates left at the end of the excising. For instance, perhaps God need not be
impassible. Thus, Premise 1 is false. In another case, perhaps humans need not
really be limited in power, and so the Fundamental Problem constructed with
“omnipotent” and “limited in power” as the allegedly contradictory pair has
a false second premise. And so on. For every pair, at least one of the attributes
fails to be implied by being divine or by being human.
Scholars can use two main methods, always in tandem, to work this strategy.
(To do either alone would be to fall back into the previous two strategies
discussed.) The first is to weaken or eliminate some of the divine attributes
associated with classical theism. On such a view, it is false that God must be
impassible, immutable, eternal, and simple (or false that God is any of these
ways in a robust, problematic sense), and so any form of the Fundamental
Problem that includes those attributes has a false first premise.
The second step is to make a distinction going back at least to St. John of
Damascus (676–749), but more recently revitalized by Thomas Morris. The
Damascene writes:
The whole He, then is perfect God, but not exclusively God, because He is not
only God but also man. Likewise, the whole He is perfect man, but not
exclusively man, because He is not only man but also God.81
Morris (1987, 65–67) makes the same distinction with the terms merely (for
exclusively) and fully (for perfect). Armed with this distinction, one turns to the
Fundamental Problem with an eye toward distinguishing the second premise.
Yes, the responder says, it is true that anything merely human is, say, limited in
81
This quotation is taken, with slight modification, from John of Damascus (2000, 283).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
42 Philosophy of Religion
knowledge or power. But, the responder continues, it is false that anything fully
human is limited in knowledge or power. Similarly, it is true that anything
merely divine is impassible, but false that anything fully divine is impassible. Of
course, it is the fully claim that the objector needs for this argument to apply to
Christ. After all, the merely interpretation of the premise would itself preclude
the truth of Premise 4, that Christ is both God and human – being merely human
implies not being both human and divine. Were the proponent of the
Fundamental Problem to employ the merely premise, the argument’s premises
would contradict one another, and so the argument would be unsound.
To summarize: consider the cases of the Fundamental Problem in which one
means to excise the human predicate. Armed with the distinction between
merely human and fully human, those instances of the Fundamental Problem
can be put in two ways, depending on how one understands the second premise.
On the merely reading, the truth of the second premise contradicts the truth of
the fourth premise, and so the argument is unsound. On the fully reading, this
response claims that the second premise is false, and so the argument is
unsound. Thus, the argument is unsound.
What to make of this strategy? In the end, even if there were a consistent,
uniform manner of applying this strategy in solving the Fundamental
Problem, there’s still the fact that such a move leaves the contradiction in
place for many who affirm the doctrine of the Incarnation. Very many
defenders of the Incarnation take it as a given that the texts cited in
Section 7.1, in which Christ is predicated by apparently incompatible
predicates, as well as many other texts from the councils and theologians,
are to be believed. So, even if there were grounds for denying Premise 1 or
Premise 2 for each presentation of the Fundamental Problem, the traditional
texts preclude simply ruling out the apparently incompatible predications of
Christ. Christ must remain both passible and impassible, for instance, on
this view. Assuming the truth of Premise 3, which this solution does nothing
to challenge, the proponent of traditional Christianity still faces
a contradiction. For this large swath of past and present proponents of the
Incarnation, one must look elsewhere for a reply.
In addition, some varieties of this solution appear to collapse into the
following solution (Section 7.3.4). To see why, consider the Word pre-
Incarnation. He is then both merely and fully divine, and so, on this response,
he is impassible (since “anything merely divine is impassible” is conceded on
this view). Once incarnate, he is fully but not merely divine. Once incarnate, he
is not impassible – were he still impassible, we would not have avoided his
being both passible and impassible in the incarnation, and so this view would
not have resolved the contradiction. Thus, this solution looks to require the
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 43
who, though he was in the form of God, did not regard equality
with God as something to be exploited,
but emptied himself, taking the form of a slave, being born in
human likeness. And being found in human form,
he humbled himself and became obedient to the point of death –
even death on a cross. (NRSV)
This self-emptying – kenosis – is the impetus for the kenotic view. While
kenotic Christology ought not to be seen as merely a response to the Fundamental
Problem, it has been used as one such response, in the following way.
It is true, says the kenotic opponent of the Fundamental Problem, that
anything that is divine is immutable or impassible at some point. And true,
anything human is limited in knowledge and power at some point. But,
importantly, these might not be the same times. And, if not the same times,
then Christ’s being impassible and passible or being omnipotent and limited in
power are no more contradictory than your being seated at one time and
standing at another. What the Fundamental Problem would have to show,
and what its kenotic opponent would fight hard to deny, is that Christ must
have both attributes at the same time. In summary: the first two premises need
an “at some time” modifier added to them, and the last three lines of the
Fundamental Problem need “at the same time” modifiers added to them. Once
the temporal modification is made explicit, the contradiction is no longer
derivable.
This theory faces some objections. First, is there a time at which Christ is both
incarnate and no longer self-emptying? Many have claimed there is. The
doctrine of the exaltation claims that after his resurrection, Christ is glorified
82
For more on kenosis, see Archer (2017), Crisp (2007b, chap. 5), Davis (2011), Evans (2006a),
Feenstra (2006), Le Poidevin (2009b, sec. 6; 2013), Senor (2011), and Thompson (2006).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
44 Philosophy of Religion
to his rightful place, bearing all his divine majesty and attributes. At that point,
Christ is still human, yet he is exalted to his former status. If the doctrine of the
exaltation is true, then kenotic Christology will not provide a universal answer
to the Fundamental Problem. For there will be some time, any post-exaltation
time, at which Christ has all the attributes humans must have in addition to the
attributes of which he supposedly emptied during his earthly mission.83
Second, depending on how one understands kenotic Christology, it can
appear inconsistent with Conciliar Christology.84 For the conciliar texts teach
that Christ, even when incarnate, retained the very divine attributes kenotic
thinkers look to deny of him during his Incarnation. Cyril writes of Christ that,
while a baby, “he filled the whole of creation and was fellow ruler with him who
begot him” (Tanner 1990, 51). And Leo, discussing the very text from
Philippians 2, says that “that self-emptying whereby the invisible rendered
himself visible, and the Creator and Lord of all things chose to join the ranks
of mortals, spelled no failure of power” (Tanner 1990, 78). Christ’s power is not
diminished, according to Leo, even though he becomes a baby. This teaching –
that Christ, even while united completely to the human nature in the Incarnation,
remained with the Father in heaven, ruling all of creation – was given the
pejorative name the extra calvinisticum (roughly, “that extra thing Calvin
added”), in later Protestant polemics.85
83
For a more in-depth discussion of kenoticism and the exaltation, see Evans (2006b, 200–202),
Feenstra (1989, 144–149), and Pawl (2016d, 114–115).
84
For this argumentation spelled out in more detail, see Pawl (2016d, chap. 5, sect V.b.).
85
For the history of the use of the term, see Willis (1966, 8–25). For more recent work on the extra
calvinisticum, see Gordon (2016) and McGinnis (2014).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 45
A necessary condition for being a circle is that the shape have all its points
equidistant from a center point. And a necessary condition for being a square
is that the shape have four 90-degree angles and four straight lines of equal
length. No one shape can fulfill both those necessary conditions. So no one
shape can be both a square and a circle. You must be mistaken.
Now, suppose I responded to you by noting that you’re right concerning the
necessary conditions. Nothing can have those features in the same respect. But
you’ve overlooked that the shape I’ve drawn has all its points equidistant from
a center point according to its circularity, or qua circle, and that it has four
straight lines and four 90-degree angles according to its squareness, or qua
square.
Are all your worries now alleviated? Likely not. In fact, now we have
additional quandaries. What does it mean for one single shape to have incon-
sistent features in these different respects? If we were to look at it, would we
see four angles or not? Without further analysis, this method of solution to
both the Fundamental Problem and the Square Circle Problem (as we might
call it) is incomplete and unhelpful. It is no surprise, then, that contemporary
86
Here I borrow an analogy Hick (1977, 178) makes concerning the coherence of orthodox
Christology. See also the clever work of Angere (2017), though, who argues that there can be
square circles, and, in fact, that it is “quite likely that there are square circles in the universe”
(88). Angere includes a figure, Figure 4, on page 86, which shows a square circle (note: it looks
like a square and not like a circle).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
46 Philosophy of Religion
authors who consider this solution often charge it with “muddying the waters”
(Morris 1987, 49).87
For this reason, it behooves the proponent of this strategy to say more about
what exactly the “qua human” or “qua divine” modifier is doing in the solution.
Elsewhere I’ve distinguished four things the “qua” might be doing, then sub-
divided two of them, for a total of six qua strategies.88 Here I add a seventh
“qua” strategy. There is no space in this Element to provide a complete treat-
ment of these strategies (for that, look at chapter 6 of Pawl (2016d), which itself
is two-thirds the length of the body of this Element). Here we must be content
with a brief summary of the strategies.
Most generally, the strategies can be distinguished by what the “qua” modi-
fies. It could modify the whole of the assertion or a part. If just a part, then, since
there are three parts – “Christ,” “is,” “(im)passible” – there are three ways to
modify a part with the “qua.” It could modify the subject of the assertion
(“Christ-qua-divine”), the copula (“is-qua-divine”), or the predicate
(“[im]passible-qua-divine”).89 The remainder of this section discusses each of
these options. While each option modifies something different, the argumenta-
tive goal is the same. The goal is to revise Premises 3 and 5, claiming that,
understood in the same sense, they are not both true. That is, they all aim to
replace 3 and 5 with the following:
3*. Nothing can be both passible and impassible in the same respect.
5*. Christ is both passible and impassible in the same respect.
3* and 5* are together contradictory. Each qua theory discussed in what follows
provides some way to deny 5*, and so to deny that a contradiction has been
derived.
This first understanding of the “qua” modifier takes it to modify the whole
assertion: Qua divine, Christ is impassible. The “qua” clause serves to point out
that in virtue of which the subject has the predicate. It is because Christ is divine
that he is impassible.
Scholars have rightly criticized this understanding in the literature. For if
something is a certain way because it is another – if S is P because it is N – then it
follows that S is P. If I am warm-blooded because I am human, then I am warm-
87
See also Van Inwagen (1998, sec. 4) and Holland (2012, 74) for criticisms of the qua move.
88
See Pawl (2015; 2016b; 2016b, chap. 6).
89
For more on divisions of qua clauses, see Adams (2009), Bäck (1997; 2008, 84–87), Cross
(2005, 193–199; 2011, 455–456), Labooy (2019), Morris (1987, 48–49), and Senor (2002,
229–33).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 47
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
48 Philosophy of Religion
90
The conditional in this sentence is sometimes referred to as Leibniz’s Law. To see a response that
rejects the use of Leibniz’s Law, see the relative identity response in Section 7.2.2.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 49
expressions to the one person, it would have no means by which to claim that the
(allegedly) contradictory predicates do not imply a contradiction.91
91
For a recent defense of the strategy of this section, see Labooy (2019).
92
I discuss this qua strategy at length in Pawl (2016d, 143–150).
93
I discuss these views in depth in Pawl (2016d, 143–150).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
50 Philosophy of Religion
Both the substitutional view and the non-substitutional view, were they
employed, have a shared cost. Each would require a modification in our
standard logical formulation of arguments. For standard formulation of logic
has no means of demarcating various copulas.
Additional adverbial solutions to the Fundamental Problem are rare in the
contemporary discussion.94 One instance of a different sort of adverbial solu-
tion comes from Bohn (2012), who distinguishes, not between humanly and
divinely had predicates, but between merely, fundamentally, and essentially
true propositions.
94
Distinctions in ways of being are less rare, however. See, for instance, McDaniel (2017).
95
I discuss this version of the qua strategy at length in Pawl (2016d, 129–143). See Gorman (2014;
2016; 2017, chap. 6) and Labooy (2019) for a recent sympathetic discussion of these “qua”
clause strategies.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 51
The proponent of the view under discussion here should fight the urge to
reason as follows: “I am an animal-qua-human, so I am an animal full stop.
Similar reasoning shows that Fido is an animal full stop. So, there is a shared
term.” Such reasoning – from the qua-modified predicate to the qua-unadorned
predicate – would cause problems elsewhere. For, if generalized, we could do
the same with the predicates correctly said of Christ, in which case we are back
to passible and impassible being said of Christ full stop in the same respect.
A second problem the non-substitutional qua modifying of predicates faces
are predicates that are not apt of Christ in virtue of either nature alone, as
discussed in Section 5.2. For instance, Christ is “two-natured.” But he is not
two-natured-qua-human, and he isn’t two-natured-qua-divine. How does one
explain the qua modification of predicates here?
One thing that could be done is a restricting of which predicates get
qua modified. Maybe animal and two-natured don’t get modified. One hopes
that the reasoning in determining which to modify is something more than
merely cataloging the ones that cause problems, then labeling those as the
modified ones. One would want a principle here, to safeguard against it being
ad hoc.
The substitutional qua modifying of the predicates fares better with univocal
predication across mundane cases. For both I and the dog are animal-qua-
something. That something is different in each case, but the same predicate is
apt of each of us. Similarly, parent-of-someone can be said of both me and many
of my readers, even if it isn’t the same someone in all but one case (that is,
supposing that my wife ever reads this Element). The substitutionary qua modi-
fication of the predicates will still need some means by which to claim that
Christ is two-natured, but not two-natured due to either nature alone. It will still
require some principle for determining which predicates get modified and
which do not.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
52 Philosophy of Religion
a contradiction, and we are supposing here that no contradictions are true. But
what if they were related, not as contradictories, but as subcontraries? That is to
say, what if they can both be apt of a thing, but it is false that they can both be
inapt of a thing? I’ve presented the logic in detail elsewhere (Pawl 2014a;
2016d, chap. 7). Here I summarize it.
To see the distinction between contradictories and subcontraries, consider
where the negation goes in the analysis of the predicate “impassible.” Is to be
impassible not to be able to be causally affected, with the negation on the
outside, at the beginning of the analysis? Or does the negation go on the inside,
for instance, by saying that to be impassible is to have a nature that is not able
to be causally affected?96 Understood in this second way, provided that one
person has two natures, where one such nature can be causally affected and the
other cannot be causally affected, then that one person can fulfill the condi-
tions required for being both passible and impassible at the same time.
Provided that everything has at least one nature (Christ alone, on traditional
Christianity, has more than one), that nature will be either causally affectable
or not. So everything will be either passible or impassible, and it is possible for
one thing – a two-natured person – to be both. In other words, the predicates
“passible” and “impassible” will be related as subcontraries, as defined in the
previous paragraph. Is Christ passible? Yes; he has a nature that can be
causally affected, and that’s what’s required to be passible. Is Christ impass-
ible? Yes; he has a nature that cannot be causally affected, and that’s what’s
required to be impassible. Both terms are truthfully predicated of the one
person Jesus Christ.
In what sense are these terms said in the same respect of Christ? Well,
“passible” is said in exactly the same way it is said of me. And “impass-
ible” is said in exactly the same way it is said of the Holy Spirit. And
neither I nor the Holy Spirit is both impassible and passible, owing to the
fact that each of us has but one nature, and no one-natured thing could
fulfill the conditions required for being both passible and impassible.
Those two predicates would imply a contradiction were they both said of
me. Given that they are contradictory when said of one-natured me, they
must be said in the same respect of me. But they are said in those very
same respects of Christ as they would be of me. So they are said in the
same respect of Christ as well.
This view too faces some objections. It requires us to understand natures such
that they can be causally affected. Such a notion of natures is contested. That
96
This is an old distinction. Gabriel Biel (died 1495) used exactly this strategy to solve the
Fundamental Problem; see Pawl (2019a, 442–447).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
The Incarnation 53
7.6 Conclusion
This section has discussed the Fundamental Problem of Christology – the
question of how one thing could be both God and human, since, as God, he
must have certain features, and, as human, have apparently contradictory
features. For ease of explication, the section focused on one pair of features –
impassibility and passibility – though the intent was to generalize to other
features. The section canvassed four types of response, many subdivided
further.
First, one might revise standard logic. This can be done by swapping absolute
identity for relative identity. Or it can be done by rejecting the universal
applicability of logical inference (as Luther does) or by accepting universal
applicability but rejecting the validity of some classical inference forms, as
Beall does.
Second, one might deny some of the worrisome predicates of Christ. Perhaps
he isn’t really impassible. Or perhaps he isn’t really ignorant. Or perhaps he has
both allegedly contradictory predicates apt of him, but he doesn’t have them apt
of him at the same time. In any case, this suite of strategies takes its defining
feature to be denying some predicate of Christ, either at a time or categorically.
Third, one might accept standard logic, accept that the worrisome pairs of
predicates are both apt (true) of Christ at the same time, but deny that they are
true in the same respect. This move is typically made with the use of “qua”
clauses. One must ask: how does the “qua” work? I provided four ways of
understanding it. The “qua” clause could modify the whole assertion, modify
the subject of the assertion, modify the copula, or modify the predicate. The first
and last two methods further subdivide.
Fourth and finally, one might accept standard logic, accept the worrisome
pairs of predicates are true of Christ at the same time, in the same respect, but
deny that the worrisome predicate pairs are inconsistent. To do this, one could
revise one’s understanding of the predicate pairs so that they are subcontraries,
each apt of a thing in virtue of some nature it has. Given that Christ has two
natures, he (and only he, on traditional Christian doctrine) is in a position to
satisfy both apparently contradictory predicates. Those predicates are inconsist-
ent for all one-natured other things.
97
For more on this robust notion of the human nature, see Pawl (2016d, 227–231; 2019b, 29–30;
2020).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
54 Philosophy of Religion
Each method has its own costs and benefits, which I have only gestured
toward here, while providing references to fuller discussions in the footnotes.
8 Conclusion
This Element has canvassed the current philosophical work on the doctrine of
the Incarnation, the Christian view that God the Son assumed a human nature,
and so became human. It focused on the metaphysical aspects of the traditional
doctrine as espoused in the ecumenical councils of the first eight centuries of the
Christian community, prior to the Great Schism.
The goal of this Element has been to present the content of Conciliar
Christology, the main philosophical objection to that doctrine, and the most
common responses to that objection. My hope is that the reader can use this
information, along with the copious footnotes, to investigate the doctrine of the
Incarnation more deeply.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
References
Adams, Marilyn McCord. 1985. “The Metaphysics of the Incarnation in Some
Fourteenth-Century Franciscans.” In Essays Honoring Allan B. Wolter, edited
by William A. Frank and Girard J. Etzkorn, 21–57. New York: Franciscan
Institute.
1999. What Sort of Human Nature? Medieval Philosophy and the Systematics
of Christology. Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press.
2000. Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
2004. “The Metaphysical Size Gap.” Sewanee Theological Review 47 (2):
129–144.
2005. “What’s Metaphysically Special about Supposits? Some Medieval
Variations on Aristotelian Substance.” Aristotelian Society
Supplementary Volume 79 (1): 15–52.
2006. Christ and Horrors: The Coherence of Christology. 1st edition.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
2009. “Christ As God-Man, Metaphysically Construed.” In Oxford Readings
in Philosophical Theology, edited by Michael C. Rea, 239–263. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
de Aldama, SJ, Joseph A., and Iesu Solano, SJ. 2014. Sacrae Theologiae Summa
IIIA: On the Incarnate Word • On the Blessed Virgin Mary. Translated by
Kenneth Baker, SJ. 1st edition. Saddle River, NJ: Keep the Faith.
Alfeyev, Metropolitan Hilarion. 2012. Orthodox Christianity: Doctrine and
Teaching of the Orthodox Church. Yonkers, NY: St. Vladimirs Seminary Press.
Anatolios, Khaled. 2004. Athanasius. New York: Routledge.
Angere, Staffan. 2017. “The Square Circle.” Metaphilosophy 48 (1–2): 79–95.
https://doi.org/10.1111/meta.12224.
Aquinas, Thomas. 1954. The Disputed Questions on Truth (in Three Volumes).
Translated by Robert Schmidt. Chicago: Regnery
2012. Commentary on the Letter of Saint Paul to the Romans. Translated by
Fabian R. Larcher, John Mortensen, and Enrique Alarcón. Lander, WY:
Aquinas Institute for the Study of Sacred Doctrine.
2013. Commentary on the Gospel of Matthew 1–12. Lander, WY: Aquinas
Institute for the Study of Sacred Doctrine.
Arcadi, James M. 2018. “Recent Developments in Analytic Christology.”
Philosophy Compass 0 (0): e12480. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3
.12480.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
56 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
References 57
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
58 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
References 61
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
62 References
McKinley, John Elton. 2009. Tempted for Us: Theological Models and the
Practical Relevance of Christ’s Impeccability and Temptation. Eugene,
OR: Paternoster.
2011. “Four Patristic Models of Jesus Christ’s Impeccability and
Temptation.” Perichoresis 9 (1): 29–66.
2015. “A Model of Jesus Christ’s Two Wills in View of Theology Proper and
Anthropology.” Southern Baptist Journal of Theology 19 (1): 69–89.
McNabb, Tyler Dalton. 2018. Religious Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Merricks, Trenton. 2007. “The Word Made Flesh: Dualism, Physicalism, and
the Incarnation” In Persons: Human and Divine, edited by Peter van
Inwagen and Dean Zimmerman, 281–301. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Milyavskaya, Marina, Michael Inzlicht, Nora Hope, and Richard Koestner.
2015. “Saying ‘No’ to Temptation: Want-to Motivation Improves Self-
Regulation by Reducing Temptation Rather than by Increasing Self-
Control.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 109 (4):
677–693. https://doi.org/10.1037/pspp0000045.
Moloney, Raymond. 2000. Knowledge of Christ. 1st edition. London;
Bloomsbury Academic.
Moreland, J. P., and William Lane Craig. 2003. Philosophical Foundations for
a Christian Worldview. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic.
Morris, Thomas V. 1983. “Impeccability.” Analysis 43 (2): 106–112.
1986. “Perfection and Power.” International Journal for Philosophy of
Religion 20 (2/3): 165–168.
1987. The Logic of God Incarnate. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
2009. “The Metaphysics of God Incarnate.” In Oxford Readings in
Philosophical Theology, edited by Michael C. Rea and Thomas P. Flint,
211–224. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mullins, R. T. 2016. The End of the Timeless God. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Murray, Michael, and Michael C. Rea. 2008. An Introduction to the Philosophy
of Religion. 1st edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nevitt, Turner C. 2016. “Aquinas on the Death of Christ.” American Catholic
Philosophical Quarterly 90 (1): 77–99.
O’Collins, Gerald. 1995. Christology: A Biblical, Historical, and Systematic
Study of Jesus Christ. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
2002. “The Incarnation: The Critical Issues.” In The Incarnation, edited by
Stephen T. Davis, Daniel Kendall, and Gerald O’Collins, 1–30. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
66 References
Oord, Thomas Jay, William Hasker, and Dean Zimmerman. 2011. God in an Open
Universe: Science, Metaphysics, and Open Theism. Eugene,OR: Pickwick.
Page, Ben. 2019. “Wherein Lies the Debate? Concerning Whether God Is a
Person.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 85 (3):
297–317. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-018–9694-x.
Pawl, Timothy. 2012. “Transubstantiation, Tropes and Truthmakers.” American
Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 86 (1): 71–96.
2014a. “A Solution to the Fundamental Philosophical Problem of
Christology.” Journal of Analytic Theology 2: 61–85.
2014b. “The Freedom of Christ and Explanatory Priority.” Religious Studies
50 (2): 157–173. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000309.
2014c. “The Freedom of Christ and the Problem of Deliberation.”
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 75 (3): 233–247.
2015. “Conciliar Christology and the Problem of Incompatible Predications.”
Scientia et Fides 3 (2): 85–106.
2016a. “Brian Hebblethwaite’s Arguments against Multiple Incarnations.”
Religious Studies 52 (1): 117–130. https://doi.org/10.1017/S00344125
14000626.
2016b. “Temporary Intrinsics and Christological Predication.” In Oxford
Studies in Philosophy of Religion, Volume 7, edited by Jonathan
L Kvanvig, 157–189. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
2016c. “Thomistic Multiple Incarnations.” Heythrop Journal 57 (2):
359–370. https://doi.org/10.1111/heyj.12230.
2016d. In Defense of Conciliar Christology: A Philosophical Essay. 1st
edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
2018. “Conciliar Christology and the Consistency of Divine Immutability
with a Mutable, Incarnate God.” Nova et Vetera 16 (3): 913–937.
2019a. “Explosive Theology: A Reply to Jc Beall’s ‘Christ –
A Contradiction.’” Journal of Analytic Theology 7: 440–451.
2019b. In Defense of Extended Conciliar Christology: A Philosophical
Essay. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
2020. “The Metaphysics of the Incarnation: Christ’s Human Nature.” In
Herausforderungen Und Modifikationen Des Klassischen Theismus,
edited by Thomas Marschler and Thomas Schärtl, forthcoming. Munster:
Aschendorff.
Pawl, Timothy, and Mark Spencer. 2016. “Christologically Inspired,
Empirically Motivated Hylomorphism.” Res Philosophica 91 (1):
137–160.
Pawl, Timothy, and Kevin Timpe. 2009. “Incompatibilism, Sin, and Free Will in
Heaven.” Faith and Philosophy 26 (4): 398–419.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
References 67
Rota, Michael. 2010. “The Eternity Solution to the Problem of Human Freedom
and Divine Foreknowledge.” European Journal for Philosophy of Religion
2 (1): 165–186.
Sanders, John. 1998. The God Who Risks: A Theology of Providence. Downers
Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.
Scarpelli, Therese. 2007. “Bonaventure’s Christocentric Epistemology: Christ’s
Human Knowledge As the Epitome of Illumination in De Scientia Christi.”
Franciscan Studies 65 (1): 63–86.
Schmaus, Michael. 1971. Dogma 3: God and His Christ. 1st edition. Mission,
KS: Sheed and Ward.
Senor, Thomas D. 2002. “Incarnation, Timelessness, and Leibniz’s Law
Problems.” In God and Time: Essays on the Divine Nature, edited by
Gregory E. Ganssle and David M. Woodruff, 220–235. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
2011. “Drawing on Many Traditions: An Ecumenical Kenotic Christology.”
In The Metaphysics of the Incarnation, edited by Anna Marmodoro and
Jonathan Hill, 88–113. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sharpe, Kevin W. 2017. “The Incarnation, Soul-Free: Physicalism, Kind
Membership, and the Incarnation.” Religious Studies 53 (1): 117–131.
https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034412515000530.
Sollier, Joseph. 1907. “Apollinarianism.” In The Catholic Encyclopedia.
New York: Robert Appleton. www.newadvent.org/cathen/01615b.htm.
Spence, Alan. 2008. Christology: A Guide for the Perplexed. London; T &
T Clark.
Stump, Eleonore. 1989. “Review of Morris’ The Logic of God Incarnate.” Faith
and Philosophy 6: 218–223.
1999. “Orthodoxy and Heresy.” Faith and Philosophy 16 (2): 147–163.
https://doi.org/10.5840/faithphil199916217.
2004. “Aquinas’s Metaphysics of the Incarnation.” In The Incarnation, edited
by Stephen T. Davis, Daniel Kendall, and Gerald O’Collins, 197–218.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
2005. Aquinas. New York: Routledge.
2019. Atonement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stump, Eleonore, and Norman Kretzmann. 1981. “Eternity.” Journal of
Philosophy 78 (8): 429–458. https://doi.org/10.2307/2026047.
1991. “Prophecy, Past Truth, and Eternity.” Philosophical Perspectives 5:
395–424. https://doi.org/10.2307/2214103.
Sturch, Richard. 1991. The Word and the Christ: An Essay in Analytic
Christology. Oxford; Oxford University Press.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
References 69
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
Acknowledgments
I thank those who participated in a workshop on the manuscript of this book at
the Logos Institute for Analytic and Exegetical Theology (University of St
Andrews): Dennis Bray, Joshua Cockayne, Preston Hill, Matthew Joss, Carol
King, Derek King, Christa McKirland, Jonathan Rutledge, Andrew Torrance,
and Koert Verhagen. I thank the Logos Institute for a senior research fellowship
(2019), during which this book was written, and the Templeton Religious Trust
(ID: TRT0095/58801) for funding that fellowship. I thank Jc Beall, Mark
DelCogliano, David Efird – whose recent death is a tragic loss in so many
ways – W. Matthews Grant, Hud Hudson, Noah Jones, Gavin Kerr, Ryan
Mullins, Ben Page, Faith Pawl, Michael Rea, Mark Spencer, Jim Stone,
Allison Timpe (but not Kevin Timpe), and Chandler Warren for comments on
the manuscript. I thank the John Templeton Foundation for a grant (ID: 61012),
which provided some of the research time I used in the writing of this book.
I thank Fr. George Welzbacher for reading the entire manuscript and giving
careful comments in his official role as Censor Librorum for the Archdiocese of
St. Paul and Minneapolis. I thank Fr. Welzbacher for providing a Nihil Obstat to
the book, and Most Reverend Bernard A. Hebda, Archbishop of Saint Paul and
Minneapolis, for his Imprimatur.
This book is dedicated to Faith Pawl, an excellent human. (The praise I
intended to include here was brilliant, moving, and longer than word limits
allow. Trust me: it was the sort of thing you dream of reading about yourself, and
not a bit of it was undeserved.)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
Philosophy of Religion
Yujin Nagasawa
University of Birmingham
Yujin Nagasawa is Professor of Philosophy and Co-director of the John Hick Centre for
Philosophy of Religion at the University of Birmingham. He is currently President of the
British Society for the Philosophy of Religion. He is a member of the editorial board of
Religious Studies, the International Journal for Philosophy of Religion and Philosophy
Compass.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341
Philosophy of Religion
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 112.203.39.42, on 30 Sep 2020 at 13:53:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108558341