Psychology
Psychology
https://books.google.com
PUBLISHERS
JAMES
& CO .
HOLT
HENRY
LANE
MEDICAL
LIBRARY
STANFORD
K121
J28
1913 STOR
Psycholo gy.
by
William
James
24503415411
J.
Schi
llin
g
2. Dept. /1915
.
LANE
JU
SE AND
NI
ER
STANFORD
VI
LELE
UNIV
MP
TH
OR RSITY
RE
NS
E
MEDICAL LIBRARY
OF L
A
SE
1885
Library of
Dr.Walter Schilling
971
d
shi
BY WILLIAM JAMES
The Principles of Psychology. 2 vols. 8vo. $5.00
Edcl. net. New York: Henry Holt & Co.
1890.
Psychology: Briefer Course. 12mo. $1.60 Edcl.
net. New York : Henry Holt & Co. 1892.
The Varieties of Religious Experience. $3.20 net.
New York : Longmans, Green & Co. 1902.
The Will to Believe, and Other Essays in Pop-
ular Philosophy. 12mo. $2.00. New York :
Longmans, Green & Co. 1897.
Is Life Worth Living ? 18mo. 50 cents net.
Philadelphia: S. B. Weston, 1305 Arch Street.
1896.
Human Immortality : Two supposed Objections
to the Doctrine. 16mo. $1.00. Boston:
Houghton, Mifflin & Co. 1898.
Pragmatism. $1.25 net. New York: Longmans,
Green & Co. 1907.
The Meaning of Truth : A Sequel to Prag-
matism . $ 1.25 net. New York: Longmans,
Green & Co. 1909.
A Pluralistic Universe. $1.50 net. New York :
Longmans, Green & Co. 1909.
Memories and Studies. $1.75 net. New York:
Longmans, Green & Co. 1911.
Some Problems in Philosophy. $1.25 net. New
York: Longmans, Green & Co. 1911.
Essays in Radical Empiricism . $1.25 net. New
York: Longmans, Green & Co. 1912.
Talks to Teachers on Psychology: and to
Students on Some of Life's Ideals. 12mo.
$1.50 Edcl. net. New York: Henry Holt &
Co. 1899.
On Some of Life's Ideals. "On a Certain Blind-
ness in Human Beings" and "What Makes
a Life Significant." Reprinted from Talks to
Teachers. 16mo. 50 cents net. New York:
Henry Holt & Co. 1912.
The Literary Remains of Henry James. Edited,
with an introduction, by William James.
With Portrait. Crown 8vo. $2.00. Boston:
Houghton, Mifflin & Co. 1885.
AMERICAN SCIENCE SERIES, BRIEFER COURSE
PSYCHOLOGY
BY
WILLIAM JAMES
NEW YORK
HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY
1913
Copyright, 1892,
BY
HENRY HOLT & CO.
CHAPTER L
PAGE
INTRODUCTORY 1
Psychology defined ; psychology as a natural science, its
data, 1. The human mind and its environment, 3. The pos-
tulate that all consciousness has cerebral activity for its condi-
tion , 5.
CHAPTER II.
SENSATION IN GENERAL ·
Incoming nerve -currents, 9. Terminal organs, 10. ' Spe-
cific energies, ' 11. Sensations cognize qualities , 13. Knowl-
edge of acquaintance and knowledge-about, 14 Objects of
sensation appear in space, 15. The intensity of sensations, 16.
Weber's law, 17. Fechner's law, 21. Sensations are not
psychic compounds, 23. The law of relativity . 24. Effects
of contrast, 26.
CHAPTER III.
SIGHT • 28
The eye, 28. Accommodation, 32. Convergence , binocular
vision, 33. Double images, 36. Distance, 39. Size, color
40. After-images, 43. Intensity of luminous objects. 45 .
CHAPTER IV .
HEARING 47
The ear, 47. The qualities of sound, 43. Pitch, 44. Tim
bre, ' 45. Analysis of compound air-waves, 56. No fusion of
elementary sensations of sound, 57. Harmony and discord, 58.
Discrimination by the ear, 59.
vii
viii CONTENTS.
CHAPTER V.
PAGE
TOUCH, THE TEMPERATURE SENSE, THE MUSCULAR SENSE,
AND PAIN · • 60
End-organs in the skin, 60. Touch, sense of pressure, 60.
Localization, 51. Sensibility to temperature, 63. The muscu
lar sense, 65. Pain, 67.
CHAPTER VI.
SENSATIONS OF MOTION 70
The feeling of motion over surfaces, 70. Feelings in joints,
74. The sense of translation, the sensibility of the semicircu
lar canals, 75.
CHAPTER VII.
THE STRUCTURE OF THE BRAIN 78
Embryological sketch, 78. Practical dissection of the sheep's
brain, 81
CHAPTER VIII.
THE FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN 91
General idea of nervous function, 91 . The frog's nerve-
centres, 92. The pigeon's nerve-centres, 96. What the hemi-
spheres do, 97. The automaton-theory, 101 . The localization
of functions, 104. Brain and mind have analogous ' elements,'
sensory and motor, 105. The motor zone, 106 . Aphasia, 108.
The visual region, 110. Mental blindness, 112. The auditory
region, mental deafness, 113. Other centres, 116.
CHAPTER IX.
SOME GENERAL CONDITIONS OF NEURAL ACTIVITY 120
The nervous discharge, 120. Reaction-time, 121. Simple
reactions, 122. Complicated reactions, 124. The summation
of stimuli, 128. Cerebral blood- supply, 130. Brain-thermome
try, 131. Phosphorus and thought, 132.
CHAPTER X.
HABIT • 134
Its importance, and its physical basis, 134 Due to pathways
formed in the centres, 136. Its practical uses. 138. Concate-
CONTENTS. 1x
PAGE
nated acts, 140. Necessity for guiding sensations in secondarily
automatic performances, 141. Pedagogical maxims concerning
the formation of habits, 142.
CHAPTER XI.
THE STREAM OF CONSCIOUSNESS · 151
Analytic order of our study, 151. Every state of mind forms
part of a personal consciousness, 152. The same state of mind
is never had twice, 154. Permanently recurring ideas are a
fiction, 156. Every personal consciousness is continuous, 157.
Substantive and transitive states, 160. Every object appears
with a ' fringe ' of relations, 163. The ' topic ' of the thought,
167. Thought may be rational in any sort of imagery, 168.
Consciousness is always especially interested in some one part
of its object, 170.
CHAPTER XII.
THE SELF • 176
The Me and the I, 176. The material Me, 177. The social
Me, 179. The spiritual Me, 181. Self-appreciation , 182. Self-
seeking, bodily, social, and spiritual, 184. Rivalry of the Mes,
186. Their hierarchy, 190. Teleology of self-interest, 193.
The I, or ' pure ego, ' 195. Thoughts are not compounded of
' fused ' sensations, 196. The ' soul ' as a combining medium,
200. The sense of personal identity, 201. Explained by iden-
tity of function in successive passing thoughts, 203. Mutations
of the self, 205. Insane delusions, 207. Alternating person.
alities, 210. Mediumships or possessions, 212. Who is the
Thinker, 215.
CHAPTER XIII.
ATTENTION 217
The narrowness of the field of consciousness, 217. Dis-
persed attention, 218. To how much can we attend at once ?
219. The varieties of attention, 220. Voluntary attention, its
momentary character, 224. To keep our attention , an object
must change, 226. Genius and attention , 227. Attention's
physiological conditions, 228. The sense-organ must be
adapted, 229. The idea of the object must be aroused, 232
Pedagogic remarks, 236. Attention and free- will, 237.
X CONTENTS.
CHAPTER XIV .
PAGE
CONCEPTION . 239
Different states of mind can mean the same, 239. Concep-
tions of abstract, of universal, and of problematic objects, 240.
6
The thought of the same ' is not the same thought over
n
agai , 243.
CHAPTER XV.
DISCRIMINATION • 244
Discrimination and association ; definition of discrimination ,
244. Conditions which favor it, 245. The sensation of differ-
ence, 246. Differences inferred, 248. The analysis of com-
pound objects, 248. To be easily singled out, a quality should
already be separately known, 250. Dissociation by varying
concomitants, 251. Practice improves discrimination, 252.
CHAPTER XVI.
ASSOCIATION C 253
The order of our ideas, 253. It is determined by cerebral
laws, 255. The ultimate cause of association is habit, 256.
The elementary law in association , 257. Indeterminateness of
its results, 258. Total recall, 259. Partial recall, and the law
of interest, 261. Frequency, recency, vividness, and emotional
congruity tend to determine the object recalled , 264. Focalized
recall, or ' association by similarity, ' 267. Voluntary trains of
thought, 271. The solution of problems, 273. Similarity no
elementary law ; summary and conclusion, 277.
CHAPTER XVII.
THE SENSE OF TIME • 280
The sensible present has duration , 280. We have no sense
for absolutely empty time, 281. We measure duration by the
events which succeed in it, 283. The feeling of past time is a
present feeling, 285. Due to a constant cerebral condition, 286.
CHAPTER XVIII.
MEMORY . 287
What it is, 287. It involves both retention and recall, 289.
Both elements explained by paths formed b, habit in the brain,
290. Two conditions of a good memorv , persistence and nu
CONTENTS. xi
PAGE
merousness of paths, 292. Cramming, 295. One's native re-
tentiveness is unchangeable, 296. Improvement of the mem-
ory, 298. Recognition, 299. Forgetting, 300. Pathological
conditions, 301.
CHAPTER XIX.
[MAGINATION . 302
What it is, 302. Imaginations differ from man to man ; Gal-
ton's statistics of visual imagery, 303 Images of sounds, 306.
Images of movement, 307. Images of touch, 308. Loss of
images in aphasia, 309. The neural process in imagination.
310.
CHAPTER XX
PERCEPTION . 812
Perception and sensation compared, 312. The perceptive
state of mind is not a compound, 313. Perception is of definite
things, 316. Illusions, 317. First type: inference of the more
usual object, 318. Second type : inference of the object of
which our mind is full, 321. Apperception,' 326. Genius
and old-fogyism, 327. The physiological process in percep-
tion, 329. Hallucinations, 330.
CHAPTER XXI.
THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE 335
The attribute of extensity belongs to all objects of sensation,
335. The construction of real space, 337. The processes
which it involves : 1 ) Subdivision , 338; 2) Coalescence of differ-
ent sensible data into one thing, ' 339; 3) Location in an en-
vironment, 340; 4) Place in a series of positions, 341 ; 5) Meas.
urement, 342. Objects which are signs, and objects which
are realities, 345. The ' third dimension, ' Berkeley's theory of
distance, 346. The part played by the intellect in space-per-
ception, 349.
CHAPTER XXII.
REASONING • 351
What it is, 351. it involves the use of abstract characters,
353. What is meant by an ' essential ' character, 354. The
' essence ' varies with the subjective interest, 358. The two
xii CONTENTS.
PAGE
great points in reasoning, ' sagacity ' and ' wisdom,' 360. Sa-
gacity, 362. The help given by association by similarity, 364.
The reasoning powers of brutes, 367.
CHAPTER XXIII.
CONSCIOUSNESS AND MOVEMENT . 870
All consciousness is motor, 370. Three classes of movement
to which it leads, 372.
CHAPTER XXIV.
EMOTION · • 373
Emotions compared with instincts, 373. The varieties of
emotion are innumerable, 374 The cause of their varieties,
375. The feeling, in the coarser emotions, results from the
bodily expression, 375. This view must not be called material-
istic, 380. This view explains the great variability of emotion,
381. A corollary verified , 382. An objection replied to, 383.
The subtler emotions, 384. Description of fear, 385. Gene.
sis of the emotional reactions, 386.
CHAPTER XXV.
INSTINCT • 391
Its definition, 391. Every instinct is an impulse, 392. In-
stincts are not always blind or invariable, 395. Two principles
of non-uniformity, 398. Enumeration of instincts in man, 406.
Description of fear, 407.
CHAPTER XXVI.
WILL . 415
Voluntary acts, 415. They are secondary performances, 415.
No third kind of idea is called for, 418. The motor-cue, 420.
Ideo-motor action , 432. Action after deliberation, 428. Five
chief types of decision, 429. The feeling of effort, 434.
Healthiness of will, 435. Unhealthiness of will, 436. The
explosive will : (1) from defective inhibition, 437 ; (2) from
exaggerated impulsion, 439. The obstructed will, 441. Effort
feels like an original force, 442. Pleasure and pain as
springs of action , 444. What holds attention determines ac-
tion , 448. Will is a relation between the mind and its
CONTENTS. xiii
PAGE
' ideas, ' 449. Volitional effort is effort of attention, 450. The
question of free- will, 455. Ethical importance of the phe-
nomenon of effort, 458.
EPILOGUE.
PSYCHOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY • • 461
What the word metaphysics means, 461. Relation of con-
sciousness to the brain, 462. The relation of states of mind to
their ' objects, ' 464. The changing character of consciousness,
466. States of consciousness themselves are not verifiable
facts, 467.
6
PSYCHOLOGY.
CHAPTER I.
INTRODUCTORY .
SENSATION IN GENERAL.
* Thus the optic nerve-fibres are traced to the occipital lobes, the
olfactory tracts go to the lower part of the temporal lobe (hippocampal
convolution), the auditory nerve-fibres pass first to the cerebellum,
and probably from thence to the upper part of the temporal lobe.
These anatomical terms used in this chapter will be explained later,
The cortex is the gray surface of the convolutions.
12 PSYCHOLOGY.
6
be given in a pure sensation) all the categories of the
understanding ' are contained . It has externality , objec-
tivity, unity, substantiality, causality, in the full sense in
which any later object or system of objects has these things.
Here the young knower meets and greets his world ; and
the miracle of knowledge bursts forth, as Voltaire says, as
much in the infant's lowest sensation as in the highest
achievement of a Newton's brain.
The physiological condition of this first sensible experi-
ence is probably many nerve-currents coming in from
various peripheral organs at once ; but this multitude of
organic conditions does not prevent the consciousness from
being one consciousness. We shall see as we go on that
it can be one consciousness, even though it be due to
the coöperation of numerous organs and be a conscious-
ness of many things together. The Object which the
numerous inpouring currents of the baby bring to his
consciousness is one big blooming buzzing Confusion.
'That Confusion is the baby's universe ; and the universe of
all of us is still to a great extent such a Confusion, poten-
tially resolvable, and demanding to be resolved, but not
yet actually resolved, into parts. It appears from first to
last as a space-occupying thing. So far as it is unanalyzed
and unresolved we may be said to know it sensationally ;
but as fast as parts are distinguished in it and we become
aware of their relations, our knowledge becomes perceptual
or even conceptual, and as such need not concern us in the
present chapter.
The Intensity of Sensations. -A light may be so weak as
not sensibly to dispel the darkness, a sound so low as not
to be heard, a contact so faint that we fail to notice it. In
other words, a certain finite amount of the outward stimu-
lus is required to produce any sensation of its presence at
all. This is called by Fechner the law of the threshold-
something must be stepped over before the object can gain
entrance to the mind. An impression just above the
threshold is called the minimum visibile, audibile, etc
SENSATION IN GENERAL. 17
81
2
FIG. 1.
cause increases. If there were no threshold, and if every
equal increment in the outer stimulus produced an equal
increment in the sensation's intensity, a simple straight line
would represent graphically the curve ' of the relation.
between the two things. Let the horizontal line stand for
the scale of intensities of the objective stimulus, so that at
0 it has no intensity, at 1 intensity 1 , and so forth. Let
the verticals dropped from the slanting line stand for the
sensations aroused. At 0 there will be no sensation ; at 1
there will be a sensation represented by the length of the
vertical S -1, at ? the sensation will be represented by
18 PSYCHOLOGY.
0 2 3 8
FIG. 2.
“ Every one knows that in the stilly night we hear things unnoticed
in the noise of day. The gentle ticking of the clock, the air circulat-
ing through the chimney, the cracking of the chairs in the room, and
a thousand other slight noises, impress themselves upon our ear It
is equally well known that in the confused hubbub of the streets, or
the clamor of a railway, we may lose not only what our neighbo
says to us, but even not hear the sound of our own voice. The star
SENSATION IN GENERAL. 19
" These figures are far from giving as accurate a measure as might
be desired. But at least they are fit to convey a general notion of the
relative discriminative susceptibility of the different senses. The
important law which gives in so simple a form the relation of the
sensation to the stimulus that calls it forth was first discovered by the
physiologist Ernst Heinrich Weber to obtain in special cases. "' *
the line then neutralize each other in the sum, and the nor
mal sensibility, if there be one ( that is, the sensibility due
to constant causes as distinguished from these accidental
ones), stands revealed . The methods of getting the aver-
age all have their difficulties and their snares, and contro-
versy over them has become very subtle indeed . As an
instance of how laborious some of the statistical methods
are, and how patient German investigators can be, I may
say that Fechner himself, in testing Weber's law for
weights by the so-called ' method of true and false cases,'
tabulated and computed no less than 24,576 separate judg-
ments.
Sensations are not compounds. The fundamental objec-
tion to Fechner's whole attempt seems to be this, that
although the outer causes of our sensations may have many
parts, every distinguishable degree, as well as every dis-
tinguishable quality, of the sensation itself appears to be
a unique fact of consciousness. Each sensation is a com-
plete integer. " A strong one," as Dr. Münsterberg says,
" is not the multiple of a weak one, or a compound of
many weak ones, but rather something entirely new, and as
it were incomparable, so that to seek a measurable differ-
ence between strong and weak sonorous, luminous, or ther-
mic sensations would seem at first sight as senseless as to
try to compute mathematically the difference between salt
and sour, or between headache and toothache. It is clear
that if in the stronger sensation of light the weaker sen .
sation is not contained, it is unpsychological to say that the
former differs from the latter by a certain increment." *
Surely our feeling of scarlet is not a feeling of pink with a
lot more pink added ; it is something quite other than
pink. Similarly with our sensation of an electric arc-light :
it does not contain that of many smoky tallow candles in
itself. Every sensation presents itself as an indivisible.
unit ; and it is quite impossible to read any clear meaning
into the notion that they are masses of units combined.
* Beiträge zur exp. Psychol. , Heft 3, p. 4.
24 PSYCHOLOGY.
when the tuning-fork was heard, etc., etc. The most famil-
lar examples of this sort of thing seem to be the increase of
pain by noise or light, and the increase of nausea by all
concomitant sensations.
Effects of Contrast. -The best-known examples of the way
in which one nerve-current modifies another are the phe-
nomena of what is known as ' simultaneous color-contrast.'
Take a number of sheets of brightly and differently col-
ored papers, lay on each of them a bit of one and the same
kind of gray paper, then cover each sheet with some trans-
parent white paper, which softens the look of both the gray
paper and the colored ground. The gray patch will appear
in each case tinged by the color complementary to the
ground ; and so different will the several pieces appear
that no observer, before raising the transparent paper, will
believe them all cut out of the same gray. Helmholtz has
interpreted these results as being due to a false application
of an inveterate habit—that, namely, of making allowance
for the color of the medium through which things are seen.
The same thing, in the blue light of a clear sky, in the red-
dish-yellow light of a candle, in the dark brown light of a
polished mahogany table which may reflect its image, is
always judged of its own proper color, which the mind adds
out of its own knowledge to the appearance, thereby cor-
recting the falsifying medium. In the cases of the papers,
according to Helmholtz, the mind believes the color of the
ground, subdued by the transparent paper, to be faintly
spread over the gray patch. But a patch to look gray
through such a colored film would have really to be of the
complementary color to the film. Therefore it is of the
complementary color, we think, and proceed to see it of
that color.
This theory has been shown to be untenable by Hering.
The discussion of the facts is too minute for recapitulation
here, but suffice it to say that it proves the phenomenon
to be physiological-a case of the way in which, when sen-
sory nerve-currents run in together, the effect of each on
SENSATION IN GENERAL. 27
SIGHT.
Cam ant.
Iris
Preil
Lens Conj.
Co p
m.
Ret.
Chon
Selen
Fov. c.
FIG. 3.
processes before they were torn away from its suspensory ligament.
A fine capillary tube may now be used to insufflate the clear ring,
just below the letter p in Fig. 3, and thus to reveal the suspensory
ligament itself.
All these parts can be seen in section in a frozen eye or one hard-
ened in alcohol.
30 PSYCHOLOGY.
Ch
R
Ch.
S
Nop P
Ch
F
R
Ch
S
FIG. 5.-Scheme of retinal fibres, after Küss. Nop.
optic nerve; S, sclerotic ; Ch, choroid ; R, retina;
FIG. 4. P, papilla (blind spot) ; F, fovea.
that the light-waves traverse the translucent nerve-fibres,
and the cellular and granular layers of the retina, before
they touch the rods and cones themselves. (See Fig. 5.)
SIGHT. 31
FIG. 6.
Cornea
Ciliary muscle Ciliary muscle
relaxed. Iris. contracted.
LENS
Ciliary Process.
FIG. 7.
will then see the two black spots swim together , as it were,
and combine into one, which appears situated between their
original two positions and as if opposite the root of his
nose. This combined spot is the result of the spots oppo-
site both eyes being seen in the same place. But in addi-
tion to the combined spot, each eye sees also the spot opposite
the other eye. To the right eye this appears to the left of
the combined spot, to the left eye it appears to the right
of it ; so that what is seen is three spots, of which the
middle one is seen by both eyes, and is flanked by two
FIG. 8.
others, each seen by one. That such are the facts can be
tested by interposing some small opaque object so as to
cut off the vision of either of the spots in the figure from
the other eye. A vertical partition in the median plane,
going from the paper to the nose, will effectually confine
each eye's vision to the spot in front of it, and then the
single combined spot will be all that appears. *
If, instead of two identical spots, we use two different
figures, or two differently colored spots, as objects for the
two fovea to look at, they still are seen in the same place;
but since they cannot appear as a single object, they appear
there alternately displacing each other from the view. This
is the phenomenon called retinal rivalry.
As regards the parts of the retinæ round about the foveæ,
a similar correspondence obtains. Any impression on the
al ar
FIG. 9.
L' R R'
FIG. 10.
FIG. 11.
farther off, their apparent size, and the modifications their retinal
images experience by aërial perspective, come in to help. The rela
tive distance of objects is easiest determined by moving the eyes ; all
stationary objects then appear displaced in the opposite direction (as
for example when we look out of the window of a railway car) and
those nearest most rapidly; from the different apparent rates of move.
ment we can tell which are farther and which nearer.'"' *
Violet
cance. Black is a color, but
does not figure on the plane of
White
ge
Whi n
gre le
Yrealnlge
te
St co
e
ra lo
B
w r - color, when they fall on our
O
Pink
Re
grluaey
Olive
Gray
Bro
another color placed alongside the two lights then mix on the retina;
or, finally, we must let the differently colored lights fall in succession
upon the retina, so fast that the second is there before the impres-
sion made by the first has died away. This is best done by looking
at a rapidly rotating disk whose sectors are of the several colors to be
mixed.
44 PSYCHOLOGY.
* Martin • op . cit.
SIGHT. 45
HEARING.*
C
A B
Co-
ha
V
Fy
Vc
Vpa'h
Fc
FIG. 19.-Casts of the bony labyrinth. A, left labyrinth seen from the outer
side; B, right labyrinth from the inner side ; C, left labyrinth from above; Co,
cochlea; V, vestibule; Fc, round foramen; Fu, oval foramen; h, horizontal
semicircular canal; ha, its ampulla; vaa, ampulla of anterior vertical semi-
circular canal; vpa, ampulla of posterior vertical semicircular canal ; vc, con-
joined portion of the two vertical canals.
SV R CC
ls
Lo no Go
ST
FIG. 21. -Section of one coil of the cochlea, magnified. SV, scala vestibuli ;
R, membrane of Reissner; CC, membranous cochlea (scala media); lls, limbus
lamina spiralis ; t, tectorial membrane ; ST, scala tympani ; lso, spiral
lamina; Co, rods of Corti ; b, basilar membrane.
vestibuli, SV, and a lower, the scala tympani, ST. Be-
tween these lie the lamina spiralis ( so) and the mem-
52 PSYCHOLOGY.
300
1
FIG. 22. The rods of Corti. A, a pair of rods separated from the rest; B, a
bit of the basilar membrane with several rods on it, showing how they cover
in the tunnel of Corti ; i, inner, and e, outer rods ; b, basilar membrane; r,
reticular membrane.
and the form of this when not too large to be felt all over.
When to learn the form of an object we move the hand
over it, muscular sensations are combined with proper tac-
tile, and such a combination of the two sensations is fre-
quent ; moreover, we rarely touch anything without at the
same time getting temperature sensations ; therefore pure
tactile feelings are rare. From an evolution point of view,
touch is probably the first distinctly differentiated sensa-
tion, and this primary position it still largely holds in our
ental life.” *
Objects are most important to us when in direct contact.
T'he chief function of our eyes and ears is to enable us to
prepare ourselves for contact with approaching bodies, or to
ward such contact off. They have accordingly been char-
acterized as organs of anticipatory touch.
" The delicacy of the tactile sense varies on different
parts of the skin ; it is greatest on the forehead, temples,
and back of the forearm , where a weight of 2 milligr. press-
ing on an area of 9 sq. millim. can be felt.
" In order that the sense of touch may be excited neigh-
boring skin-areas must be differently pressed . When the
hand is immersed in a liquid, as mercury, which fits into
all its inequalities and presses with practically the same
weight on all neighboring immersed areas, the sense of
pressure is only felt at a line along the surface, where the
immersed and non-immersed parts of the skin meet.
The Localizing Power of the Skin.-" When the eyes are
closed and a point of the skin is touched we can with some
ccuracy indicate the region stimulated ; although tactile
feelings are in general characters alike, they differ in some-
hing besides intensity by which we can distinguish them ;
some sub-sensation quality not rising definitely into promi-
Mence in consciousness must be present, comparable to the
upper partials determining the timbre of a tone. The
accuracy of the localizing power varies widely in different
dotted line rapidly sinks, and soon tumbles below the hori-
zontal into the realm of the disagreeable or painful in
which it declines. That all sensations are painful when
too strong is a piece of familiar knowledge. Light, sound,
odors, the taste of sweet even, cold , heat, and all the skin-
sensations, must be moderate to be enjoyed.
The quality of the sensation complicates the question, how-
ever, for in some sensations, as bitter, sour, salt, and certain
smells, the turning point of the dotted curve must be drawn
very near indeed to the beginning of the scale. In the
skin the painful quality soon becomes so intense as entirely
to overpower the specific quality of the sort of stimulus.
Heat, cold, and pressure are indistinguishable when extreme
-we only feel the pain . The hypothesis of separate end-
organs in the skin receives some corroboration from recent
experiments, for both Blix and Goldscheider have found ,
along with their special heat- and cold spots, also special
' pain-spots ' on the skin. Mixed in with these are spots
which are quite feelingless. However it may stand with
the terminal pain-spots, separate paths of conduction to the
brain, for painful and for merely tactile stimulations of
the skin, are made probable by certain facts. In the con-
dition termed analgesia, a touch is felt, but the most vio-
lent pinch, burn, or electric spark destructive of the tissue
will awaken no sensation. This may occur in disease of
the cord, by suggestion in hypnotism, or in certain stages
of ether and chloroform intoxication. " In rabbits a similar
state of things was produced by Schiff, by dividing the
gray matter of the cord , leaving the posterior white col-
umns intact. If, on the contrary, the latter were divided
and the gray substance left, there was increased sensitive-
ness to pain, and possibly touch proper was lost. Such
experiments make it pretty certain that when afferent
impulses reach the spinal cord at any level and there enter
its gray matter with the posterior root-fibres, they travel
on in different tracts to conscious centres ; the tactile ones
coming soon out of the gray network and coursing on in a
PAIN. 69
* Martin : or t
CHAPTER VI.
SENSATIONS OF MOTION.
(Cb in all the figures) and the pons Varolii below (P.V. in
Fig. 33) . In its hindmost portions the posterior vesicle
thickens below into the medulla oblongata ( Mo in all the
figures), whilst on top its walls thin out and melt, so that
one can pass a probe into the cavity without breaking
through any truly nervous tissue. The cavity which one.
thus enters from without is named the fourth ventricle
(4 in Figs. 32 and 33) . One can run the probe for-
80 PSYCHOLOGY.
Imp. M.b.
ThE
Py
FIG. 33 (after Huxley).
are divided, and the portion of dura mater (tentorium) which projects
between the hemispheres and the cerebellum is cut through at its
edges, the brain comes readily out.
It is best examined fresh. If numbers of brains have to be pre-
pared and kept, I have found it a good plan to put them first in a
solution of chloride of zinc, just dense enough at first to float them,
II
-III
[V
V
VI
VII
-VII
VIII
-IX
X
XI
XI XII
ncI
FIG 31 -The human brain from below, with its nerves numbered, after Henle.
I, olfactory; II, optic ; III, oculo-motorius ; IV, trochlearis ; V, trifacial ; VI,
abducens oculi ; VII, facial ; VIII, auditory ; IX, glosso-pharyngeal ; X, pneu-
mogastric ; XI, spinal accessory; XII, hypoglossal; ncI, first cervical, etc.
and to leave them for a fortnight or less. This softens the pia mater,
which can then be removed in large shreds, after which it is enough
to place them in quite weak alcohol to preserve them indefinitely,
tough, elastic, and in their natural shape, though bleached to a
uniform white color. Before immersion in the chloride all the more
superficial adhesions of the parts must be broken through, to bring
84 PSYCHOLOGY.
the fluid into contact with a maximum of surface. If the brain is used
fresh, the pia mater had better be removed carefully in most places
with the forceps, scalpel, and scissors. Over the grooves between
the cerebellum and hemispheres, and between the cerebellum and
medulla oblongata, thin cobwebby moist transparent vestiges of the
arachnoid membrane will be found.
The subdivisions may now be examined in due order. For the
convolutions, blood-vessels, and nerves the more special books must
be consulted.
First, looked at from above, with the deep longitudinal fissure be
tween them, the hemispheres are seen partly overlapping the intri
cately wrinkled cerebellum, which juts out behind, and covers in turn
almost all the medulla oblongata. Drawing the hemispheres apart,
the brilliant white corpus callosum is revealed, some half an inch
below their surface. There is no median partition in the cerebel-
lum, but a median elevation instead.
Looking at the brain from below, one still sees the longitudinal
fissure in the median line in front, and on either side of it the
olfactory lobes, much larger than in man ; the optic tracts and com-
missure or chiasma ' ; the infundibulum cut through just behind
them ; and behind that the single corpus albicans or mamillare, whose
function is unknown and which is double in man. Next the crura
appear, converging upon the pons as if carrying fibres back from either
side. The pons itself succeeds, much less prominent than in man ;
and finally behind it comes the medulla oblongata, broad and flat and
relatively large. The pons looks like a sort of collar uniting the two
halves of the cerebellum, and surrounding the medulla, whose fibres
by the time they have emerged anteriorly from beneath the collar
have divided into the two crura. The inner relations are, however,
somewhat less simple than what this description may suggest.
Now turn forward the cerebellum ; pull out the vascular choroid
plexuses of the pia, which fill the fourth ventricle ; and bring the
upper surface of the medulla oblongata into view. Thefourth ventricle
is a triangular depression terminating in a posterior point called the
calamus scriptorius. (Here a very fine probe may pass into the central
canal of the spinal cord . ) The lateral boundary of the ventricle on
either side is formed by the restiform body or column, which runs into
the cerebellum, forming its inferior or posterior peduncle on that side.
Including the calamus scriptorius by their divergence, the posterior
columns of the spinal cord continue into the medulla as the fasciculi
graciles. These are at first separated from the broad restiform
bodies by a slight groove. But this disappears anteriorly, and the
' slender ' and ' ropelike ' strands soon become outwardly indistin
guishable.
THE STRUCTURE OF THE BRAIN. 85
Turn next to the ventral surface of the medulla, and note the anterior
pyramids, two roundish cords, one on either side of the slight median
groove. The pyramids are crossed and closed over anteriorly by the
pons Varolii, a broad transverse band which surrounds them like a
collar, and runs up into the cerebellum on either side, forming its
middle peduncles. The pons has a slight median depression and its
III
IV
Cr
Fg
FIG. 35.-Fourth ventricle, etc. (Henle). III, third ventricle; IV, fourth ver
tricle; P. anterior, middle, and posterior peduncles of cerebellum cut through;
Cr, restiform body ; Fg, funiculus gracilis ; Cq, corpora quadrigemina.
Cut the corpus callosum transversely through near its posterior edge
and bend the anterior portion of it forwards and sideways . The rear
edge (splenium) left in situ bends round and downwards and becomes
Cel
Cs
SI
Cr
ངོ
སོ
།ང
ད
Tho
Cn
Fio 36.-Horizontal section of human brain just above the thalami. -Cel, cor-
pus callosum in section; Cs, corpus striatum; Sl, septum lucidum ; Cf, columns
of the fornix; Tho, optic thalami; Cn, pineal gland. (After Henle.)
continuous with the fornix. The anterior part is also continuous with
the fornix, but more along the median line, where a thinnish mem-
brane, the septum lucidum, triangular in shape, reaching from the one
body to the other, practically forms a sort of partition between the
88 PSYCHOLOGY.
Co
rp
O
p
n
Call
Inf
Pit
Crus.
Th.
Pons
Mo
bl
FIG. 37.--Median section of human brain below the hemispheres. Th, thalamus
Cg, corpora quadrigemina ; P , third ventricle; Com, middle commissure ;
F, columns of formix; Inf, infundibulum; Op.n, optic nerve ; Pit, pituitary
body; Av, arbor vitæ. (After Obersteiner).
90 PSYCHOLOGY.
Cc
Pf
Ic
Th •
3d V
NI
When all is said and done, the fact remains that, for the
beginner, the understanding of the brain's structure is not
an easy thing. It must be gone over and forgotten and
learned again many times before it is definitively assimi-
lated by the mind . But patience and repetition , here as
elsewhere, will bear their perfect fruit.
CHAPTER VIII.
suffer a fly to crawl over his nose unsnapped at. Fear, too ,
seems to have deserted him. In a word . he is an extremely
complex machine whose actions, so far as they go, tend to
self-preservation ; but still a machine, in this sense-that
it seems to contain no incalculable element. By applying
the right sensory stimulus to him we are almost as certain
of getting a fixed response as an organist is of hearing a
certain tone when he pulls out a certain stop.
But now if to the lower centres we add the cerebral hemi-
spheres, or if, in other words, we make an intact animal
the subject of our observations, all this is changed. In
addition to the previous responses to present incitements
of sense, our frog now goes through long and complex acts
of locomotion spontaneously, or as if moved by what in
ourselves we should call an idea. His reactions to outward
stimuli vary their form, too. Instead of making simple
defensive movements with his hind-legs, like a headless
frog, if touched ; or of giving one or two leaps and then sit-
ting still like a hemisphereless one, he makes persistent
and varied efforts of escape, as if, not the mere contact of
the physiologist's hand, but the notion of danger suggested
by it were now his spur. Led by the feeling of hunger,
too, he goes in search of insects, fish, or smaller frogs, and
varies his procedure with each species of victim . The
physiologist cannot by manipulating him elicit croaking,
crawling up a board, swimming or stopping, at will . His
conduct has become incalculable - we can no longer fore-
tell it exactly. Effort to escape is his dominant reaction ,
but he may do anything else, even swell up and become
perfectly passive in our hands.
he calls into play all the leg-muscles which a frog with his
full medulla oblongata and cerebellum uses when he turns
from his back to his belly. Their contractions are, how-
ever, combined differently in the two cases, so that the
results vary widely. We must consequently conclude that
specific arrangements of cells and fibres exist in the cord
for wiping, in the medulla for turning over, etc. Simi-
larly they exist in the thalami for jumping over seen ob-
stacles and for balancing the moved body ; in the optic
lebes for creeping backwards, or what not. But in the
hemispheres, since the presence of these organs brings no
new elementary form of movement with it, but only deter-
mines differently the occasions on which the movements
shall occur, making the usual stimuli less fatal and ma-
chine-like, we need suppose no such machinery directly
coördinative of muscular contractions to exist. We may
rather assume, when the mandate for a wiping-movement
is sent forth by the hemispheres, that a current goes straight
to the wiping-arrangement in the spinal cord , exciting this
arrangement as a whole. Similarly, if an intact frog wishes
to jump, all he need do is to excite from the hemispheres
the jumping-centre in the thalami or wherever it may be,
and the latter will provide for the details of the execution .
It is like a general ordering a colonel to make a certain
movement, but not telling him how it shall be done.
The same muscle, then, is repeatedly represented at dif-
ferent heights; and at each it enters into a different com-
bination with other muscles to coöperate in some special
form of concerted movement. At each height the move-
ment is discharged by some particular form of sensorial
stimulus, whilst the stimuli which discharge the hemi-
spheres would seem not so much to be elementary sorts
of sensation, as groups of sensations forming determinate
objects or things.
The Pigeon's Lower Centres.- The results are just the
same if, instead of a frog, we take a pigeon, cut out his
hemispheres carefully and wait till he recovers from the
THE FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 97
The same diagram can symbolize both the inner and the
outer world ; dots or circles standing indifferently for cells
or ideas, and lines joining them, for fibres or associations.
The associationist doctrine of ideas ' may be doubted to
be a literal expression of the truth, but it probably will
always retain a didactic usefulness. At all events, it is
interesting to see how well physiological analysis plays into
its hands. To proceed to details.
The Motor Region.- The one thing which is per-
6
fectly well established is this, that the central ' con-
NK MOVEMENTS OF TOES
LEXUION OF THIGH AND I
TFR
H
AND EOOT
E
E
SUR
RETRACTION FIS
A
PROTRACTION
I
AR
AP
D
TR
FLEXION
IN
ARM
SBICEPS
RE
D
SU
AN
RE
IS
SU
I US
IS
UPPER LV
FACE URE SY
S
MUSCLES SPLATYS MA
FI OF ST
LL
FACE
RA
MOUTH AND
LARYNX
PA
MOVEMENTS OFFLEXION AT
KNEE EXTENSION
TOES AND CHAMSTRINGS
FOOT L AT
EG HIP MOVEMENTS ROTATION
TAILOF ANDLATERAL
RU NK MOVEMENT
MOVEMENTS
GIOFN ! OF
SO - MARSPINE
ANDM HEAD
AR
Fig. 43, after Starr, shows how the fibres run downwards.
All sensory currents entering the hemispheres run out
from the Rolandic region, which may thus be regarded as
a sort of funnel of escape, which narrows still more as it
plunges beneath the surface, traversing the inner capsule,
pons, and parts below. The dark ellipses on the left half
of the diagram stand for hemorrhages or tumors, and the
reader can easily trace, by following the course of the
fibres, what the effect of them in interrupting motor cur-
rents may be.
108 PSYCHOLOGY.
VIL.. VIL.
FIG. 43. Schematic transverse section of the human brain, through the rolan-
dic region. S, fissure of Sylvius; N.C., nucleus candatus, and N.L., nucleus
lenticularis, of the corpus striatum: O.T., thalamus; C, crus; M. medulla
oblongata; VII, the facial nerves passing out from their rucleus in the region
of the pons. The fibres passing between O.T. and N.L. constitute the so-
called internal capsule.
CM
R
A
C
O
KE
IC
R
N
ER
B
FIG. 44. -Schematic profile of left hemisphere, with the parts shaded whose
destruction causes motor (' Broca ' ) and sensory ( Wernicke ' ) aphasia.
T. 0. S. 0. D. T.
N.O.S.
F.C.S N. O. D
F.L.D
T.O.D
CC.L
P.O.C.
F.O. C.P
F.O.
G.A
Cu
Cu
L.O.S LO.D
FIG. 45. -Scheme of the mechanism of vision, after Seguin. The cuneus con-
volution (Cu) of the right occipital lobe is supposed to be injured, and all
the parts which lead to it are darkly shaded to show that they fail to exert
their function. F.O. are the intra -hemispheric optical fibres. P.O.C. is the
region of the lower optic centres (corpora geniculata and quadrigemina).
T.O.D. is the right optic tract ; C, the chiasma ; F.L.D. are the fibres going
to the lateral or temporal half T of the right retina, and F.C.S. are those
going to the central or nasal half of the left retina. O.D. is the right, and
O.S. the left, eyeball. The rightward half of each is therefore blind; in other
words, the right nasal field, R.N.F., and the left temporal field, L.T.F., have
become invisible to the subject with the lesion at Cu.
112 PSYCHOLOGY.
us Callosu
Corp
which the patient could read, talk, and write , but not
understand what was said to him) , the lesion was limited
to the first and second temporal convolutions in their
posterior two thirds. The lesion (in right-handed , i.e. left-
brained, persons) is always on the left side, like the lesion
in motor aphasia. Crude hearing would not be abolished
even were the left centre for it utterly destroyed ; the right •
centre would still provide for that. But the linguistic use
of hearing appears bound up with the integrity of the left
centre more or less exclusively. Here it must be that
words heard enter into association with the things which
they represent, on the one hand , and with the movements
necessary for pronouncing them, on the other. In most
of us (as Wernicke said) speech must go on from auditory
cues ; that is, our visual, tactile, and other ideas probably
do not innervate our motor centres directly, but only after
first arousing the mental sound of the words. This is the
immediate stimulus to articulation ; and where the possi-
bility of this is abolished by the destruction of its usual
channel in the left temporal lobe, the articulation must
suffer. In the few cases in which the channel is abolished
with no bad effect on speech we must suppose an idiosyn-
crasy. The patient must innervate his speech- organs either
from the corresponding portion of the other hemisphere
or directly from the centres of vision, touch, etc. , without
leaning on the auditory region. It is the minuter analysis
of such individual differences as these which constitutes
Charcot's contribution towards clearing up the subject.
Every namable thing has numerous properties, qualities,
or aspects. In our minds the properties together with the
name form an associated group. If different parts of the
brain are severally concerned with the several properties,
and a farther part with the hearing, and still another
with the uttering, of the name, there must inevitably be
brought about (through the law of association which we
shall later study) such a connection amongst all these brain-
parts that the activity of any one of them will be likely t
THE FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 115
Upp PaP r
er ariieetal Co
tal nv
.
Ang
a-
ula
pr
e
ra-margin
Su
Conv.
r C
Occipital
Convs.
onv
o-
mp
Te
l
ra s
o nv
C .
FIG. 47.
a บ
20
m
m
FIG. 48.-A is the auditory centre, the visual, W the writing, and E that for
speech.
Reaction-line.
Time-line.
FIG. 49.
the passer often buys from the last one of them, through the
effect of the reiterated solicitation, what he refused to buy
from the first in the row.
Cerebral Blood-supply. - All parts of the cortex, when
electrically excited , produce alterations both of respiration
and circulation. The blood-pressure somewhat rises, as a
rule, all over the body, no matter where the cortical irrita-
tion is applied, though the motor zone is the most sensi-
tive region for the purpose. Slowing and quickening of the
heart are also observed . Mosso , using his plethysmograph
as an indicator, discovered that the blood-supply to the arms
diminished during intellectual activity, and found further-
more that the arterial tension (as shown by the sphygmo-
graph) was increased in these members (see Fig. 50). So
www
HABIT.
to which all the other organs of our body are exposed ; for,
as we saw on pp. 9-10, Nature has so blanketed and wrapped
the brain about that the only impressions that can be made
upon it are through the blood, on the one hand, and the
sensory nerve-roots, on the other ; and it is to the infinitely
attenuated currents that pour in through these latter chan-
nels that the hemispherical cortex shows itself to be so
peculiarly susceptible. The currents, once in, must find a
way out. In getting out they leave their traces in the
paths which they take. The only thing they can do, in
short, is to deepen old paths or to make new ones ; and the
whole plasticity of the brain sums itself up in two words
when we call it an organ in which currents pouring in from
the sense-organs make with extreme facility paths which
do not easily disappear. For, of course, a simple habit,
like every other nervous event- the habit of snuffling, for
example, or of putting one's hands into one's pockets, or of
biting one's nails -is, mechanically, nothing but a reflex
discharge; and its anatomical substratum must be a path
in the system. The most complex habits, as we shall pres-
ently see more fully, are, from the same point of view,
nothing but concatenated discharges in the nerve- centres,
due to the presence there of systems of reflex paths, so
organized as to wake each other up successively -the im-
pression produced by one muscular contraction serving as
a stimulus to provoke the next, until a final impression
inhibits the process and closes the chain.
It must be noticed that the growth of structural modi-
fication in living matter may be more rapid than in any
lifeless mass, because the incessant nutritive renovation of
which the living matter is the seat tends often to corrob-
orate and fix the impressed modification, rather than to
counteract it by renewing the original constitution of the
tissue that has been impressed . Thus, we notice after ex-
ercising our muscles or our brain in a new way, that we
can do so no longer at that time ; but after a day or two
of rest, when we resume the discipline, our increase in skill
138 PSYCHOLOGY.
wwFIG. 51.
w
the women once so divine, the stars, the woods , and the
waters, how now so dull and common ! -the young girls
that brought an aura of infinity, at present hardly distin-
guishable existences ; the pictures so empty ; and as for
the books, what was there to find so mysteriously signifi-
cant in Goethe, or in John Mill so full of weight ? Instead
of all this , more zestful than ever is the work, the work ;
and fuller and deeper the import of common duties and of
common goods.
I am sure that this concrete and total manner of regard-
ing the mind's changes is the only true manner, difficult
as it may be to carry it out in detail. If anything seems
obscure about it, it will grow clearer as we advance.
Meanwhile, if it be true, it is certainly also true that no
two ideas ' are ever exactly the same, which is the propo-
sition we started to prove. The proposition is more
important theoretically than it at first sight seems. For
it makes it already impossible for us to follow obediently
in the footprints of either the Lockian or the Herbartian
school, schools which have had almost unlimited influence
in Germany and among ourselves. No doubt it is often
convenient to formulate the mental facts in an atomistic
sort of way, and to treat the higher states of consciousness
as if they were all built out of unchanging simple ideas
which pass and turn again.' It is convenient often to
treat curves as if they were composed of small straight
lines, and electricity and nerve-force as if they were fluids.
But in the one case as in the other we must never forget
that we are talking symbolically, and that there is noth-
ing in nature to answer to our words. A permanently
existing Idea ' which makes its appearance before the
footlights of consciousness at periodical intervals is as
mythological an entity as the Jack of Spades.
Within each personal consciousness, thought is sensibly
continuous. I can only define ' continuous ' as that which
is without breach, crack, or division . The only breaches.
that can well be conceived to occur within the limits of a
158 PSYCHOLOGY .
them . They do not fit into its mould. And the gap of
one word does not feel like the gap of another, all empty
of content as both might seem necessarily to be when de-
scribed as gaps. When I vainly try to recall the name of
Spalding, my consciousness is far removed from what it is
when I vainly try to recall the name of Bowles. There
are innumerable consciousnesses of want, no one of which
taken in itself has a name, but all different from each
other. Such a feeling of want is toto cœlo other than a
want of feeling : it is an intense feeling. The rhythm of
a lost word may be there without a sound to clothe it ; or
the evanescent sense of something which is the initial
vowel or consonant may mock us fitfully, without grow-
ing more distinct. Every one must know the tantalizing
effect of the blank rhythm of some forgotten verse, rest-
lessly dancing in one's mind , striving to be filled out with
words.
What is that first instantaneous glimpse of some one's
meaning which we have, when in vulgar phrase we say we
'twig ' it ? Surely an altogether specific affection of our
mind. And has the reader never asked himself what kind
of a mental fact is his intention of saying a thing before
he has said it ? It is an entirely definite intention, dis-
tinct from all other intentions, an absolutely distinct state
of consciousness, therefore ; and yet how much of it con-
sists of definite sensorial images, either of words or of
things ? Hardly anything ! Linger, and the words and
things come into the mind ; the anticipatory intention , the
divination is there no more. But as the words that re-
place it arrive, it welcomes them successively and calls
them right if they agree with it, it rejects them and calls
them wrong if they do not. The intention to-say-so-
and-so is the only name it can receive. One may admit
that a good third of our psychic life consists in these rapid
premonitory perspective views of schemes of thought not
yet articulate. How comes it about that a man reading
something aloud for the first time is able immediately to
THE STREAM OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 165
emphasize all his words aright, unless from the very first
he have a sense of at least the form of the sentence yet
to come, which sense is fused with his consciousness of
the present word, and modifies its emphasis in his mind
so as to make him give it the proper accent as he utters
it ? Emphasis of this kind almost altogether depends on
grammatical construction . If we read ' no more,' we ex-
6
pect presently a ' than ' ; if we read however,' it is a ' yet,'
a still,' or a ' nevertheless,' that we expect. And this
foreboding of the coming verbal and grammatical scheme
is so practically accurate that a reader incapable of under-
standing four ideas of the book he is reading aloud can
nevertheless read it with the most delicately modulated
expression of intelligence.
It is, the reader will see, the reinstatement of the vague
and inarticulate to its proper place in our mental life which
I am so anxious to press on the attention. Mr. Galton
and Prof. Huxley have, as we shall see in the chapter on
Imagination, made one step in advance in exploding the
ridiculous theory of Hume and Berkeley that we can have
no images but of perfectly definite things. Another is
made if we overthrow the equally ridiculous notion that,
whilst simple objective qualities are revealed to our knowl-
6
edge in states of consciousness ,' relations are not. But
these reforms are not half sweeping and radical enough.
What must be admitted is that the definite images of tra-
ditional psychology form but the very smallest part of our
minds as they actually live. The traditional psychology
talks like one who should say a river consists of nothing
but pailsful, spoonsful, quartpotsful, barrelsful, and other
moulded forms of water. Even were the pails and the pots
all actually standing in the stream , still between them the
free water would continue to flow. It is just this free
water of consciousness that psychologists resolutely over-
look. Every definite image in the mind is steeped and
dyed in the free water that flows round it. With it goes
the sense of its relations, near and remote, the dying echo
166 PSYCHOLOGY.
a b
FIG. 52.
THE SELF
them. They do not fit into its mould. And the gap of
one word does not feel like the gap of another, all empty
of content as both might seem necessarily to be when de-
scribed as gaps . When I vainly try to recall the name of
Spalding, my consciousness is far removed from what it is
when I vainly try to recall the name of Bowles. There
are innumerable consciousnesses of want, no one of which
taken in itself has a name, but all different from each
other. Such a feeling of want is toto cœlo other than a
want of feeling : it is an intense feeling. The rhythm of
a lost word may be there without a sound to clothe it ; or
the evanescent sense of something which is the initial
vowel or consonant may mock us fitfully, without grow-
ing more distinct. Every one must know the tantalizing
effect of the blank rhythm of some forgotten verse, rest-
lessly dancing in one's mind, striving to be filled out with
words.
What is that first instantaneous glimpse of some one's
meaning which we have, when in vulgar phrase we say we
'twig ' it ? Surely an altogether specific affection of our
mind. And has the reader never asked himself what kind
of a mental fact is his intention of saying a thing before
he has said it ? It is an entirely definite intention, dis-
tinct from all other intentions, an absolutely distinct state.
of consciousness, therefore ; and yet how much of it con-
sists of definite sensorial images, either of words or of
things ? Hardly anything ! Linger, and the words and
things come into the mind ; the anticipatory intention, the
divination is there no more. But as the words that re-
place it arrive, it welcomes them successively and calls
them right if they agree with it, it rejects them and calls
them wrong if they do not. The intention to-say-so-
and-so is the only name it can receive. One may admit
that a good third of our psychic life consists in these rapid
premonitory perspective views of schemes of thought not
yet articulate. How comes it about that a man reading
something aloud for the first time is able immediately to
THE STREAM OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 165
emphasize all his words aright, unless from the very first
he have a sense of at least the form of the sentence yet
to come, which sense is fused with his consciousness of
the present word, and modifies its emphasis in his mind
so as to make him give it the proper accent as he utters
it ? Emphasis of this kind almost altogether depends on
grammatical construction. If we read ' no more,' we ex-
pect presently a ' than ' ; if we read however,' it is a ‘ yet,'
a ' still,' or a ' nevertheless,' that we expect. And this
foreboding of the coming verbal and grammatical scheme
is so practically accurate that a reader incapable of under-
standing four ideas of the book he is reading aloud can
nevertheless read it with the most delicately modulated
expression of intelligence.
It is, the reader will see, the reinstatement of the vague
and inarticulate to its proper place in our mental life which
I am so anxious to press on the attention. Mr. Galton
and Prof. Huxley have, as we shall see in the chapter on
Imagination, made one step in advance in exploding the
ridiculous theory of Hume and Berkeley that we can have
no images but of perfectly definite things. Another is
made if we overthrow the equally ridiculous notion that,
whilst simple objective qualities are revealed to our knowl-
edge in states of consciousness,' relations are not. But
these reforms are not half sweeping and radical enough.
What must be admitted is that the definite images of tra-
ditional psychology form but the very smallest part of our
minds as they actually live. The traditional psychology
talks like one who should say a river consists of nothing
but pailsful, spoonsful, quartpotsful, barrelsful, and other
moulded forms of water. Even were the pails and the pots
all actually standing in the stream, still between them the
free water would continue to flow. It is just this free
water of consciousness that psychologists resolutely over-
look. Every definite image in the mind is steeped and
dyed in the free water that flows round it. With it goes
the sense of its relations, near and remote, the dying echo
166 PSYCHOLOGY.
a
FIG. 52.
THE SELF
Success
Self-esteem =
Pretensions
goods, and the temptation lies very near to deny that they
are goods at all. We find this mode of protecting the Self
by exclusion and denial very common among people who
are in other respects not Stoics. All narrow people intrench
their Me, they retract it, —from the region of what they
cannot securely possess . People who don't resemble them,
or who treat them with indifference, people over whom they
gain no influence, are people on whose existence, however
meritorious it may intrinsically be, they look with chill
negation, if not with positive hate. Who will not be mine
I will exclude from existence altogether ; that is, as far as
I can make it so, such people shall be as if they were not.
Thus may a certain absoluteness and definiteness in the out-
line of my Me console me for the smallness of its content.
Sympathetic people, on the contrary, proceed by the
entirely opposite way of expansion and inclusion. The
outline of their self often gets uncertain enough, but for
this the spread of its content more than atones. Nil
humani a me alienum. Let them despise this little per-
son of mine, and treat me like a dog, I shall not negate
them so long as I have a soul in my body. They are reali-
ties as much as I am. What positive good is in them shall
be mine too, etc., etc. The magnanimity of these expansive
natures is often touching indeed . Such persons can feel
a sort of delicate rapture in thinking that, however sick,
ill -favored , mean-conditioned , and generally forsaken they
may be, they yet are integral parts of the whole of this
brave world, have a fellow's share in the strength of the
dray-horses, the happiness of the young people, the wisdom
of the wise ones, and are not altogether without part or lot
in the good fortunes of the Vanderbilts and the Hohen-
zollerns themselves. Thus either by negating or by em-
bracing, the Ego may seek to establish itself in reality.
He who, with Marcus Aurelius, can truly say, " O Universe,
I wish all that thou wishest," has a self from which every
trace of negativeness and obstructiveness has been re-
moved- no wind can blow except to fill its sails.
190 PSYCHOLOGY.
a. Insane delusions ;
B. Alternating selves ;
7. Mediumships or possessions.
ceive. One patient has another self that repeats all his
thoughts for him. Others, amongst whom are some of the
first characters in history, have internal dæmons who speak
with them and are replied to. Another feels that someone
' makes ' his thoughts for him. Another has two bodies,
lying in different beds. Some patients feel as if they had
lost parts of their bodies, teeth, brain, stomach, etc. In
some it is made of wood, glass, butter, etc. In some it
does not exist any longer, or is dead, or is a foreign object
quite separate from the speaker's self. Occasionally, parts
of the body lose their connection for consciousness with
the rest, and are treated as belonging to another person
and moved by a hostile will. Thus the right hand may
fight with the left as with an enemy. Or the cries of the
patient himself are assigned to another person with whom
the patient expresses sympathy. The literature of insan-
ity is filled with narratives of such illusions as these. M.
Taine quotes from a patient of Dr. Krishaber an account
of sufferings, from which it will be seen how completely
aloof from what is normal a man's experience may sud-
denly become :
" After the first or second day it was for some weeks
impossible to observe or analyze myself. The suffering—
angina pectoris was too overwhelming. It was not till
the first days of January that I could give an account to
myself of what I experienced . . . . Here is the first thing
of which I retain a clear remembrance. I was alone, and
already a prey to permanent visual trouble, when I was
suddenly seized with a visual trouble infinitely more pro-
nounced. Objects grew small and receded to infinite dis-
tances -men and things together. I was myself immeas-
urably far away. I looked about me with terror and
astonishment ; the world was escaping from me. . . . I
remarked at the same time that my voice was extremely
far away from me, that it sounded no longer as if mine . I
struck the ground with my foot, and perceived its resist-
ance ; but this resistance seemed illusory - not that the
THE SELF. 209
soil was soft, but that the weight of my body was reduced
to almost nothing. . . . I had the feeling of being without
weight...." In addition to being so distant, " objects
appeared to me flat. When I spoke with anyone, I saw
him like an image cut out of paper with no relief. • •
This sensation lasted intermittently for two years.
Constantly it seemed as if my legs did not belong to me.
It was almost as bad with my arms. As for my head, it
seemed no longer to exist. .... . . I appeared to myself to
act automatically, by an impulsion foreign to myself. ...
. . .
There was inside of me a new being, and another part of
myself, the old being, which took no interest in the new-
comer. I distinctly remember saying to myself that the
sufferings of this new being were to me indifferent. I was
never really dupe of these illusions, but my mind grew
often tired of incessantly correcting the new impressions,
and I let myself go and live the unhappy life of this new
entity. I had an ardent desire to see my old world again,
to get back to my old self. This desire kept me from
killing myself. • I was another, and I hated , I despised
this other ; he was perfectly odious to me ; it was certainly
another who had taken my form and assumed my func-
tions." *
In cases like this, it is as certain that the I is unaltered
as that the Me is changed . That is to say, the present
Thought of the patient is cognitive of both the old Me and
the new, so long as its memory holds good. Only, within
that objective sphere which formerly lent itself so simply
to the judgment of recognition and of egoistic appropria-
tion, strange perplexities have arisen. The present and
the past, both seen therein, will not unite. Where is my
old Me ? What is this new one ? Are they the same ?
Or have I two ? Such questions, answered by whatever
theory the patient is able to conjure up as plausible, form
the beginning of his insane life.
ATTENTION.
are those which are said to ' interest ' us at the time ; and
thus that selective character of our attention on which so
much stress was laid on pp. 173 ff. appears to find a
physiological ground . At all times, however, there is a
liability to disintegration of the reigning system . The con-
solidation is seldom quite complete, the excluded currents
are not wholly abortive, their presence affects the ' fringe '
and margin of our thought.
Dispersed Attention. Sometimes, indeed, the normal
consolidation seems hardly to exist . At such moments it
is possible that cerebral activity sinks to a minimum.
Most of us probably fall several times a day into a fit
somewhat like this : The eyes are fixed on vacancy, the
sounds of the world melt into confused unity , the attention
.
is dispersed so that the whole body is felt , as it were, at
once, and the foreground of consciousness is filled, if by
anything, by a sort of solemn sense of surrender to the
empty passing of time. In the dim background of our
mind we know meanwhile what we ought to be doing : get-
ting up, dressing ourselves, answering the person who has
spoken to us, trying to make the next step in our reason-
ing. But somehow we cannot start; the pensée de derrière
la tête fails to pierce the shell of lethargy that wraps our
state about. Every moment we expect the spell to break,
for we know no reason why it should continue. But it
does continue, pulse after pulse, and we float with it , until
also without reason that we can discover-an energy is
given, something we know not what enables us to
gather ourselves together, we wink our eyes , we shake our
heads, the background-ideas become effective , and the
wheels of life go round again .
This is the extreme of what is called dispersed atten-
tion. Between this extreme and the extreme of concen-
trated attention, in which absorption in the interest of the
moment is so complete that grave bodily injuries may be
unfelt, there are intermediate degrees, and these have been
studied experimentally. The problem is known as that of
ATTENTION. 219
FIG. 54.
CONCEPTION.
DISCRIMINATION .
ASSOCIATION.
b m
FIG. 57.
word ' heir ' in the verse from ' Locksley Hall,' which was
our first example. How such tendencies are constituted
we shall have soon to inquire with some care. Unless they
are present, the panorama of the past, once opened, must
unroll itself with fatal literality to the end, unless some
outward sound, sight, or touch divert the current of
thought.
ASSOCIATION. 261
FIG. 58.
A B
FIG. 59.
во
FIG. 60.
FIG. 61.
MEMORY.
are led into by few paths, and are relatively little liable to be
awakened again. Speedy oblivion is the almost inevitable
fate of all that is committed to memory in this simple way.
Whereas, on the contrary, the same materials taken in
gradually, day after day, recurring in different contexts,
considered in various relations, associated with other exter-
nal incidents, and repeatedly reflected on, grow into such a
system, form such connections with the rest of the mind's
fabric, lie open to so many paths of approach, that they
remain permanent possessions. This is the intellectual
reason why habits of continuous application should be
enforced in educational establishments. Of course there
is no moral turpitude in cramming. Did it lead to the
desired end of secure learning, it were infinitely the best
method of study. But it does not ; and students them-
selves should understand the reason why.
One's native retentiveness is unchangeable. It will now
appear clear that all improvement ofthe memory lies in the
line of ELABORATING THE ASSOCIATES of each of the several
things to be remembered. No amount of culture would
seem capable of modifying a man's GENERAL retentiveness.
This is a physiological quality, given once for all with his
organization, and which he can never hope to change. It
differs no doubt in disease and health ; and it is a fact of
observation that it is better in fresh and vigorous hours
than when we are fagged or ill . We may say, then, that a
man's native tenacity will fluctuate somewhat with his
hygiene, and that whatever is good for his tone of health
will also be good for his memory. We may even say that
whatever amount of intellectual exercise is bracing to the
general tone and nutrition of the brain will also be profit-
able to the general retentiveness. But more than this we
cannot say ; and this, it is obvious, is far less than most
people believe.
It is, in fact, commonly thought that certain exercises,
systematically repeated , will strengthen, not only a man's
remembrance of the particular facts used in the exercises,
MEMORY. 297
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0
t n m r 1 sh g f b S
d jk V с
chc Z
g qu
300 PSYCHOLOGY.
IMAGINATION.
PERCEPTION.
way, such are the tangible shape, size, mass, etc. Other
properties, being more fluctuating, we regard as more or
less accidental or inessential. We call the former qualities
the reality, the latter its appearances. Thus, I hear a
sound, and say a horse-car ' ; but the sound is not the
horse-car, it is one of the horse-car's least important mani-
festations. The real horse-car is a feelable, or at most a
feelable and visible, thing which in my imagination the
sound calls up. So when I get, as now, a brown eye-pic-
ture with lines not parallel, and with angles unlike, and
call it my big solid rectangular walnut library- table, that
picture is not the table. It is not even like the table as
the table is for vision , when rightly seen . It is a distorted
perspective view of three of the sides of what I mentally
perceive (more or less ) in its totality and undistorted shape.
The back of the table, its square corners, its size, its heavi-
ness, are features of which I am conscious when I look,
almost as I am conscious of its name. The suggestion of
the name is of course due to mere custom. But no less is
that of the back, the size, weight, squareness , etc.
Nature, as Reid says, is frugal in her operations, and
will not be at the expense of a particular instinct to give
us that knowledge which experience and habit will soon
produce. Reproduced attributes tied together with pres-
ently felt attributes in the unity of a thing with a name,
these are the materials out of which my actually perceived
table is made. Infants must go through a long education
of the eye and ear before they can perceive the realities
which adults perceive. Every perception is an acquired
perception.
The Perceptive State of Mind is not a Compound . There
is no reason, however, for supposing that this involves a
fusion of separate sensations and ideas. The thing per-
ceived is the object of a unique state of thought ; due no
doubt in part to sensational, and in part to ideational cur-
rents, but in no wise ' containing ' psychically the identical
6
sensations ' and images which these currents would sev-
314 PSYCHOLOGY.
B
this
FIG. 63.
and thence into all the paths of B, each increment of ad-
vance making A more and more impossible. The thoughts
correlated with A and B, in such a case, will have objects
different, though similar. The similarity will, however,
consist in some very limited feature if the ' this ' be smail.
Thus the faintest sensations will give rise to the percep-
tion of definite things if only they resemble those which the
things are wont to arouse.
Illusions. Let us now, for brevity's sake, treat A and B
in Fig. 63 as if they stood for objects instead of brain-
processes. And let us furthermore suppose that A and B
are, both of them, objects which might probably excite the
sensation which I have called this,' but that on the
present occasion A and not B is the one which actually
does so. If, then, on this occasion ' this ' suggests A and
not B, the result is a correct perception . But if, on the
contrary, ' this ' suggests B and not A, the result is a false
perception, or, as it is technically called, an illusion. But
the process is the same, whether the perception be true
or false.
318 PSYCHOLOGY.
* In Mind, IX. 206, M. Binet points out the fact that what is falla-
ciously inferred is always an object of some other sense than the
' this.' ' Optical illusions ' are generally errors of touch and muscu-
lar sensibility, and the fallaciously perceived object and the experi
ences which correct it are both tactile in these cases.
PERCEPTION. 319
contact first with the forefinger and next with the second
finger, the two contacts seem to come in at different points
of space. The forefinger-touch seems higher, though the
finger is really lower ; the second -finger-touch seems lower,
though the finger is really higher. We perceive the con-
tacts as double because we refer them to two distinct parts
of space." The touched sides of the two fingers are nov-
mally not together in space, and customarily never do
touch one thing; the one thing which now touches them,
therefore, seems in two places, i.e. seems two things.
There is a whole batch of illusions which come from
optical sensations interpreted by us in accordance with our
usual rule, although they are now produced by an unusual
object. The stereoscope is an example. The eyes see a
picture apiece, and the two pictures are a little disparate,
the one seen by the right eye being a view of the object
taken from a point slightly to the right of that from which
the left eye's picture is taken. Pictures thrown on the
two eyes by solid objects present this sort of disparity,
so that we react on the sensation in our usual way, and
perceive a solid. If the pictures be exchanged we perceive
a hollow mould of the object, for a hollow mould would
cast just such disparate pictures as these. Wheatstone's
instrument, the pseudoscope, allows us to look at solid ob-
jects and see with each eye the other eye's picture. We
then perceive the solid object hollow, if it be an object
which might probably be hollow, but not otherwise . Thus
the perceptive process is true to its law, which is always to
react on the sensation in a determinate and figured fash-
ion if possible, and in as probable a fashion as the case
admits. A human face, e.g., never appears hollow to the
pseudoscope, for to couple faces and hollowness violates all
our habits. For the same reason it is very easy to make
an intaglio cast of a face, or the painted inside of a paste-
board mask, look convex, instead of concave as they are.
Curious illusions of movement in objects occur when-
ever the eyeballs move without our intending it. We
320 PSYCHOLOGY.
that the thrush was the bird I fired at, so complete was
my mental supplement to my visual perception." *
As with game, so with enemies, ghosts, and the like.
Anyone waiting in a dark place and expecting or fearing
strongly a certain object will interpret any abrupt sensa-
tion to mean that object's presence. The boy playing ' I
spy,' the criminal skulking from his pursuers, the super-
stitious person hurrying through the woods or past the
churchyard at midnight, the man lost in the woods, the
girl who tremulously has made an evening appointment
with her swain, all are subject to illusions of sight and
sound which make their hearts beat till they are dispelled.
Twenty times a day the lover, perambulating the streets
with his preoccupied fancy, will think he perceives his
idol's bonnet hefore him.
The Proof-reader's Illusion.- I remember one night in
Boston, whilst waiting for a ' Mount Auburn ' car to bring
me to Cambridge, reading most distinctly that name upon
the signboard of a car on which (as I afterwards learned )
' North Avenue ' was painted . The illusion was so vivid
that I could hardly believe my eyes had deceived me. All
reading is more or less performed in this way.
" Practised novel- or newspaper-readers could not possi-
bly get on so fast if they had to see accurately every single
letter of every word in order to perceive the words. More
than half of the words come out of their mind, and hardly
half from the printed page. Were this not so, did we per-
ceive each letter by itself, typographic errors in well-known.
words would never be overlooked . Children, whose ideas
are not yet ready enough to perceive words at a glance,
read them wrong if they are printed wrong, that is, right
according to the way of printing. In a foreign language,
although it may be printed with the same letters , we read
by so much the more slowly as we do not understand , or
are unable promptly to perceive, the words. But we notice
misprints all the more readily. For this reason Latin and
Greek, and still better Hebrew, works are more correctly
printed , because the proofs are better corrected , than in
German works. Of two friends of mine, one knew much
Hebrew, the other little ; the latter, however, gave instruc-
tion in Hebrew in a gymnasium ; and when he called the
other to help correct his pupils' exercises, it turned out
that he could find out all sorts of little errors better than
his friend, because the latter's perception of the words as
totals was too swift." *
Testimony to personal identity is proverbiallyfallacious
for similar reasons . A man has witnessed a rapid crime
or accident, and carries away his mental image. Later he
is confronted by a prisoner whom he forthwith perceives
in the light of that image, and recognizes or ' identifies ' as
the criminal, although he may never have been near the
spot. Similarly at the so-called ' materializing séances '
which fraudulent mediums give : in a dark room a man
sees a gauze-robed figure who in a whisper tells him she is
the spirit of his sister, mother, wife, or child, and falls
upon his neck. The darkness, the previous forms, and the
expectancy have so filled his mind with premonitory
images that it is no wonder he perceives what is suggested .
These fraudulent séances ' would furnish most precious
documents to the psychology of perception, if they could
only be satisfactorily inquired into. In the hypnotic
trance any suggested object is sensibly perceived. In cer-
tain subjects this happens more or less completely after
waking from the trance. It would seem that under favor-
able conditions a somewhat similar susceptibility to sug-
called the first whole eggs he saw ' potatoes,' having been
accustomed to see his ' eggs ' broken into a glass , and his
potatoes without the skin. A folding pocket-corkscrew he
unhesitatingly called ' bad -scissors. ' Hardly any one of us
can make new heads easily when fresh experiences come.
Most of us grow more and more enslaved to the stock con-
ceptions with which we have once become familiar, and
less and less capable of assimilating impressions in any
but the old ways. Old-fogyism, in short, is the inevitable
terminus to which life sweeps us on. Objects which vio-
" 1
late our established habits of apperception ' are simply
not taken account of at all ; or, if on some occasion we are
forced by dint of argument to admit their existence,
twenty-four hours later the admission is as if it were not ,
and every trace of the unassimilable truth has vanished
from our thought. Genius, in truth , means little more
than the faculty of perceiving in an unhabitual way.
On the other hand , nothing is more congenial, from
babyhood to the end of life, than to be able to assimilate
the new to the old, to meet each threatening violator or
burster of our well -known series of concepts, as it comes
in, see through its unwontedness, and ticket it off as an
old friend in disguise. This victorious assimilation of the
new is in fact the type of all intellectual pleasure. The lust
for it is scientific curiosity. The relation of the new to the
old , before the assimilation is performed , is wonder. We
feel neither curiosity nor wonder concerning things so far
beyond us that we have no concepts to refer them to or
standards by which to measure them. * The Fuegians, in
off a cannon straight at you , what should you do ? ' ' Get out of the
way,' would be the answer. ' No need of that, ' the teacher might
reply. You may quietly go to sleep in your room , and get up again,
you may wait till your confirmation -day, you may learn a trade, and
grow as old as I am, -then only will the cannon-ball be getting near,
then you may jump to one side ! See , so great as that is the sun's
distance! ' " (K. Lange, Ueber Apperception, 1879, p. 76. )
330 PSYCHOLOGY.
then have expressed it. The surprise cooled me, and the
discussion was dropped .
"Some minutes after, having occasion to speak to my
brother, I turned towards him, but he was gone. I in-
quired when he left the room, and was told that he had
not been in it, which I did not believe, thinking that he
had come in for a minute and had gone out without being
noticed. About an hour and a half afterwards he appeared ,
and convinced me, with some trouble, that he had never
been near the house that evening. He is still alive and
vell."
The hallucinations of fever-delirium are a mixture of
pseudo-hallucination, true hallucination, and illusion.
Those of opium, haschish, and belladonna resemble them
in this respect. The commonest hallucination of all is that
of hearing one's own name called aloud . Nearly one half
of the sporadic cases which I have collected are of this
sort.
Hallucination and Illusion.- Hallucinations are easily
produced by verbal suggestion in hypnotic subjects. Thus,
point to a dot on a sheet of paper, and call it ‘ General
Grant's photograph,' and your subject will see a photo-
graph of the General there instead of the dot. The dot
gives objectivity to the appearance, and the suggested
notion of the General gives it form. Then magnify the
dot by a lens ; double it by a prism or by nudging the eye-
ball ; reflect it in a mirror ; turn it upside-down ; or wipe
it out ; and the subject will tell you that the ' photograph '
has been enlarged, doubled , reflected, turned about, or
made to disappear. In M. Binet's language, the dot is the
outward point de repère which is needed to give objectivity
to your suggestion , and without which the latter will only
produce an inner image in the subject's mind. M. Binet has
shown that such a peripheral point de repère is used in an
enormous number, not only of hypnotic hallucinations, but
of hallucinations of the insane. These latter are often uni-
lateral; that is, the patient hears the voices always on one
PERCEPTION. 333
side of him, or sees the figure only when a certain one of his
eyes is open. In many of these cases it has been distinctly
proved that a morbid irritation in the internal ear, or an
opacity in the humors of the eye, was the starting point of
the current which the patient's diseased acoustic or optical
centres clothed with their peculiar products in the way of
ideas. Hallucinations produced in this way are illusions ' ;
and M. Binet's theory, that all hallucinations must start in
the periphery, may be called an attempt to reduce hallucina-
tion and illusion to one physiological type, the type, namely,
to which normal perception belongs. In every case, accord-
ing to M. Binet, whether of perception, of hallucination ,
or of illusion, we get the sensational vividness by means of
a current from the peripheral nerves. It may be a mere
trace of a current. But that trace is enough to kindle the
maximal process of disintegration in the cells (cf. p . 310) ,
and to give to the object perceived the character of exter-
nality. What the nature of the object shall be will depend
wholly on the particular system of paths in which the pro-
cess is kindled . Part of the thing in all cases comes from
the sense organ, the rest is furnished by the mind . But
we cannot by introspection distinguish between these parts ;
and our only formula for the result is that the brain has
reacted on the impression in the resulting way.
M. Binet's theory accounts indeed for a multitude of
cases, but certainly not for all. The prism does not always
double the false appearance, nor does the latter always dis-
appear when the eyes are closed . For Binet, an abnor-
mally or exclusively active part of the cortex gives the
nature of what shall appear, whilst a peripheral sense-
organ alone can give the intensity sufficient to make it
appear projected into real space. But since this intensity.
is after all but a matter of degree, one does not see why,
under rare conditions, the degree in question might not
be attained by inner causes exclusively. In that case we
should have certain hallucinations centrally initiated , as
well as the peripherally initiated hallucinations which are
334 PSYCHOLOGY.
a d
that is when our eyes and the object both are in what may
be called the normal position. In this position our head is
upright and our optic axes either parallel or symmetrically
convergent ; the plane of the object is perpendicular to the
visual plane ; and if the object is one containing many
lines, it is turned so as to make them, as far as possible,
either parallel or perpendicular to the visual plane. In this
situation it is that we compare all shapes with each other ;
here every exact measurement and every decision is made.
Most sensations are signs to us of other sensations whose
space-value is held to be more real. The thing as it would
appear to the eye if it were in the normal position is what
we think of whenever we get one of the other optical views.
Only as represented in the normal position do we believe
we see the object as it is ; elsewhere, only as it seems.
Experience and custom soon teach us, however, that the
seeming appearance passes into the real one by continuous
gradations. They teach us, moreover, that seeming and
being may be strangely interchanged . Now a real circle
may slide into a seeming ellipse ; now an ellipse may, by
sliding in the same direction, become a seeming circle ;
now a rectangular cross grows slant-legged ; now a slant-
legged one grows rectangular.
Almost any form in oblique vision may be thus a deriva-
tive of almost any other in ' primary ' vision ; and we must
learn, when we get one of the former appearances, to trans-
late it into the appropriate one of the latter class ; we must
learn of what optical ' reality ' it is one of the optical signs.
Having learned this, we do but obey that law of economy
or simplification which dominates our whole psychic life,
when we think exclusively of the ' reality ' and ignore as
much as our consciousness will let us the ' sign ' by which
we came to apprehend it. The signs of each probable real
thing being multiple and the thing itself one and fixed,
we gain the same mental relief by abandoning the former
for the latter that we do when we abandon mental images ,
with all their fluctuating characters, for the definite and
346 PSYCHOLOGY.
REASONING.
M is P;
S is M ;
... S is P
354 PSYCHOLOGY.
-we see that the second or minor premise, the ' subsump-
tion ' as it is sometimes called, is the one requiring the
sagacity ; the first or major the one requiring the fertility,
or fulness of learning. Usually the learning is more apt to
be ready than the sagacity, the ability to seize fresh aspects
in concrete things being rarer than the ability to learn old
rules ; so that, in most actual cases of reasoning, the minor
premise, or the way of conceiving the subject, is the one
that makes the novel step in thought. This is, to be sure,
not always the case ; for the fact that M carries P with it
may also be unfamiliar and now formulated for the first
time.
The perception that S is M is a mode of conceiving S.
The statement that M is P is an abstract or general propo-
sition. A word about both is necessary.
What is meant by a Mode of Conceiving. -When we con-
ceive of S merely as M (of vermilion merely as a mercury-
compound, for example), we neglect all the other attri-
butes which it may have, and attend exclusively to this
one. We mutilate the fulness of S's reality. Every reality
has an infinity of aspects or properties. Even so simple a
fact as a line which you trace in the air may be considered
in respect to its form, its length, its direction, and its loca-
tion. When we reach more complex facts, the number of
ways in which we may regard them is literally endless.
Vermilion is not only a mercury-compound, it is vividly
red, heavy, and expensive, it comes from China, and so on,
ad infinitum. All objects are well-springs of properties,
which are only little by little developed to our knowledge,
and it is truly said that to know one thing thoroughly
would be to know the whole universe. Mediately or im-
mediately, that one thing is related to everything else ; and
to know all about it, all its relations need be known. But
each relation forms one of its attributes, one angle by
which some one may conceive it, and while so conceiving
it may ignore the rest of it. A man is such a complex
fact. But out of the complexity all that an army com
REASONING. 355
them than any others ; they are only more frequently ser-
viceable ways to us.
Reasoning is always for a subjective interest. To re-
vert now to our symbolic representation of the reasoning
process :
M is P
S is M
S is P
M is discerned and picked out for the time being to be
the essence of the concrete fact, phenomenon, or reality, S.
But M in this world of ours is inevitably conjoined with
P; so that P is the next thing that we may expect to find
conjoined with the fact S. We may conclude or infer P,
through the intermediation of the M which our sagacity
began by discerning, when S came before it, to be the es-
sence of the case.
Now note that if P have any value or importance for us,
M was a very good character for our sagacity to pounce
upon and abstract. If, on the contrary, P were of no im-
portance, some other character than M would have been a
better essence for us to conceive of S by. Psychologically,
as a rule, P overshadows the process from the start. We
are seeking P, or something like P. But the bare totality
of S does not yield it to our gaze ; and casting about for
some point in S to take hold of which will lead us to P,
we hit, if we are sagacious, upon M, because M happens to
be just the character which is knit up with P. Had we
wished Q instead of P, and were N a property of S conjoined
with Q, we ought to have ignored M, noticed N, and con-
ceived of S as a sort of N exclusively.
Reasoning is always to attain some particular conclusion ,
or to gratify some special curiosity. It not only breaks
up the datum placed before it and conceives it abstractly;
it must conceive it rightly too ; and conceiving it rightly
means conceiving it by that one particular abstract charac-
ter which leads to the one sort of conclusion which it is
the reasoner's temporary interest to attain.
REASONING. 359
E B
D о
FIG. 66.
posed the name recept, and Prof. Lloyd Morgan the name
construct, for the idea of a vaguely abstracted and gener-
alized object-class. A definite abstraction is called an
isolate by the latter author. Neither construct nor recept
seems to me a felicitous word ; but poor as both are, they
form a distinct addition to psychology, so I give them
here. Would such a word as influent sound better than
recept in the following passage from Romanes ?
" Water-fowl adopt a somewhat different mode of alight-
ing upon land, or even upon ice, from that which they
adopt when alighting upon water ; and those kinds which
dive from a height (such as terns and gannets) never do
so upon land or upon ice. These facts prove that the
animals have one recept answering to a solid surface,
and another answering to a fluid. Similarly a man will
not dive from a height over hard ground or over ice,
nor will he jump into water in the same way as he jumps.
upon dry land. In other words, like the water-fowl he has
two distinct recepts, one of which answers to solid ground ,
and the other to an unresisting fluid. But unlike the
water-fowl he is able to bestow upon each of these recepts
a name, and thus to raise them both to the level of con-
cepts. So far as the practical purposes of locomotion are
concerned, it is of course immaterial whether or not he
thus raises his recepts into concepts ; but . . . for many
other purposes it is of the highest importance that he is
able to do this. " *
A certain well-bred retriever of whom I know never bit
his birds. But one day having to bring two birds at once,
which, though unable to fly, were alive and kicking,' he
deliberately gave one a bite which killed it, took the other
one still alive to his master, and then returned for the first.
It is impossible not to believe that some such abstract
thoughts as alive-get away-must kill,' . . . etc., passed in
rapid succession through this dog's mind, whatever the
EMOTION.
the rest of the chapter I shall use the word object of emo-
tion indifferently to mean one which is physically present
or one which is merely thought of.
The varieties of emotion are innumerable. Anger, fear,
love, hate, joy, grief, shame, pride, and their varieties, may
be called the coarser emotions, being coupled as they are
with relatively strong bodily reverberations. The subtler
emotions are the moral, intellectual, and æsthetic feelings,
and their bodily reaction is usually much less strong. The
mere description of the objects, circumstances, and varie-
ties of the different species of emotion may go to any
length. Their internal shadings merge endlessly into each
other, and have been partly commemorated in language,
as, for example, by such synonyms as hatred, antipathy,
animosity, resentment, dislike, aversion, malice, spite, re-
venge, abhorrence, etc. , etc. Dictionaries of synonyms
have discriminated them, as well as text-books of psychol-
ogy - in fact, many German psychological text-books are
nothing but dictionaries of synonyms when it comes to the
chapter on Emotion. But there are limits to the profitable
elaboration of the obvious, and the result of all this flux is
that the merely descriptive literature of the subject, from
Descartes downwards, is one of the most tedious parts of
psychology. And not only is it tedious, but you feel that
its subdivisions are to a great extent either fictitious or
unimportant, and that its pretences to accuracy are a
sham . But unfortunately there is little psychological
writing about the emotions which is not merely descriptive.
As emotions are described in novels, they interest us, for
we are made to share them. We have grown acquainted
with the concrete objects and emergencies which call them
forth, and any knowing touch of introspection which may
grace the page meets with a quick and feeling response.
Confessedly literary works of aphoristic philosophy also
flash lights into our emotional life, and give us a fitful
delight. But as far as the scientific psychology ' of the
emotions goes, I may have been surfeited by too much
EMOTION. 375
INSTINCT.
6
liability of such arcs is to have their activity inhibited ' by
other processes going on at the same time. It makes no
difference whether the arc be organized at birth, or ripen
spontaneously later, or be due to acquired habit ; it must
take its chances with all the other arcs, and sometimes
succeed, and sometimes fail, in drafting off the currents
through itself. The mystical view of an instinct would
make it invariable. The physiological view would require
it to show occasional irregularities in any animal in whom
the number of separate instincts, and the possible entrance
of the same stimulus into several of them, were great.
And such irregularities are what every superior animal's
instincts do show in abundance.
Wherever the mind is elevated enough to discriminate ;
wherever several distinct sensory elements must combine
to discharge the reflex arc ; wherever, instead of plumping
into action instantly at the first rough intimation of what
sort of a thing is there, the agent waits to see which one of
its kind it is and what the circumstances are of its appear-
ance ; wherever different individuals and different circum-
stances can impel him in different ways ; wherever these
are the conditions -we have a masking of the elementary
constitution of the instinctive life. The whole story of
our dealings with the lower wild animals is the history
of our taking advantage of the way in which they judge
of everything by its mere label, as it were, so as to ensnare
or kill them. Nature, in them, has left matters in this
rough way, and made them act always in the manner
which would be oftenest right. There are more worms
unattached to hooks than impaled upon them ; therefore ,
on the whole, says Nature to her fishy children, bite at
every worm and take your chances. But as her children
get higher, and their lives more precious, she reduces the
risks . Since what seems to be the same object may be
now a genuine food and now a bait ; since in gregarious
species each individual may prove to be either the friend
or the rival, according to the circumstances, of another ;
398 PSYCHOLOGY.
returned to the mother when ten days old. The hen fol-
lowed it, and tried to entice it in every way ; still, it con-
tinually left her and ran to the house or to any person of
whom it caught sight. This it persisted in doing, though
beaten back with a small branch dozens of times, and, in-
deed, cruelly maltreated . It was also placed under the
mother at night, but it again left her in the morning. "
The instinct of sucking is ripe in all nammals at birth,
and leads to that habit of taking the breast which, in the
human infant, may be prolonged by daily exercise long
beyond its usual term of a year or a year and a half. But
the instinct itself is transient, in the sense that if, for any
reason , the child be fed by spoon during the first few days
of its life and not put to the breast, it may be no easy
matter after that to make it suck at all. So of calves. If
their mother die, or be dry, or refuse to let them suck for
a day or two, so that they are fed by hand, it becomes hard
to get them to suck at all when a new nurse is provided .
The ease with which sucking creatures are weaned, by
simply breaking the habit and giving them food in a new
way, shows that the instinct, purely as such, must be en-
tirely extinct.
Assuredly the simple fact that instincts are transient,
and that the effect of later ones may be altered by the
habits which earlier ones have left behind , is a far more
philosophical explanation than the notion of an instinctive
constitution vaguely ' deranged ' or ' thrown out of gear.'
I have observed a Scotch terrier, born on the floor of a
stable in December, and transferred six weeks later to a
carpeted house, make, when he was less than four months
old, a very elaborate pretence of burying things, such as
gloves, etc., with which he had played till he was tired .
He scratched the carpet with his forefeet, dropped the
object from his mouth upon the spot, then scratched all
about it, and finally went away and let it lie. Of cours
the act was entirely useless. I saw him perform it o
age some four or five times, and never again in
404 PSYCHOLOGY
WILL.
nervation itself is. The mind does not need it ; the end
alone is enough.
The idea of the end, then, tends more and more to
make itself all - sufficient. Or, at any rate, if the kinæs-
thetic ideas are called up at all, they are so swamped in
the vivid kinæsthetic feelings by which they are immedi-
ately overtaken that we have no time to be aware of their
separate existence. As I write, I have no anticipation, as
a thing distinct from my sensation, of either the look or
the digital feel of the letters which flow from my pen.
The words chime on my mental ear, as it were, before I
write them, but not on my mental eye or hand. This
comes from the rapidity with which the movements follow
on their mental cue. An end consented to as soon as con-
ceived innervates directly the centre of the first movement
of the chain which leads to its accomplishment, and then
the whole chain rattles off quasi-reflexly, as was described
on pp. 115-6.
The reader will certainly recognize this to be true in all
fluent and unhesitating voluntary acts. The only special
fiat there is at the outset of the performance. A man says
to himself, " I must change my clothes," and involuntarily
he has taken off his coat, and his fingers are at work in
their accustomed manner on his waistcoat-buttons, etc .;
or we say, " I must go downstairs," and ere we know it we
have risen, walked , and turned the handle of the door ; --
all through the idea of an end coupled with a series of
guiding sensations which successively arise. It would
seem indeed that we fail of accuracy and certainty in our
attainment of the end whenever we are preoccupied with
the way in which the movement will feel. We walk a beam
the better the less we think of the position of our feet upon
it. We pitch or catch, we shoot or chop the better the
less tactile and muscular (the less resident ) , and the more
exclusively optical (the more remote) , our consciousness
is. Keep your eye on the place aimed at, and your hand
will fetch it ; think of your hand , and you will very likely
422 PSYCHOLOGY.
the warmth and the cold ; we fall into some revery con-
nected with the day's life, in the course of which the idea
flashes across us, " Hollo ! I must lie here no longer "-an
idea which at that lucky instant awakens no contradictory
or paralyzing suggestions, and consequently produces im-
mediately its appropriate motor effects. It was our acute
consciousness of both the warmth and the cold during the
period of struggle, which paralyzed our activity then and
kept our idea of rising in the condition of wish and not
of will. The moment these inhibitory ideas ceased, the
original idea exerted its effects.
This case seems to me to contain in miniature form the
data for an entire psychology of volition. It was in fact
through meditating on the phenomenon in my own person
that I first became convinced of the truth of the doctrine
which these pages present, and which I need here illustrate
by no farther examples. The reason why that doctrine is
not a self-evident truth is that we have so many ideas
which do not result in action. But it will be seen that in
every such case, without exception, that is because other
ideas simultaneously present rob them of their impulsive
power. But even here, and when a movement is inhibited
from completely taking place by contrary ideas, it will
incipiently take place. To quote Lotze once more :
"The spectator accompanies the throwing of a billiard-
ball, or the thrust of the swordsman, with slight move-
ments of his arm ; the untaught narrator tells his story
with many gesticulations ; the reader while absorbed in the
perusal of a battle- scene feels a slight tension run through
his muscular system, keeping time as it were with the
actions he is reading of. These results become the more
marked the more we are absorbed in thinking of the
movements which suggest them ; they grow fainter ex-
actly in proportion as a complex consciousness, under the
dominion of a crowd of other representations, withstands
the passing over of mental contemplation into outward
action. "
426 PSYCHOLOGY.
the evidence is all in, and that reason has balanced the
books, may be either present or absent. But in either case
we feel, in deciding, as if we ourselves by our own wilful
act inclined the beam : in the former case by adding our
living effort to the weight of the logical reason which,
taken alone, seems powerless to make the act discharge ;
in the latter by a kind of creative contribution of some-
thing instead of a reason which does a reason's work. The
slow dead heave of the will that is felt in these instances
makes of them a class altogether different subjectively
from all the four preceding classes. What the heave of
the will betokens metaphysically, what the effort might
lead us to infer about a will-power distinct from motives,
are not matters that concern us yet. Subjectively and
phenomenally, the feeling ofeffort, absent from the former
decisions, accompanies these. Whether it be the dreary
resignation for the sake of austere and naked duty of all
sorts of rich mundane delights ; or whether it be the heavy
resolve that of two mutually exclusive trains of future
fact, both sweet and good and with no strictly objective
or imperative principle of choice between them, one shall
forevermore become impossible, while the other shall be
come reality ; it is a desolate and acrid sort of act, an en-
trance into a lonesome moral wilderness. If examined
closely, its chief difference from the former cases appears
to be that in those cases the mind at the moment of de-
ciding on the triumphant alternative dropped the other
one wholly or nearly out of sight, whereas here both alter-
natives are steadily held in view, and in the very act of
murdering the vanquished possibility the chooser realizes
how much in that instant he is making himself lose. It
is deliberately driving a thorn into one's flesh ; and the
sense of inward effort with which the act is accompanied
is an element which sets this fifth type of decision in
strong contrast with the previous four varieties, and makes
of it an altogether peculiar sort of mental phenomenon.
The immense majority of human decisions are decisions
434 PSYCHOLOGY.
his life. The hero and the neurotic subject, on the other
hand, do. Now our spontaneous way of conceiving the
effort, under all these circumstances, is as an active force
adding its strength to that of the motives which ultimately
prevail. When cuter forces impinge upon a body, we say
that the resultant motion is in the line of least resistance,
or of greatest traction. But it is a curious fact that our
spontaneous language never speaks of volition with effort
in this way. Of course if we proceed a priori and define
the line of least resistance as the line that is followed, the
physical law must also hold good in the mental sphere.
But we feel, in all hard cases of volition, as if the line
taken, when the rarer and more ideal motives prevail , were
the line of greater resistance , and as if the line of coarser
motivation were the more pervious and easy one, even at
the very moment when we refuse to follow it. He who
under the surgeon's knife represses cries of pain , or he
who exposes himself to social obloquy for duty's sake, feels
as if he were following the line of greatest temporary re-
sistance. He speaks of conquering and overcoming his
impulses and temptations.
But the sluggard, the drunkard , the coward, never talk
of their conduct in that way, or say they resist their energy,
overcome their sobriety, conquer their courage, and so
forth. If in general we class all springs of action as pro-
pensities on the one hand and ideals on the other, the sen-
sualist never says of his behavior that it results from a
victory over his ideals, but the moralist always speaks of
his as a victory over his propensities. The sensualist uses
terms of inactivity, says he forgets his ideals, is deaf to
duty, and so forth ; which terms seem to imply that the
ideal motives per se can be annulled without energy or
effort , and that the strongest mere traction lies in the line
of the propensities. The ideal impulse appears, in com-
parison with this, a still small voice which must be artifi-
cially reinforced to prevail. Effort is what reinforces it,
making things seem as if, while the force of propensity
444 PSYCHOLOGY.
that this is so, for every reader must have felt some fiery
passion's grasp. What constitutes the difficulty for a man
laboring under an unwise passion of acting as if the pas-
sion were wise ? Certainly there is no physical difficulty.
It is as easy physically to avoid a fight as to begin one, to
pocket one's money as to squander it on one's cupidities,
to walk away from as towards a coquette's door. The dif-
ficulty is mental : it is that of getting the idea of the wise
action to stay before our mind at all. When any strong
emotional state whatever is upon us, the tendency is for no
images but such as are congruous with it to come up. If
others by chance offer themselves, they are instantly smoth-
ered and crowded out. If we be joyous, we cannot keep
thinking of those uncertainties and risks of failure which
abound upon our path ; if lugubrious, we cannot think of
new triumphs, travels, loves, and joys ; nor if vengeful, of
our oppressor's community of nature with ourselves . The
cooling advice which we get from others when the fever-
fit is on us is the most jarring and exasperating thing in
life. Reply we cannot, so we get angry ; for by a sort of
self-preserving instinct which our passion has, it feels that
these chill objects, if they once but gain a lodgment, will
work and work until they have frozen the very vital spark
from out of all our mood and brought our airy castles in
ruin to the ground . Such is the inevitable effect of rea-
sonable ideas over others- if they can once get a quiet hear-
ing; and passion's cue accordingly is always and every-
where to prevent their still small voice from being heard
at all. " Let me not think of that ! Don't speak to me
of that !" This is the sudden cry of all those who in a
passion perceive some sobering considerations about to
check them in mid-career. There is something so icy in
this cold-water bath, something which seems so hostile to
sations from his muscular passivity. The action of his will, in sus-
taining the expectation, is identical with that required for a painful
muscular effort. What is hard for both is facing an idea as real.
452 PSYCHOLOGY.
pendent variable ' amongst the fixed data of the case, our
motives, character, etc. If it be really so, if the amount of
our effort is not a determinate function of those other data,
then, in common parlance, our wills are free. If, on the
contrary, the amount of effort be a fixed function , so that
whatever object at any time fills our consciousness was
from eternity bound to fill it then and there, and compel
from us the exact effort, neither more nor less, which we
bestow upon it, then our wills are not free, and all our
acts are foreordained . The question of fact in the free-
will controversy is thus extremely simple. It relates solely
to the amount of effort of attention which we can at any
time put forth. Are the duration and intensity of this
effort fixed functions of the object, or are they not ? Now,
as I just said, it seems as if we might exert more or less
in any given case. When a man has let his thoughts go
for days and weeks until at last they culminate in some
particularly dirty or cowardly or cruel act, it is hard to
persuade him, in the midst of his remorse, that he might
not have reined them in ; hard to make him believe that
this whole goodly universe (which his act so jars upon)
required and exacted it of him at that fatal moment, and
from eternity made aught else impossible. But, on the
other hand, there is the certainty that all his effortless voli-
tions are resultants of interests and associations whose
strength and sequence are mechanically determined by the
structure of that physical mass, his brain ; and the general
continuity of things and the monistic conception of the
world may lead one irresistibly to postulate that a little
fact like effort can form no real exception to the over-
whelming reign of deterministic law. Even in effortless
volition we have the consciousness of the alternative being
also possible. This is surely a delusion here ; why is it
not a delusion everywhere ?
The fact is that the question of free - will is insoluble on
strictly psychologic grounds. After a certain amount of
effort of attention has been given to an idea, it is mani-
WILL. 457
tween the past and future and has no breadth of its own.
Where everything is change and process, how can we talk
of ' state ' ? Yet how can we do without states,' in de-
scribing what the vehicles of our knowledge seem to be ?
States of consciousness themselves are not verifiable facts.
But 6 worse remains behind.' Neither common -sense, nor
psychology so far as it has yet been written, has ever
doubted that the states of consciousness which that science
studies are immediate data of experience. Things ' have
been doubted, but thoughts and feelings have never been
doubted. The outer world, but never the inner world,
has been denied . Everyone assumes that we have direct
introspective acquaintance with our thinking activity as
such, with our consciousness as something inward and
contrasted with the outer objects which it knows. Yet I
must confess that for my part I cannot feel sure of this
conclusion. Whenever I try to become sensible of my
thinking activity as such, what I catch is some bodily
fact, an impression coming from my brow, or head , or
throat, or nose. It seems as if consciousness as an inner
activity were rather a postulate than a sensibly given fact,
the postulate, namely, of a knower as correlative to all
this known ; and as if ' sciousness ' might be a better
word by which to describe it. But ' sciousness postulated
as an hypothesis ' is practically a very different thing from
' states of consciousness apprehended with infallible cer.
tainty by an inner sense.' For one thing, it throws the
question of who the knower really is wide open again, and
makes the answer which we gave to it at the end of
Chapter XII a mere provisional statement from a popular
and prejudiced point of view.
Conclusion. When, then, we talk of psychology as a
natural science,' we must not assume that that means a
sort of psychology that stands at last on solid ground. It
means just the reverse ; it means a psychology particularly
fragile, and into which the waters of metaphysical criticism
leak at every joint , a psvchology all of whose elementary
468 PSYCHOLOGY.
THE END.
INDEX.
NOV 14 1958
1969
M A R - 6
SEP 1 5 1971
APR 11 2002
APR - 2 2002
1102
K121 James , W.
07
J28 Psvah 1104
191z James ,olWo.gy
h
Psyc
K121 DATE DUE
J28 3
191
NAME
58
Y 19
N 4.
es t
Am Res Cen Life Sci.
நீ
MAR
cED
chi 15 1973
Psy
2-48-5M
PSYCHOLOGY
JAMES