0% found this document useful (0 votes)
28 views1 page

Cantors Theorem

Cantor's Theorem states that a set S cannot have the same cardinality as its power set P(S), meaning there is no function from S onto P(S). The proof involves constructing a subset A of S that cannot be reached by any function mapping S to P(S). This implies that P(S) is always larger than S, even for infinite sets, and the process can be iterated to create increasingly larger sets.

Uploaded by

nguyenhoangthanh
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
28 views1 page

Cantors Theorem

Cantor's Theorem states that a set S cannot have the same cardinality as its power set P(S), meaning there is no function from S onto P(S). The proof involves constructing a subset A of S that cannot be reached by any function mapping S to P(S). This implies that P(S) is always larger than S, even for infinite sets, and the process can be iterated to create increasingly larger sets.

Uploaded by

nguyenhoangthanh
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 1

Cantor’s Theorem

For a set S, define its power set (denoted P(S)) to be the set whose members are the subsets of S.
For example, if S is the two-element set {1, 2}, then P(S) = {∅, {1}, {2}, {1, 2}}. Thus P(S) is always a
set of sets.
If S is a finite set with n elements, then P(S) contains 2n elements. (This is because to form a subset
of S, we can go through the n elements, deciding for each whether to put it into the subset or leave it
out—two choices. There are 2n ways of making the n choices.) This hold even for n = 0; the power set
of ∅ is the one-element set {∅}.
It is always true that n < 2n , and therefore a finite set is always strictly smaller than its power set.
Something analogous holds for all sets:

Cantor’s Theorem (1873). A set never has the same cardinality as its power set. In fact, for
any set S, there is no function from S onto its power set.

Proof: Consider any set S and any function f from S to P(S). We want to show that f is not onto
P(S). For that purpose, it suffices to find some subset A of S that is not in the range of f .
Here it is:
A = {x ∈ S | x ∈
/ f (x)}.
The definition of A makes sense; whenever x is in S, then f (x) will be a subset of S, and it might or
might not contain x itself.
At least A ⊆ S. It remains to verify that A in not in the range of f . That is, we need to be sure
that for each x0 in S, we have A 6= f (x0 ). We have by the construction of A,
x0 ∈ A ⇐⇒ x0 ∈
/ f (x0 ).
But this tells us that the two sets A and f (x0 ) differ in at least one way: one of the two contains x0 and
the other does not! a

Example: IN and P(IN ) do not have the same cardinality, so P(IN ) is uncountable. The above proof
of Cantor’s theorem, when we take S to be IN , is closely related to the proof on page 18 that the reals
are uncountable.
For any non-empty set S, it is easy to find a function from P(S) onto S. (How?) So in a sense, we
can “cover” S by P(S). Cantor’s theorem tells us that we cannot, in this sense, cover P(S) by S. So
there is a sense in which P(S) is larger than S, even when S is infinite.
We can iterate the power-set operation: S, P(S), P(P(S)), . . ., obtaining larger and larger sets.
There is no largest set.

H. B. Enderton

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy