This document introduces philosophical thinking, emphasizing its pursuit of wisdom and knowledge through reason and experience. It explores various philosophical perspectives from figures like Aristotle, Descartes, Hume, Kant, and Foucault, highlighting their views on the nature of knowledge, causation, and the societal role of philosophy. The text also acknowledges the existence of philosophical thought beyond Western traditions, asserting that philosophical inquiry is a universal human endeavor.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes)
45 views6 pages
On Philosophical Thinking
This document introduces philosophical thinking, emphasizing its pursuit of wisdom and knowledge through reason and experience. It explores various philosophical perspectives from figures like Aristotle, Descartes, Hume, Kant, and Foucault, highlighting their views on the nature of knowledge, causation, and the societal role of philosophy. The text also acknowledges the existence of philosophical thought beyond Western traditions, asserting that philosophical inquiry is a universal human endeavor.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 6
On Philosophical Thinking
This section will introduce you to philosophical thinking. As an introduction, it
will clarify the key concepts as “philosophical” and “thinking.” While selective, this module will include philosophical thinking as gaining wisdom, knowledge based on reason, experience, and engaging in rational discussion that will have an impact on society and thinking itself. Offhand, how these words are understood now would be nuanced depending on the inclinations or views of different philosophers. Martin Heidegger, for instance, considers thinking as “memory, thinking that recalls, thanks.” (Heidegger, What Is Called Thinking, 244) Put differently, it is a mental activity that pays homage to a source that makes thought possible. But thinking as a gerund can just be a generic term for a mental activity as in the case of imagining, dreaming, analysing, solving puzzles, willing, etc. In addition, “philosophical” can mean engaging in abstruse or deep thought, that is, sounding difficult to understand, as when a person remarks on another’s thinking as “You sound so philosophical.” In all these, one can notice the difficulty of making sense of the question on philosophical thinking. In this regard, in this introductory section, it must be borne in mind that this discussion in no way puts finality to the meaning of these two words; it offers no claim what philosophical thing should be. It merely accounts, rather selectively, the possible meanings that can be found in the tradition among philosophers. The way to begin is to trace the qualifying word “philosophical,” to go back to “memory,” to philosophy. As previously encountered in the preparatory course, philosophy is a combination of Greek root words “philia” (love) and “sophia” (wisdom). On the one hand, however it is interpreted, love entails a strong affection, if not devotion, for its object—wisdom in this case. Wisdom, on the other hand, signifies profound science, learning or knowledge. Thus, the philosophical aspect manifests a strong inclination for deep and cultivated knowledge. This strong inclination could have been initiated by the fascination for the external world. How does this etymological distinction shed light on philosophical thinking? We can gain insight into this by understanding how philosophers conduct their activities. Pythagoras, who was said to have coined the term philosophy, showed such activity by being constantly preoccupied by the question concerning the primary principle of things, the basic stuff that constitutes things. Long before him, early ancient philosophers who wondered about the same concern associated this ultimate principle to such elementary substances as earth, air, water, and fire. Meanwhile, Pythagoras and his followers held that the “infinity and unity itself were the substance of the things of which they are predicated. This is why the number was the substance of all things” (see Aristotle, Metaphysics 987a 17-19). For them, what underlies all things is not sensible; numbers are not objects of sense perception—things can be numbered; numbers are not things (in this instance, we consider things as having material or physical existence). Curiously, the attention expended by these ancient philosophers to look for the ultimate constitution of things was admirable; they did not settle for knowledge of the appearance of but the explanation behind things. They were absorbed in the fundamental question of the appearance of things. Perhaps, they too wrestled the basic question that still resonates to this day: “Why is there something rather than nothing?” Whether this tendency to ask into the nature of things was driven by an inherent inclination on the part of the inquirer or by the allure of the reason itself was not the point here, rather the character of that thinking which they qualified as philosophical. The philosophical thinking, it can be drawn from above, involves seeking for that knowledge that would explain the existence of the material phenomena. Of course, these philosophers could not agree on that specific principle as they provided that varied answers. Nevertheless, they provided justifications for their answers. Following on the notion, Aristotle clarified what philosophy is as love of wisdom. For him, knowledge of wisdom is not that of experience, that is, knowledge acquired through the senses. Any person who knows through the senses may gain knowledge that things exist but they may need not know “why” they exist. Wisdom requires that one knows the “why” of things. For Aristotle, “wisdom is knowledge of certain principles and causes” (Aristotle, Metaphysics 982a 1). The causes Aristotle was referring to are the material, formal, efficient, and final causes. Briefly, the material cause is the substance from which a thing exists; the formal cause is the essence or the substantial characteristics that differentiate a thing from another which may possess similar substance; efficient cause is the one that effects change in a thing; and, final cause is the purpose or the end of change. In this respect, knowledge of these four causes, for Aristotle, would be wisdom. Based on this Aristotelian claim, philosophical thinking requires the pursuit of the ultimate causes of things; philosophical activities can be circumscribed in the search for the causes of reality. Rene Descartes (1596-1650) took differently what philosophical thinking entails. Although his view appeared sympathetic to the previous idea of doing philosophy by putting little importance to sensory knowledge, he differed from it when he held that acceptable knowledge or understanding must be grasped with certainty by the thinking subject; reason as cogito recognises only knowledge with clarity and distinctness without any moment for doubt. What is unique in Descartes’ thinking is the reversal of focus. Previously, ancient philosophers placed the point of knowledge and understanding on something external to the inquiring mind, that the mind beholds what possible knowledge may be disclosed by the external world. Descartes, on the contrary, shifted this point of understanding to the inquiring mind itself or the cogito, that the mind acknowledges possession of knowledge when its object submits to the conditions of clarity and distinctness as set forth by the methodic doubt. (Note: this lecture assumes that you are familiar with the method used by Descartes.) In other words, knowledge is gained when it is determined as clear and distinct without an occasion for doubt by the inquiring mind. Reason then is the measure by which wisdom is gained. In this view, Descartes added a new requirement to philosophical thinking, that is, it is rational and submits to the rules of reason. David Hume (1711-1776) would question the presumptions concerning causes and reason. On the one hand, cause from the tradition of Aristotle up to Hume’s time seemed to be beyond question and that the human mind by default accepts causation as a fact. On the other hand, reason was thought as an overarching principle for knowledge of things. In Hume’s view, experience, “lively perception,” is an inevitable source of the contents of the mind and cause is not even before experience—the notion of causation is drawn from experience. In Hume’s analysis, philosophy involves a mental activity that values the sensible world as a source of knowledge or wisdom; philosophical thinking entails not only discovering the principles or causation and subjecting forms of analysis to reason, but also valuing and examining experiences, and even causation and reason. Sympathetic to Hume’s concern, Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) offered his critiques that would cover the realm of reason and experience. His essay on “What is Enlightenment?”, however, proposed a different character of philosophical thinking. By challenging one to think, “Sapere aude!”, Kant emphasized a different aspect of doing philosophy. Without devaluing the importance of his critiques, one can notice in this essay a significant character of philosophical thinking in the societal milieu, that is, thinking must be free and has the “vocation” to aid others in achieving the ability to use their own reason; philosophical thinking engages the public to use reason, to be free, and have the resolve to think and speak for themselves. (Kant, in Politics of Truth, 35) Put differently, aside from attaining knowledge and understanding, philosophical thinking has the critical part in guiding public discourses by expressing, without fear, its prudent and well-thought ideas. By doing so, it also inspires others to recognise their ability to think independently for themselves. Another form of philosophical thinking is suggested by Michel Foucault (1926-1984). For him, philosophical thinking pursues knowledge but ventures into exploring other ways of thinking differently. Here, philosophical thinking is critical thinking, which involves what Foucault calls as the “refusal to be governed,” that is, it is not obsessed with assimilating knowledge, rather it ventures into other ways of thinking. Philosophical thinking in this sense unsettles our everyday life for it casts doubt even on what we already know just to “explore how it might be possible to think differently” (Foucault 1990, 8-9). In this thinking, knowledge is respected, but it is not regarded as absolute or certain since often it is arrived at through the competing relations of interests, concepts, strategies, positions, etc.—relations of power. Several aspects can be drawn from these views of philosophical thinking. First, the object of thought. While thinking may be inspired by the experience of sensible or conceivable things, philosophical thinking departs from them to be able to reach what can be regarded as their principles. It is dissatisfied with merely figuring out the dynamics of the material universe and is inclined towards discovering the ultimate principles of things. Ultimate cause, principle of causation, principle of sufficient reason, sufficient explanation of things—however they are called, the mind, the faculty of knowing, supposes that “metaphysical” principles can be arrived at. Second, the manner of knowing. Philosophical thinking seeks to clarify whether we can know with certainty or whether we are really capable of knowing at all; it inquires into the principles and categories of knowing. Philosophers argue, in this respect, about the bases for determining true statements about the objects of our thought. Third, the nature or properties of our thought. Given that philosophers can qualify some of the statements about the world as true, they differ in their view on the status of what we know; they argue whether our linguistic expressions or knowledge would be reliable enough to be a guide in what we do. Here, more than our knowledge claims is the application of philosophical thinking in the various worldly phenomena and other practical concerns. For instance, philosophical thinking may be used in analysing how we as human beings relate with and act towards each other considering that we significantly differ in terms of opinions or views, values, and concerns. From these samples of philosophical thinking, we now have the context for understanding some of the fields in philosophy. Here are some fields of philosophy: Metaphysics is a branch of philosophy that concerns with the ultimate principles or causes of reality. The word itself suggests a study beyond physics. Epistemology as a discipline analyses the conditions and limits of our knowledge. Its main concern is on how it is possible for us to know and how can we know that we know. Ethics, the focus of the whole course, studies what it means to act as a human being, that is, what actions are proper to being human. This field of philosophy certainly engages in practical thinking as it examines our practice. There are other fields of philosophical thought which vary only depending on their object of thinking. These fields are obviously focused on their objects: philosophy of environment, political philosophy, philosophy of science, philosophy of technology, philosophy of religion, philosophy of education, philosophy of history, and so on. In all these discussions, it might give the impression that philosophical thinking is non-existent in other geographical areas such as Asia, Africa, and America. It is not to say that philosophy is exclusive to the Greeks, although undeniably they should be credited for the sturdy philosophical tradition that thrived in their locale, and the term itself, philosophy, is etymologically Greek. But if one were to examine the philosophical thinking engaged in by philosophers in these regions, their philosophies cannot be excluded in the conversation. For instance, the notions of Tao, Brahman, Atman, Nirvana, etc. cannot fall outside the field of metaphysics. Other aspects of the ideas in these areas fall indisputably from other fields in philosophy like epistemology and ethics. Broadly, philosophising has been going on since human beings wondered about their existence and their place in the grand scheme of things. Thus, it must be borne in mind that the discussion herein only serve to shed light on philosophical thinking and other philosophies need not be excluded. In all these forms of philosophical thinking, regardless of divergence in views, regardless whether they agree on the views that they have arrived at, philosophers offer arguments, present their explanations, and most importantly, offer their proofs or supports for their views. The thought that they have arrived at is not handed down as if they must be taken on authority. They present arguments that can be accepted, rejected, or even critiqued based on the soundness and validity of the arguments presented. In this context, it is worth noting that philosophical thinking entails argument construction. By argument, we refer to the group of statements one of which, the conclusion or claim, is deemed to follow from other statements (premises or proofs). As one will get acquainted with the discussion in this course or as suggested in the discussion above, philosophical thinking requires that a thinker or philosopher presents her views which must be examined based on the soundness of these views. In the chapters that follow, we can view some of the philosophical claims of these philosophers and the premises or proofs that they offer for their claim. And when we agree or disagree to their views, often it is because we consider them to in error, because the claim does not follow from the premises or the statements are not true, and so on. In this article, we clarified philosophical thinking by examining the etymology of philosophy. As love of wisdom, philosophy pursues profound knowledge, as wisdom suggests. In this respect, philosophical thinking is directed towards finding the ultimate principles and causes of the object of thought. This is what Aristotle and other thinkers did in their philosophizing. Moreover, philosophical thinking shifted to determining knowledge based on the criteria set forth by thinking mind—and this was initiated by Descartes. Hume, however, includes in philosophical thinking the analysis of our experiences which serve as the source for the contents of the mind. This form of philosophical thinking is, however, given different direction when he espoused for a thinking that will be unfettered and has practical societal impact—one which he calls the public use of reason. And, Foucault similarly advocated for an independent thinking that is not claimed or ordered by previous knowledge. All these are but samples of philosophical thinking.
Hbrs 10 Must Reads On Diversity With Bonus Article Making Differences Matter A New Paradigm For Managing Diversity by David A Thomas and Robin J Ely Harvard Business Review Download