M E Warren Weberian Concept of Power - 112119
M E Warren Weberian Concept of Power - 112119
3
© 1992 SAGE (London, Newbury Park and New Delhi) 19
Max Weber defined power as ’the probability that one actor within a social
relationship will be in a position to carry out his own will despite resistance,
regardless of the basis on which this probability rests’ (Weber, 1978: 53). While
Weber’s concept of power is not universally accepted, two key elements are
replicated in virtually every definition of power as a potentially conflictual
relationship between dominant and subordinate individuals (e.g. Oppenheim,
1981: 29-31 ). The first element is an understanding of power as an expression of
the wills and capacities of individuals. The second is a distinction between
relations of power and other social relationships in terms of a conflict of interest
between individuals.
Most social scientists have found Weber’s definition congenial. On the one
hand, his definition refers power in institutions and structures to individuals and
the relations between them. That is, it seems consistent with methodological
individualism, and thus seems to accord with a mainstream consensus about
what counts as an explanation. On the other hand, his definition has a normative
bearing on liberal-democratic politics. Because it distinguishes power relations
from other kinds of social relations - consensual and voluntary ones, for example
-
it can help to identify social relations that, just because they are relations of
power, we may wish to structure by means of political rights and protections. In
contrast, definitions of power so broad as to include all social relations -
Nietzsche’s and Foucault’s cosmological definitions are examples - would seem
to devalue rights and protections because they fail to distinguish between power
and other kinds of social relations.
In this article I take issue with this conventional understanding of Weber’s
approach to power and offer an alternative account. The problem is not with the
supposed advantages of Weber’s definition. He did value explanatory con-
creteness (Hekman, 1983). And he quite explicitly fashioned his sociology to
[D]omination will thus mean the situation in which the manifested will
(command) of the ruler or rulers is meant to influence the conduct of one or
more others (the ruled) and actually does influence it in such a way that
their conduct to a socially relevant degree occurs as if the ruled had made
the content of the command the maxim of their conduct for its very own
sake. (Weber,1978: 946)
Notice the apparent contradiction: on the one hand, Weber refers to the
NIETZSCHE’S INFLUENCE
One way of getting Weber right on this issue is to interpret his conception of
power in light of his Nietzschean inheritance, for this is where we find the most
radical questioning of conceptions of agency. Weber is reported to have written
in a letter that ’one can measure the honesty of a contemporary scholar, and
above all a contemporary philosopher, in his posture toward Marx and
Nietzsche’ (Mitzman, 1970: 182). Marx’s influence has never been much of a
mystery: Weber was always in contact with contemporary socialists, and it is not
difficult to see his sociology as an alternative to Marx that also incorporates him.
It is different with Nietzsche. While most now agree that Nietzsche was an
important figure, there is little agreement as to what his importance was. Thus we
are less sure what he might have meant to Weber. To be sure, there are some clear
lines of influence. Most obviously, Weber’s concern with modern disen-
chantment and the increasing meaninglessness of rationalized culture and
institutions is Nietzschean to the core (Hennis, 1988: Ch. 4; Scaff, 1984: 196;
Schroeder, 1987).
But we have not yet appreciated the extent to which Weber was influenced by
Nietzsche’s rejection of modern understandings of agency. We find this
influence above all in the ways Weber poses his questions: his sociology takes no
particular kind of individuality or personality for granted, but instead asks how
different kinds of agents, personalities, configurations of desire and interpre-
tation come into being. He puts the question in part by asking how individuals’
experiences, social creations, goals and reflexive capacities are formed within
interpretative systems of value. As Hennis has put it, Weber is interested in the
’forms of moral constitution’ of the self (Hennis, 1987:73).’ This is a
Nietzschean problematic. Nietzsche’s critique of modern culture is a result of
pursuing the metaphysics of Christianity and rationalism into modern concep-
tions of subjectivity, so that his critique of modern values is also a critique of
modern conceptions of agency. ’Metaphysical’ conceptions of subjectivity
involve attributing a unity to the self in terms of its interests, goals, values,
meanings, or capacities. But although we may experience the self as a unity, such
unity is not, in Nietzsche’s view, guaranteed by transcendental certainties or by
substantive unity within the self. Rather, unity is given by a projected moral ideal
which is in a constant state of achievement, and the form of unity reflects the
conditions under which the moral ideal is incarnated. What distinguishes
modernity, Nietzsche held, is that the contingency of the self becomes apparent
as a matter of sociocultural fact. He called the experience of this awareness
’nihilism’, because with the disintegration of the moral identities it had taken for
granted, the self loses a meaningful orientation toward the world.
Under these circumstances, Nietzsche thought, we can no longer make do
with the modernist approach of using the self to measure and morally judge the
world. Nietzsche’s most important innovation lies at this juncture: he asks a new
kind of question, and from this question follows virtually the entirety of his
philosophy. His question is: How are selves - ’types’ as he calls them - forged
out of the practices, interpretations and conditions that make up a form of life?
Practices produce the self, in Nietzsche’s view, according to general existential
demands for meaning - demands, as it were, for agent-unity, a center out of
which the self might act with effect. We do not forge the self under conditions of
our own choosing, however. Indeed, existing social relations of power present
the self with dilemmas for its unity and direction, so that the kind of unity the self
achieves will retain an imprint, as it were, of the power relations under which it is
forged. The kind of self that results from historically contingent practices - a
Christian soul, an ascetic, a rational calculator, a romantic - will have much to do
with the conditions under which the practices are generated. If these conditions
include oppression, power relations can become an essential part of the narrative
through which the self locates its own agent-unity, in this way becoming
essential to self-identity. This is, in effect, the pattern of explanation we find in
Nietzsche’s analysis of the ’slave type’ he viewed as endemic to Christian culture:
he conceives a kind of self that finds power relations essential to its identity just
because it achieves identity through a scriptural narrative that developed in
response to slave conditions of life. Nietzsche, in other words, provides an
analysis of domination, one that Weber borrows, refines and expands in his
Sociology of Religion (Warren, 1988b: Ch. 1; Weber, 1946: Ch. IX). This
analysis, we shall see, provides a template for understanding Weber.
Nietzsche does not generalize his example into a concept of domination,
leaving us to extract it from a single sustained example: his analysis of priestly
power in his critique of Christianity in On the Genealogy of Morals and The
Antichrist. The example is interesting not because Nietzsche gives a full account
of the sociology of Christianity (Weber is much more sensitive to its historical
variations), but because it provides the model of analysis upon which Weber
relies, and which Weber refines and elaborates, notwithstanding his somewhat
disingenuous critique of Nietzsche.’ Nietzsche’s account is well known: he
portrays Christianity in terms of its interpretative constitution of the self, a
constitution that permits and justifies the domination of the Church, while
defining individuals in such a way that their self-identities can be maintained only
by accepting the power of the Church. He looks for the origins of ’the
Christian-moral hypothesis’ and other ascetic ideals in the existential interest
situation of those who suffer, especially at the hands of others (Warren,
1988b: Ch. 1). Suffering is not, in Nietzsche’s view, problematic in itself, but
rather when it is senseless, without meaning (Nietzsche, 1968a: 503-5). Meaning
is not, however, a problem of representing or discovering meanings that are
inherent in the world; it is not a problem of truth as traditionally understood.
Instead, Nietzsche understands meaning as an experience given by individuals’
abilities to interpret their situations in ways that allow them to form a ’will’ - an
orientation toward conditions of self-reproduction. Demands for meaning
become estranged from practices and are idealized as the problem of ’truth’,
however, when, for reasons of experience or cultural mapping, practices become
so disjoined that individuals can no longer plausibly interpret them as effects of
their ’will’. It is not that humans always connect meaning to will-formation.
Rather, suffering produces the problem of meaning because the ’will’ that one
would have formed through traditional orientations, habitually and without
thinking (’instinctively’, in Nietzsche’s terminology), is no longer possible. This
is why humans ’would rather will nothingness than not will’ (1968: 533).
Suffering at the hands of others produces a problem of meaning because it
violates an existential need for will-formation - a point that Nietzsche seems to
have borrowed loosely from Hegel, and bequeathed directly to Weber. The key
to both Nietzsche’s and Weber’s analyses is that suffering structures interest
situations subject to interpretation.3 Christianity addresses these interest situ-
ations by offering an image of the world that permits a unity of the will by
providing a goal - that is, a projected (and transcendentally protected) identity in
terms of which the unity of the self can be secured over and against worldly
suffering. The Christian narrative about sin, punishment, the need for obedience,
and behavioral conditions of salvation draws much of its strength from its
internal coherence. It makes contact with the world only with respect to a few
painful experiences, experiences that help to underwrite the Christian devalu-
ation of the world. Indeed, this is a condition of its success: the Christian
narrative serves those who subscribe to the story precisely because it inverts the
world. Oppressors will be punished rather than saved, the ’will’ that is lacking in
practice is restored to individuals as children of God, the community missing on
earth will exist in an afterlife, and the suffering that one experiences is nonetheless
a just consequence of human sin (Nietzsche, 1968a: 482-8).
natural causes of a deed are no longer &dquo;natural&dquo;, but thought of as caused by the
conceptual specters of superstition, by &dquo;God&dquo;, by &dquo;spirits&dquo;, by &dquo;souls&dquo;, as if they
were merely &dquo;moral&dquo; consequences, as reward, punishment, hint, means of
Nietzsche, the priestly rulers of the Church do not simply minister to the
sufferings of their followers. They exploit suffering in such a way that they gain
control over the capacities of sufferers to sustain their sense of subjectivity.
Nietzsche views the priest ’type’ as an ideologist who employs politically
produced sufferings to solidify his interpretative authority, while destroying the
if, Nietzsche argues, the world is will to power, does this not make any
as
particular analysis of power beside the point? The answer is no: the analyses
operate on different, although interrelated, levels in Nietzsche’s thought. I have
argued extensively elsewhere that in characterizing the world as will to power,
Nietzsche develops a general relational ontology of practices (Warren,
1988b: Ch. 4). The concept simultaneously denotes the motivation to form a
will, the interpretative structures within which wills are identified, and
experiential conditions and resistances. Wills, Nietzsche argues in an important
aphorism in Beyond Good and Evil, are ex post interpretative identities that
reflect a narrative continuity of practices (Nietzsche, 1968b: 215-17). One
interprets consistent effects of practices in terms of a unified origin, which
evolves into the interpretation ’I’. Domination, however, is based on a broken
link between practices and self-identity; identities that reflect domination are, in
Nietzsche’s terms, ’pathological’ developments of will to power.
We find, then, the distinctions necessary to a relational definition of power
within Nietzsche’s general ontology of power. He chooses to call all practices
’power’, but then distinguishes some of these as ’pathological’ - that is,
configurations of practice that displace self-identity into a realm of non-
contingent, transcendental identities. Nietzsche’s analysis thus fits the relational
definition of power. It does so, however, without producing the two paradoxes
of the standard elaboration. First, we can see that the fact that there is a conflict of
interest does not mitigate the organization-building qualities of power. The
instability of master-slave relations as compared to the stability of the Church
testifies to this. But we can also see why conceptually: hierarchical relations that
engage the wills of subordinates are less costly for the dominant. Obedience
secured voluntarily does not require police, guards, or overseers. It does require
guidance, discipline and codes of conduct. But these are internalized as part of the
same interpretative structure that provides the payoff in meaning and identity for
In both cases, individuals enter into power relations ’willingly’ and this is why
Weber describes these relations as domination rather than, say, oppression. The
difference between the two, however, turns on the extent to which an
individual’s subjectivity is defined by the relationship. In the ideal type of market
domination, individuals remain cognitively competent; they can distinguish their
interests from the interests of those they serve. In this sense, they remain, in
Weber’s terms, ’formally free’. In the second case, however, interests are defined
through the relationship itself, and individuals lose, as it were, the cognitive
competence to identify their distinctive interests. Their subjectivity is molded in
the image of the power relation.
These are, of course, limiting types, so that the ’borderline between these two
types of domination is fluid’ (Weber, 1978: 943). Indeed, they interact. Weber
uses the example of an economic monopoly: a monopoly over goods in the
market will allow a dominant party to dictate terms of trade to those who need
the goods and have no alternatives. Once such interactions are established,
however, domination in the market can evolve into domination by authority.
For example, a dominant firm will guarantee its monopoly by integrating
suppliers and retailers into the organization, so that they become part of a
hierarchical bureaucracy (Weber, 1978:943-6). The relation of domination is no
longer based solely on material interests, but also on recognized authority.
Indeed, Weber holds that domination will tend to evolve in this direction, so that
even the formal freedom of market domination will tend to produce bureaucratic
by a legal code that secures and enforces private property, binding contracts
and the like. Thus the legal structure both lays out a framework of formally free
exchanges between juridically free and equal subjects, and routinizes these
exchanges in ways that come to define the subject parties: retailers become
branch offices of monopolistic distributors; workers become integrated into
hierarchical chains of command. Free exchanges evolve into organizational
hierarchies which coordinate individuals through rules, disciplines, codes of
conduct and offices. They become, as it were, a way of life for the parties to the
exchange, engaging and defining identities in ways that go beyond the initial
motivations and add a layer of determination to the structural conditions of the
exchange. Routines allow the coercive backgrounds of these exchanges to recede
as individuals become integrated into the exchange in such ways that they no
longer experience overt conflicts of interest. Thus for Weber, unlike most
contemporary social scientists, coercion and legitimate authority are often two
sides of the same coin. Here we can see that the paradox involving willing
acceptance of coercive relations is not really a paradox at all, but instead describes
two complementary moments of power relations that have insinuated them-
selves into individual identities.
Weber does not conceive individuals subject to domination as passive victims.
The insinuation of power into self-identity can occur only because individuals
struggle to satisfy what Weber sometimes calls ’ideal’ interests through the
relations in which they find themselves entangled.’ This is not always clear in
Weber’s writings because he does not always use the term ’interest’ carefully.
Often, as in the above definitions of domination, the term simply refers to
material gain. But he also makes use of a broader conception of interests,
sometimes insisting that interests are never just ’material’, but also affective, ideal,
rational and so on (e.g. Weber,1978: 499). It is this broader conception of interest
that is implied in his definition of social action as behavior oriented toward other
persons to which the actor ascribes a meaning (Weber,1978: 4). Indeed, Weber’s
ontology of social action builds on an assumption that ’meaning’ is a general
human need, one closely linked to the reflexive constitution of the self. It is in this
sense that interests are not only material, but also what Weber sometimes calls
’ideal’: they are closely linked to a person’s reflexive constitution of the self from
within available material and cultural resources. This is why Weber argues that
domination by virtue of material interests is much more likely to be experienced
as oppressive than domination by authority, even though the latter usually
includes and goes beyond the former (Weber, 1978: 946). And it most certainly
explains why Weber claims that relations of domination founded on ’constel-
lations of [material] interests’ alone are unstable bases of organization: material
interests are never enough to constitute ’meaning’, that is, to orient/constitute the
self in such a way that institutional practices can and do continue.
This same idea appears in the seemingly odd and ironically Kantian wording of
Weber’s definition of domination as conduct that ’occurs as if the ruled had made
the content of the command the maxim of their conduct for its very own sake’
(Weber, 1978: 946). This means that subordinate parties obey because their ’ideal
interests’ are engaged and defined through the system of attributions that
legitimizes the power relation. From this perspective we can see that Weber’s
well-known types of legitimate domination - traditional, charismatic and
rational - are distinguished by the different ways in which the subordinate parties
define their identities.’ Each constitutes different kinds of selves according to the
actions that are required of them: as a member of a family or a tribe; as an
instrument of God, the nation, or a leader; as an official, a legal-juridical person
with rights, and so on. Insofar as subordinate parties orient their activities and
explain their lives through these identities, the power relation is legitimate and
justified. In each case, self-definition is integrated into the practices required by
the power relation, and the stability of the power relation depends on ’meaning-
fully’ constituted practices within the relationship such that agent-identities are
formed. This point is reinforced by our intuitive understanding that a power
relationship that comes into question - that is, identified as a power relation by
subordinates - is less powerful and stable than one accepted without question.
One of the many things that Weber seems to have learned from Nietzsche and
integrated into his conception of power, then, is that ’meaninglessness’ is an
untenable situation. Humans need to explain to themselves and others their
social fortunes and misfortunes, which also means that they need to ascribe
meaning to themselves as social subjects. This is true not just for those who are
dominated, but also those who dominate. With respect to a dominating group,
for example, Weber comments that
...
justification of its legitimacy is much more than a matter of theoretical
or philosophical speculation; it rather constitutes the basis of very real
Similarly in his sociology of religion Weber claims that with the rise of rational
religions, general ’religious needs’ (that is, needs for meaning) are transformed
into a ’need for an ethical interpretation of the &dquo;meaning&dquo; of the distribution of
fortunes among men’ (Weber, 1946: 270, 275). Weber’s formulations imply that
subordinates are never passively ’constituted’ as subjects by external relations.
They may accept a ruling ’myth’ that legitimizes domination, but they do so only
when they can define their own identities in and through it, and they often
transform these myths in the process, providing a key impetus for cultural
evolution.
In terms of Weber’s ontology of social action, such needs are not external to
social action, but part of what makes it an ’action’ rather than a mere behavior.
Every act has a more or less explicit set of reasons and justifications attached to it
that are so fundamental as to situate the individual qua subject/agent in relation to
existing material and cultural resources. Indeed, for Weber, it is not proper to
speak of social action at all prior to the emergence of capacities involving an
individual’s reflexive monitoring of conduct in social situations, as in the case of
purely traditional and affective behavior (Weber, 1978 : 25). As Charles Taylor
has argued, this process of monitoring one’s own motives and the ability to give a
meaningful account of one’s conduct is what defines agent capacities (Taylor,
1985: Chs 1-2). It is here that we find Weber’s counterfactual account of
interests: he conceptualizes the need for meaning/subjective identity in a way
that assumes the possibility of agency. The guiding normative proposition of his
studies is that there is a general interest in directing and affecting one’s life, an
interest that is both cultivated and undermined within rationalized cultures. This
interest is realized in a personality constituted by the ’consistency of its inner
relationship to certain ultimate values and meanings of life, which are turned into
purposes and thus into teleologically rational action’ (Weber, 1975:192; cf.
L6with, 1982:45-6; Portis, 1978; Schluchter, 1979: 73-4). A person has a ca-
pacity for agency when he or she can combine a consistent system of values
potential for, rational agency, and why Weber saw bureaucratic power relations
as the most urgent problem for western societies. Weber did not believe, of
This point is clear even in the most obvious kind of power, the threat to use
violence against a subordinate (Wrong, 1980: 26). The use of violence signifies
that the dominant party has become powerless because it has failed to engage the
subordinate’s will, and thus cannot make use of the capacities of the subordinate
as an agent. This is no doubt why Hannah Arendt, an advocate of the view of
CONCLUSION
We can see, then, why the standard appropriations of Weber’s relational defi-
This is why experiences of agency that depend on a power relation can actually
reinforce the relation against the interests of the subordinate party. Yet Weber’s
critical insight - one expressed by Gramsci, hinted at by Foucault and picked up
by Habermas - is that relations of domination can also develop capacities for
agency through (ideological) legitimations. These become promises which are
materialized in expectations, often to the point of rendering relations of
domination vulnerable. Neither Nietzsche nor Weber develops his conceptions
of power in this direction, but they do both provide us with some of the critical
resources for doing so.
Department of Government
Georgetown University, Washington DC
NOTES
1 Taylor (1990) argues in a similar vein that an intrinsic relationship exists between moral
identity and human agency.
2 Weber (1946: Ch. XI; 1978: 499) mistakenly reduces Nietzsche’s account of the origins
of salvation religion to his account of ’ressentiment’.
3 Compare Weber’s discussion of the causality of religious ideas: ’Not ideas, but material
and ideal interests, directly govern men’s conduct. Yet very frequently the "world
images" that have been created by "ideas" have, like switchmen, determined the tracks
along which action has been pushed by the dynamics of interest. "From what" and "for
what" one wished to be redeemed and, let us not forget, "could be" redeemed,
depended upon one’s image of the world’ (Weber, 1946: 280).
4 See note 3 above.
5 ’Psychologically, the command may have achieved its effect upon the ruled either
through empathy or through inspiration or through persuasion by rational argument,
or through some combination of these three principal types of influence of one person
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Foucault, M. (1983) ’The Subject and Power’, in H. Dreyfus and P. Rabinow (eds)
Michel Foucault:
Beyond Structuralism and ,Hermeneutics 2nd edn, pp. 208-26.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hekman, S. (1983) Weber: The Ideal Type, and Contemporary Social Theory. Notre
Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
Hennis, W. (1987) ’Personality and Life Orders: Max Weber’s Theme’, in S. Whimster
and S. Lash (eds) Max Weber and Modernity, pp. 52-74. London: Allen & Unwin.
Hennis, W. (1988) Max Weber: Essays in Reconstruction, trans. K. Tribe. London: Allen
& Unwin.
K. (1982) Max Weber and Karl Marx, trans. H. Fantel. London: Allen &
Löwith,
Unwin.
Lukes, S. (1974) Power: A Radical View
. London: Macmillan.
Mitzman, A. (1970) The Iron Cage. New York: Knopf.
, in The Portable Nietzsche, ed. and trans. W. Kauf-
Nietzsche, F. (1954) The Antichrist
mann. New York: Viking Press.
Nietzsche, F. (1967) The Will to Power, ed. W. Kaufmann, trans. W. Kaufmann and R.
J. Hollingdale. New York: Random House.
Nietzsche, F. (1968a) On the Genealogy of Morals, in The Basic Writings , of Nietzsche
ed. and trans. W. Kaufmann. New York: Random House.
Nietzsche, F. (1968b) Beyond Good and Evil , in The Basic Writings of Nietzsche, ed.
and trans. W. Kaufmann. New York: Random House.
Nietzsche, F. (1974) The Gay Science
, trans. W. Kaufmann. New York: Random
House.
Nietzsche, F. (1982) Daybreak, trans. R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press.
Oppenheim, F. (1981) Political Concepts. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Parsons, T. (1960) Structure and Stress in Modern Societies
. New York: Free Press.
Portis, E. B. (1978) ’Max Weber’s Theory of Personality’, Sociological Inquiry 48: 113-
20.
Scaff, L. (1984) ’Weber Before Weberian Sociology’, British Journal of Sociology
35: 190-215.
Schluchter, W. (1979) ’Value Neutrality and the Ethics of Responsibility’, in G. Roth
and W. Schluchter, Max Weber’s Vision . of History Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA:
University of California Press.
Schluchter, W. (1981) The Rise of Western Rationalism
. Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press.
Schroeder, R. (1987) ’Nietzsche and Weber: Two "Prophets" of the Modem World’, in
S. Lash and S. Whimster (eds) Max Weber, Rationality, and Modernity, pp. 207-21.
London: Allen & Unwin.
Taylor, C. (1985) Human Agency and Language: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1. Cam-
bridge : Cambridge University Press.
Taylor, C. (1990) Sources of the Self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Warren, M. (1988a) ’Max Weber’s Liberalism for a Nietzschean World’, American Pol-
itical Science Review 82: 31-50.
Warren, M. (1988b) Nietzsche and Political Thought. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Warren, M. (1988c) ’Marx and Methodological Individualism’, Philosophy of the Social
Sciences 18: 447-76.
Weber, M. (1946) From Max Weber, ed. and trans. H. Gerth and C. W. Mills. New
York: Oxford University Press.
, ed. and trans. E. Shils and
Weber, M. (1949) The Methodology of the Social Sciences
H. Finch. New York: Free Press.
Weber, M. (1975) Roscher and Knies: The Logical Problems of Historical Economics
,
trans. G. Oakes. New York: Free Press.
Weber, M. (1978) Economy and Society, ed. G. Roth and C. Wittich. Berkeley: University
of California Press.
Wrong, D. (1980) Power: Its Forms, Bases, and Uses. New York: Harper & Row.