0% found this document useful (0 votes)
10 views4 pages

QIC1

This document is an exercise sheet for a course on Quantum Information and Computation, covering various topics such as entanglement, the Born rule, no-signalling, Schmidt decomposition, no-cloning, no-deleting principles, and unambiguous state discrimination. It includes several problems that require demonstrating key concepts and theorems related to quantum states and operations. The exercises are designed to deepen understanding of quantum mechanics and its implications for information theory.

Uploaded by

derekdereklch
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
10 views4 pages

QIC1

This document is an exercise sheet for a course on Quantum Information and Computation, covering various topics such as entanglement, the Born rule, no-signalling, Schmidt decomposition, no-cloning, no-deleting principles, and unambiguous state discrimination. It includes several problems that require demonstrating key concepts and theorems related to quantum states and operations. The exercises are designed to deepen understanding of quantum mechanics and its implications for information theory.

Uploaded by

derekdereklch
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 4

QUANTUM INFORMATION AND COMPUTATION

EXERCISE SHEET 1
Nilanjana Datta n.datta@damtp.cam.ac.uk (Lent 2023-2024)

(1) (Basic entanglement for two qubits)


(a) Show that the state |Ak ⟩ = 12 (|00⟩ + |01⟩ + |10⟩ + (−1)k |11⟩) is entangled if k = 1 and
unentangled if k = 0. Express the latter case explicitly as a product state.

(b) Can |Ak ⟩ for k = 0 or 1 be prepared from |0⟩ |0⟩ by applying only 1-qubit gates to the
qubits? Give a reason for your answer.

(c) Generalising (a), show that |ψ⟩ = α |00⟩ + β |01⟩ + γ |10⟩ + δ |11⟩ is entangled iff αδ − βγ ̸= 0.

(2) (Born rule, Pauli operations)


Let |ψ⟩ = a |0⟩ + b |1⟩ be any 1-qubit quantum state. Suppose we receive one of the four states
|ψ⟩, X |ψ⟩, Y |ψ⟩, and Z |ψ⟩, with equal prior probabilities of 1/4. (We could equivalently use
instead the four Pauli operations I, σx , σy and σz , and the action on |ψ⟩ is called Pauli-twirling.)

Show that any outcome of any complete projective measurement on the Pauli-twirled version
of |ψ⟩ has probability half. (Thus the received state contains no information at all about the
identity of |ψ⟩.)

(3) (Born rule, no-signalling, but having nonlocality)


Consider the 2-qubit state |ψ⟩ = √12 (|00⟩ + |11⟩). Suppose that the two qubits are separated
widely in space and held by Alice (A) and Bob (B) respectively, who can then apply only local
quantum operations i.e. unitary gates and measurements only to the qubit they hold. Introduce
the 1-qubit gate (“rotation by θ”)
 
cos θ − sin θ
U (θ) = .
sin θ cos θ

(a) Suppose A applies U (α) and B applies U (β). Show that the resulting state is

|ψαβ ⟩ = √1 (cos(α − β) |00⟩ − sin(α − β) |01⟩ + sin(α − β) |10⟩ + cos(α − β) |11⟩) .


2

Deduce that for any choice of α and β, if we measure either one of the qubits of |ψαβ ⟩ in the
computational basis we will get output 0 or 1 with equal probabilities of half. Show that this
remains true even if the other party has (unbeknown to us) already made the measurement
and obtained his/her suitably random outcome and post-measurement state i.e. choice of local
angle on one side cannot affect the measurement statistics obtained locally on the other side.
(This is another example of the no-signalling principle, discussed in lectures.)

(b) Suppose A and B now both measure (in the computational basis) their held qubit of |ψαβ ⟩
(in either order or simultaneously – the statistics are the same). Show that for the two bit
outcome obtained from the two local measurements, prob(outcomes differ) = sin2 (α − β).

(c) (Optional, but interesting! Good for discussion if time permits)


We now consider only three angle settings θ = − π6 , 0, π6 . Let MA (α) denote the following oper-
ation for Alice: apply U (α) to her qubit and measure it in the computational basis. Similarly
MB (β) for Bob. Consider now the following experiment denoted E(α, β): A and B have many
|ψ⟩ states and perform a long sequence of MA (α) and MB (β) with each choosing one of the
allowed angles (which is kept the same for the whole sequence). We imagine that for each |ψ⟩
the local operations are done essentially simultaneously (or at least at a spacelike interval). For
long sequences, probabilities will be reflected in frequencies of occurrence of 0’s and 1’s. Show

1
that the following statistics will be seen:
(i) E(0, 0): prob(differ) = 0 A and B’s sequences will be the same sequence.
(ii) E(0, − π6 ): prob(differ) = 1/4 The sequences will differ in about 1 in 4 places.
(iii) E( π6 , 0): prob(differ) = 1/4 The sequences will differ in about 1 in 4 places.
(iv) E( π6 , − π6 ): prob(differ) = 3/4 The sequences will differ in about 3 in 4 places!
Recall that the sequence seen locally by A or B will, in every case, be uniformly random, in
contrast to the angle-dependent correlations above.

Although we cannot apply two different M (θ) operations on any single system (for two different
angles) on one side, we can still consider counterfactually the sequences of outcomes that would
have been obtained if A or B had performed each of the three possible actions on their side for
any choice on the other side.

By considering these sequences and the correlations between them implied by (i) to (iv) above,
argue that it is impossible for the local outcomes at A (resp. B) to be independent of the choice
of angle chosen and used remotely at B (resp. A) i.e. that the local outcomes at A (resp. B)
must be “instantaneously influenced” by the choice of angle at B (resp. A).
[ Suggestion: Get Alice and Bob to do E( π6 , − π6 ), and ask each of them (separately) to think
about what would have happened if the other party had used a different angle.]

Stated more colourfully, we see that the correlations in the quantum measurement outcomes
can only occur if there is some “spooky action at a distance” (Einstein’s phrase) implied by
the quantum rules for local operations on composite systems. Note also that by (a), although
the “instantaneous influence” must exist, it cannot be used to instantaneously send a signal
from A to B (or vice versa) by suitable choice of local angle, since the effect is manifest only in
correlations (which require the local outcomes from both sides to be compared, to be noticed)
and not in any local measurement statistics separately.

(4) (Schmidt form; making 2-qubit states)


The Schmidt decomposition theorem for bipartite quantum states is the following:
Theorem: Let |ψ⟩AB be any quantum state of a composite system comprising an m dimensional
system A and n dimensional system B. Let d = min{m, n}.
Then there are orthonormal bases {|α1 ⟩ , . . . , |αm ⟩} of A and {|β1 ⟩ , . . . , |βn ⟩} of B (called
Schmidt bases for |ψ⟩) and non-negative real numbers λ1 , . . . , λd (called the Schmidt coeffi-
cients of |ψ⟩), such that
X d
|ψ⟩ = λi |αi ⟩ |βi ⟩
i=1
i.e. when expressed in the Schmidt bases, |ψ⟩ has no cross terms |αi ⟩ |βj ⟩ for i ̸= j.
The number of non-zero Schmidt coefficients is called the Schmidt rank of |ψ⟩. □

We will consider the Schmidt decomposition of states of two qubits (i.e. m = n = 2).

(a) By inspection (or otherwise) find Schmidt bases, coefficients and ranks for the product state
|a⟩ |b⟩ and for |A1 ⟩ = 12 (|00⟩ + |01⟩ + |10⟩ − |11⟩).
Show that √12 (|00⟩ + |11⟩) = √12 (|++⟩ + |−−⟩) and deduce that Schmidt bases are not uniquely
determined if two Schmidt coefficients are equal.

(b) Recall the statement of the singular value decomposition theorem for matrices (or google
P don’t know it). Here we’ll use it for 2 × 2 matrices. Writing a general 2-qubit state as
it if you
|ψ⟩ = ij aij |ij⟩ use the singular value decomposition theorem to prove Schmidt decomposition
theorem for pairs of qubits.
[ Note that the Schmidt form for higher dimensions follows similarly from the singular value
decomposition theorem for larger matrices.]

2
(c) Let {|α0 ⟩ = a |0⟩ + b |1⟩ , |α1 ⟩ = c |0⟩ + d |1⟩} be any orthonormal basis for a qubit. Show
that there is a 1-qubit unitary gate U with U |0⟩ = |α0 ⟩ and U |1⟩ = |α1 ⟩.
Hence or otherwise, show that any 2-qubit state can be manufactured from |0⟩ |0⟩ by application
of a sequence of unitary gates comprising only 1-qubit gates and at most just a single application
of the 2-qubit CX gate. For which states is the CX gate not required?

(d) (optional, if time permits.) The Schmidt form does not in fact generalise to tri-partite
systems. To see this, show that there are states |ψ⟩ABC of three qubits that cannot be expressed
as
X2
|ψ⟩ = λi |αi ⟩ |βi ⟩ |γi ⟩
i=1

(i.e. with no cross terms in the bases) for any triple of bases {|αi ⟩}, {|βi ⟩}, {|γi ⟩}. You may
assume that Schmidt bases are unique (up to overall phases and ordering of vectors) if the
Schmidt coefficients are different. It may be helpful to begin with the (valid) Schmidt form of
|ψ⟩ABC for the bi-partition of A vs. BC.

(5) (No-cloning)
(a) Let |ξi ⟩ and |ηi ⟩ for i = 0, 1 be two pairs of states. Show that if ⟨ξ0 |ξ1 ⟩ = ⟨η0 |η1 ⟩ then there
is a unitary U with U |ξi ⟩ = |ηi ⟩ for i = 0, 1. (Note: this is a generalisation of the first part of
question 4(c)).

(b) (a stronger no-cloning theorem) Consider the problem of cloning for two distinct non-
orthogonal states |αi ⟩ with i = 0, 1. We know that cloning is impossible but suppose that in
addition to the instance of |αi ⟩ we are also given some extra (generally quantum) information
about it, in the form of a state |βi ⟩ (generally depending on i).

Write down the general form of a unitary process that corresponds to the cloning of |αi ⟩ with
the assistance of |βi ⟩. By mimicking the proof of the no-cloning theorem in lectures, show that
if we are given |αi ⟩ |βi ⟩ then it is still impossible by any unitary process to obtain a second copy
of |αi ⟩, unless |αi ⟩ can already be created from |βi ⟩ alone i.e. the extra assistance state must
already contain the full information of |αi ⟩ within itself.

(6) (No-deleting principle) (a kind of “opposite process” to cloning)


A deleting operation for the states |αi ⟩ (as in question (5)(b)) is any process acting on two
copies |αi ⟩ |αi ⟩ with an ancilla, effecting the following:

|αi ⟩ |αi ⟩ |M ⟩ → |αi ⟩ |0⟩ |Mi ⟩

i.e. given two copies we ‘delete’ one of them. Here |0⟩ is any fixed state (independent of i) and
|Mi ⟩ is a state that can depend on i.

(a) Show that if such a deleting operation is unitary then |αi ⟩ can always be reconstituted from
|Mi ⟩ alone i.e there is a unitary operation U with U |0⟩ |Mi ⟩ = |αi ⟩ |N ⟩ where |N ⟩ is independent
of i. In this sense, quantum information cannot be deleted by a unitary process, even if we are
given a second copy to help delete it; it can only be moved out to ‘another place’ (“the rubbish
bin”) from where it can always be perfectly retrieved.

(b) Show that quantum information can be deleted if we allow measurements in the process.

(c) Can classical information be deleted by purely reversible Boolean operations (given, as
above, a second copy initially to help)?

3
(7) (Unambiguous state discrimination)
Consider the states
|ψ0 ⟩ = cos θ |0⟩ + sin θ |1⟩
|ψ1 ⟩ = cos θ |0⟩ − sin θ |1⟩
with 0 ≤ θ ≤ π/4.

(a) Consider the 2-qubit linear operation Uα defined by

Uα |00⟩ = cos α |00⟩ + sin α |11⟩


Uα |11⟩ = sin α |00⟩ − cos α |11⟩
Uα |01⟩ = |01⟩ Uα |10⟩ = |10⟩ .

Show that Uα is unitary. Let |ξi ⟩ = Uα |0⟩ |ψi ⟩. Find α such that |ξ0 ⟩ and |ξ1 ⟩ have orthogonal
projections into the 2-dimensional subspace spanned by |00⟩ and |01⟩.

(b) Using the result of (a), construct a scheme for the unambiguous discrimination of the states
|ψi ⟩ i.e. a quantum process with three outputs called 0, 1 and ‘fail’, such that if 0 (resp. 1) is
obtained then the state was certainly |ψ0 ⟩ (resp. |ψ1 ⟩), and if ‘fail’ occurs then all information
about the state has been lost (and we cannot do anything further to discriminate them). Show
that the probability of failure is |⟨ψ0 |ψ1 ⟩|.

(c) What should we do if π/4 ≤ θ ≤ π/2? Can we still unambiguously discriminate the states?

(8) (More on unambiguous discrimination)


Let {|α1 ⟩ , . . . , |αn ⟩} be a set of n quantum states. They can be unambiguously discriminated
if there is a quantum process with n + 1 outcomes labelled 1, . . . , n and ‘fail’ such that if the
outcome k occurs then the input state was certainly |αk ⟩, and if outcome ‘fail’ occurs then the
process was inconclusive. Also for every k, on input |αk ⟩, outcome k must have a non-zero
probability of occurring.

You may assume that any prospective discrimination process is a unitary process (with inclu-
sions of ancillas) having just a final measurement at the end (in fact without loss of generality
– cf Remark in lecture notes after the statement of the no-cloning theorem).

(a) Show that if the states can be unambiguously discriminated then they must form a linearly
independent set.

(b) (more difficult) Show that if the states are linearly independent then they can be unam-
biguously discriminated. (It may help to begin by adjoining an n-dimensional ancilla.)

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy