Oxford University Press American Historical Association
Oxford University Press American Historical Association
Century England
Author(s): Joyce Appleby
Source: The American Historical Review, Vol. 81, No. 3 (Jun., 1976), pp. 499-515
Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the American Historical Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1852421 .
Accessed: 05/01/2014 11:37
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Oxford University Press and American Historical Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The American Historical Review.
http://www.jstor.org
JOYCE APPLEBY
on domesticconsumption.Accordingto traditionalwriters,thevillainofthe
piece was the East India Company. Not only did the company enjoy a
monopolyofthetradeto India, butthenatureofitstrade-exportingbullion
in returnforimportscompetitive withEnglishgoods-ran athwartthe most
cherishedprinciplesofthebalance-of-trade concept.Fromthepointofviewof
thosein the Englishwoolenand silkindustriesthecompany'sgreatestcrime
was introducingthe English public to the light,colorful,cheap fabricsof
India. By I690, the tasteforchintz,calico, and muslinhad reachedepidemic
proportions. What had begunas an inconspicuoususe ofcottonforsuitlining
had givenway to a gaudydisplayofprinteddraperies,bedspreads,tapestries,
shirts,and dresses."6With marketingexpertiseequal to Macy's, in the
twentieth century,themanagersoftheEast India Companyhad sentEnglish
fabricdesignersto India to directthe Indian craftsmenin reproducingpat-
ternsespeciallyadmiredat home.The impactupon employment in England
was strong.The popularityand competitiveadvantagesofimportedcottons
led to a glut in the home marketforwoolens and silks. Contemporaries
complainedthat thousandsof workersin the two domesticindustrieswere
thrownonto the parish forsupport.The effectedproducerswanted a flat
prohibitionon domesticimportsof Indian cottons.Their advice to the East
India Companywas to sell theircalicoes abroad wherecheap textileswould
underminethe nativeindustriesof Great Britain'straderivals.17
Althoughit is difficultto learn fromcontemporary pamphletswhetherthe
poor were importantforworkingup manufactures or manufacturing impor-
tantforemployingthepoor,increasingly afteri66otheemphasisfellupon the
importanceof expanding opportunitiesfor work. Bans on the export of
Englishraw materialsand proposalsforreplacingforeignimportswithdo-
mesticsubstituteswere advanced on the groundthat theywould increase
employment.From this point of view, items requiringmore labor were
sociallymoreusefulthanthoserequiringless. Even labor-savingdeviceswere
suspect. The woolen and silk manufacturers drew upon this rationale in
fightingthe East India Company.They stressedthe unfairnessofsearching
out places whichcould undersellEnglishcommoditiesand questionedwhy
manufacturing oughtnotbe promoted"in England [rather]thanin India."'8
Charles Davenant was obviouslythinkingwithinthe traditionaltheoretical
frameworkwhen he asserted that cheap importedtextiles"freed" more
English woolens forforeignexport,but other writersrecognizedthat the
clothierscould onlybe convincingly answeredby movingoutsidethebalance-
of-tradelogicaltogether.'9
16 p. J. Thomas, Mercantilism and theEast India Trade(London, 1963),30, 51; Suviranta,Theory ofthe
Balanceof Trade,7. Both Thomas and Suvirantapointed out the stimulusof the East India trade to
economicreasoningin the seventeenthcentury.
17 The (;reat Necessity
and Advantage ofPreserving ourOwn Manufacturies (London, 1697),6-1o; [Thomas
Smith],England'sDangerbyIndianManufactures (n.p., [16981),2-7; lPollexfenj,EnglandandEast India,18-20;
ReasonsHumbly OfferedforthePassingofa Bill (London, 1697),7-23; An Answer totheMostMaterialObjections
(np., [16991),i.
'8 Ibid.,2.
'9 Thomas, Mercantilism andtheEast India Trade,8i.
In Considerations
on theEast-India Trade, Henry Martyn made a full frontal
attackon the theoryofthe social utilityofhighlabor costsby examiningthe
differentials
in domesticconsumption.ConcedingthatIndian imports"abate
the price of English Manufactures,"he maintainedthat this abatement
stimulatedother segmentsof the economy. Laborers who bought Indian
cottonswould have moremoneyavailable fromtheirwages to spendon those
itemsproducedmoreefficiently by the English.Even ifEnglishlaborerswere
thrownout ofwork,the greatercompetitionforjobs would lowerwages and
push down the cost ofotherEnglishproducts.Drivinghome his cost-advan-
tage theory,Martyn stressedthat any law which forcedthe English to
consumeonlyEnglishgoodsforcedthemto pay morefortheirneedsthanwas
necessary.He likenedthis to denyingthe benefitsof new inventionsor the
obvioussavingsfromthedivisionoflaboror rejectingwheatsentas a giftfrom
God.20Martynexploredthe relationbetweenearningand purchasingpower
with unprecedentedanalytical skill. Many of his observationshad been
anticipatedby earliercommentators.For example,Dalby Thomas had ex-
tolledthe labor-savingingenuitywhichthedesireto acquire called forth, and
John Houghton had disputed Samuel Fortrey'sstricturesagainst French
importsby pointingout that even foreignluxuryitems satisfiedgenuine
consumerdemandsand made peopleworkharder.21 These writerslegitimized
domesticcompetitionbecause theyperceivedthat England was not a giant
workhousebut a giantmarketwhoseindividualmembershad differing needs.
In focusingattentionon thesenew marketrelationships, the pamphletson
Indian importsrevealedthose areas of conflictbetweenmanufacturers and
merchantswhichthe predominating concernwithforeigntrade had so long
obscured. Driven no doubt by self-interest,the defendersof the East India
Company put fortha justificationfor"a good buy" which amountedto a
defenseof domesticconsumption.Here the issue became criticalto thewhole
structureof ideas associated withthe balance-of-trade theory,because the
idea ofthe Englisheconomyas a collectiveundertaking was beingchallenged.
This lineofattackcutdeeperthanthesuperficial The actual
clash ofinterests.
social atomizationwhichcame withthe seventeenth-century transitionto a
marketeconomyhad been amelioratedby an imaginativemodelofeconomic
unityorganized around national productionand fortified by religionand
patriotism.Psychologicalatomizationcould be forestalledas long as this
image retained its credibility.When individualsbegan to thinkof their
separate needs and demands as acceptable social considerations, the coher-
ence of the earlier model would disappear. The benefitsof the English
consumers'havingaccess to cheap East Indian importsdepended upon the
rejectionof the view that societywas an interlocking set of producersand
distributorsand the acceptanceofthe alternativeviewthattheeconomywas
Tractson Commerce,
6o6,578-86.
21
IThomasi, An Historical
Account,
361-62; John Houghton],England'sGreatHappiness (London, 1677),
18-20.
" Lawrence Stone, "Social Mobility in England, 1500-1700," no. 33 (I966), 52-55.
Past and Present,
money."54Francis Gardner put the low wage argument in a nut shell: "The
Poor, if Two Dayes work will maintain them, will not work three: and our
Manufactures are never so well wrought as, in a time of dull Trade, when we
pay less for Workmanship, and yet the Poor live as well then as in time of
greatest Plenty, if they have but a full stroke of Work."55
The efficacyof the market as an implement of control in a technically free
economy depended, however, upon whether it was a buyer's or a seller's
market. As John Locke commented, mechanics and apprentices lived such a
"hand-to-mouth" existence that they were forced to accept food for wages
rather than starve.56Another writer feared their excessive freedom and de-
scribed the poor withina fifty-mile radius of London as idle and surly and will-
ing to work only "if two days pay will keep them a week." Others suggested
an excise tax on food and drink to make the poor work a full week.57Against
this background the danger of a consumption formula foreconomic growth
can be assessed better: it threatened the most effectiveformof class discipline
in a liberal society. The capitalistic organization of the economy could force
men and women on to the labor market since that was the only place where
they could earn the means of subsistence, but the amount of labor they were
forced to sell depended upon the wage rate.
The employers' need to control the labor forcereveals the incompatibilities
between liberalism and capitalism. Liberalism asserted the right of each
person to the enjoyment of himselfand the fruitsofhis labor. It did not matter
whether laborers were predisposed toward leisure or consuming. But the
economic growth which the capitalistic system promoted, required a disci-
plined and expandable work force. Leisure preferencescould be as inhibiting
to growthas archaic Poor Laws. Employers did not seek conditions ofpolitcal
and moral freedom for the working class. In fact, as they well perceived,
transportingworkersto centers of employmentwas much more efficientthan
relyingupon necessitous, but free,workersto go where thejobs were.58While
much has been made of the congruence between freedomand capitalism, it
was the freedomof propertyowners fromsocial obligations which was critical
to capitalistic growth in the seventeethcentury. Ideas which promoted free
choice among the poor were inherentlydangerous to the entrepreneurs.The
writers who extolled the advantages of domestic spending in the fightover
Indian imports implied that human behavior could be shaped by the impulse
to consume, but such optimistic reliance upon envyand emulation must have
appeared inadequate to the task of controllinglaborers described as idle and
surly and willing to work only iftwo days pay would keep them a week. Since
54 [Petty],A Treatiseof Taxes,43. See also Thomas Manley, Usuryat Six PerCent.Examined, andFound
Unjustly Charged(London, 1669),24-25.
56 [Gardner],SomeReflectionsona Pamphlet, 16.
58 JohnLocke], SomeConsiderations oftheLowering
oftheConsequences ofInterest(London, 1692),34.
57 The TradeofEngland Revived;andtheAbusesThereof (n.p., 1681),8. See also E. P. Thompson,
Rectified
"Time, Work-Discipline, and IndustrialCapitalism,"PastandPresent,no. 38 (1967),56-97; KeithThomas,
"Work and Leisure in Pre-IndustrialSociety,"ibid.,no. 24 (1964), 61-62.
"8Sir Josiah Child, A New Discourse of Trade(London, 1693),67; [Petty],A Treatiseof Taxes,48-49;
Robinson,EnglandsSafety, 44-45.
the old social justification for ordering all economic relations had been de-
stroyed in the fight to make property private and property-owners free,
economic theory had to supply the reasons for statutoryregulations.59This
was the role which the balance-of-trade dogmas played in the eighteenth
century.
The critical differencebetween Adam Smith's theory of economic growth,
which was anticipated in the closing years of the seventeenth century, and
that of the mercantilists was the constructive value given to consumption.
This constructive value in turn rested upon the assumption that all men
wished to maximize their market power because that and that alone offered
an avenue of self-improvement.Although Smith's sympathies lay strongly
with the savers and investors,the propensityto consume provides the linchpin
for his whole system.60Externally, it creates the effectivedemand which calls
forthproduction systems large enough forspecialization and division of labor.
Internally,the drive to truck and barter-to buy and sell-directs individual
energies toward the market and away from other human satisfactions. So
axiomatic is it to Smith that self-improvementwill be fulfilledthrough eco-
nomic activitythat he does not even entertain ideas about alternate means to
improve oneself, much less alternate goals. One improves through market
power, but market power rests upon producing power. The more one pro-
duces, the more one can satisfy wants. Since self-improvement,as Smith
defined it, has no natural limit, there is no limit to man's endeavors. In
Smith's model, people as producers and people as consumers act like an
alternating electrical current, throwing a steady flow of impulses into the
economy. The flow can be taken for granted because it came from human
qualities assumed to be universal.
The acceptance of the idea of universal economic rationality was the key
step in the triumph of modern liberalism, because the natural economic laws
depended upon natural modes of behavior. Beforethe laws could be accepted,
the description of human nature supporting them had to be credible. Histori-
cally, however, before economic rationality became a learned pattern of
response, explicit control was necessary to secure working-class discipline.
The laboring poor had to be managed. The spendthriftwith a feast or famine
mentalityhad to be transformedinto the shrewd saver, and the saver had to
become an orderly,but compulsive, investorand consumer. Market thinking
could be relied upon only after the variety of forces influencing personal
preferences in the use of time and wealth had been ruthlessly narrowed to
one-the likelihood of gain. This radical reductionism was the essence of
59 For Edward Coke's role in endowingeconomic freedomwith a constitutionalsanction see David
Little,Religion, Order,and Law (New York, i969), 203-17, 243-46; Barbara Malament, "The 'Economic
Liberalism' of Sir Edward Coke," Yale Law Review,76 (1967), 1321-58; Donald 0. Wagner, "Coke and the
Rise of Economic Liberalism," EconomicHistoryReview,6 (1935), 30-44.
oftheproduceroughtto
60 "Consumptionis the sole end and purposeof all production;and the interest
be attendedto, only so faras it may be necessaryforpromotingthat of the consumer.The maximis so
perfectly thatit would be absurdto attemptto proveit." Adam Smith,AnInquiry
self-evident, intotheNature
and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (New York, 1937) [originally published in 17761, 625. For Smith's
ambivalenceon the subjectof consumption,comparethisquotationwiththoseon ibid., 321-25.
Smith's economic rationality. The economically rational person was the one
who subverted all other drives to the economic one of gaining more power in
the market.
During the first part of the seventeenth century when invested capital
moved England toward a marketeconomy, only the vanguard ofentrepreneurs
operated as economic rationalists. To them, the rest ofthe society represented
a problem demanding external control and direction. To meet this challenge,
moreover,they relied upon a model of economic growth which obscured the
possibilitythat the extension ofeconomic rationalism to the workingclass was
either desirable or possible. Rather the economic irrationalityof the poor was
assumed; the solution was to train them up to habits of work. When the
writersin the closing decades of the seventeenthcenturyproposed unleashing
the acquisitive instinctsof all classes, theywere proposing a route to economic
growth fraughtwith perils. The idea of self-improvementthrough spending
implied genuine social mobility. The assertion that "the meaner sort" could
and should emulate their betters suggested that class distinctionswere based
on little more than purchasing power. The moral implications of growth
through popular spending were even more suspect. Unlike the work ethic
which called upon powerful longings forself-disciplineand purposeful activ-
ity, the ethic of consumption rested upon a moral base so shallow as to
threaten the whole complex of conventional religious precepts. Calvinism had
joined an ancient Christian ascetic impulse to a modern reorganization of
work; the psychology of consumption offerednothingmore than a calculating
hedonism.
The moral anemia of appeals to consume was inextricably tied up with
questions of control. Liberalism had posited man's freedom and responsi-
bility. Capitalism required unrelenting personal effortin the market place.
The two could meet only ifthe poor, like the rich, were convertedto possessive
individualism and economic rationality.Until this transitionhad been made,
class discipline needed the support of economic theories bolstered by religion
and patriotism. When capitalism and freechoice werejoined by Adam Smith,
they were compatible because Smith could theorize froma human model in
which the drive for economic self-improvementpredominated. This concep-
tion of man was the antithesis of freedom, for it presumed a compulsive
market response. In recommending the democratization of consumption in
the I69os, the proponents of a spending model of economic growth were
revealing for the first time the tensions that lay beneath the values and
sensibilities associated with the producing and consuming sides of capitalism.
Only when economic rationalism had become internalized by the working,as
well as the investing,class could liberal economics support the onus of its
amorality. The ideology of mercantilsim in the meantime blunted the forceof
new ideas.