Figure 1.8 Does Triangle FEA Have Two Right Angles?: 1.3 Axioms For Euclidean Geometry 21
Figure 1.8 Does Triangle FEA Have Two Right Angles?: 1.3 Axioms For Euclidean Geometry 21
Our axiom set is a descendant of the five axioms provided by Euclid, but there
are some differences. There are two main reasons why we do not use Euclid’s axioms
as he originally gave them:
1. Euclid phrases his axioms in a way that is hard for the modern reader to
appreciate.
2. It has been necessary to add axioms to Euclid’s set in order to be able to give
rigorous proofs of many Euclidean theorems.
A number of individuals, and at least one committee, have taken their turn at
improving Euclid’s axiom set, notably David Hilbert in 1899, G. D. Birkhoff in 1932,
and the School Mathematics Study Group (SMSG) working during the 1960s. Even
though these axiom sets differ from one another and from Euclid’s, they all lead to
the well-known theorems in Euclid’s Elements. Consequently, we say that they are all
axiom sets for Euclidean geometry. The axioms we list in this section are a minor
rewording of the SMSG axiom set.
As we embark on our study of axiomatic Euclidean geometry, you will be asked
to consider proofs of some statements that seem obvious and many that you have
learned before. To enter into the spirit of our study, you must put aside what you have
learned before or find obvious. In earlier sections we have relied on some geometry
you have studied before. But in this section, our proofs are constructed only from the
22 CHAPTER 1 THE AXIOMATIC METHOD IN GEOMETRY
axioms we are about to list and any theorems we have previously proved from those
axioms. Keep in mind that our objective in our axiomatic discussion of Euclidean
geometry is not to learn the most facts of geometry, but to learn about the logical
structure of geometry and to practice the art of proof.
* T H E O R E M 1.1
Two lines intersect in at most one point.
PROOF
Suppose lines L and M contain the two points A and B. Then A and B would have
two lines containing them, violating Axiom 1. This contradiction shows that our
supposition that L and M contain two points in common must be false.
Our next axiom is just a mathematical way of saying what everyone who has
ever used a ruler will find familiar: A line “comes with” a set of numerical markings
that we can use for calculations and proofs.
This axiom allows us to use the properties of the real numbers to find out things
about lines. For example, there are infinitely many real numbers, so we must have
infinitely many corresponding points on a line. The ruler axiom also allows us to
define the key geometric idea of betweenness.
A line will have many possible ruler functions: For example, replacing fA by
fA + 7 for every A on a line gives another ruler function. But the theorems we
are going to prove come out the same even if we use a new set of ruler functions
conforming to Axiom 2.
DEFINITIONS
Let A, B, and C be three points on a line and f be the ruler function for that line.
1. We say B is between A and C if either fA < fB < fC or fC < fB < fA.
We write A-B-C to indicate that B is between A and C C-B-A has the same
meaning as A-B-C.
2. The segment from A to B, denoted AB, is defined to be the set consisting of
A, B, and all points X where A-X-B.
3. If AB = CD, then the segments AB and CD are called congruent.
* T H E O R E M 1.2
1. AB = BA.
2. If A-B-C, then AB + BC = AC.
3. If A B C are three different points on a line, then exactly one of them is
between the other two.
PROOF
1. AB = fB − fA = − fA − fB = fA − fB = BA.
2. There are two cases. First, suppose fA < fB < fC. Then
We leave the second case, where fC < fB < fA, as an exercise.
1.3 AXIOMS FOR EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY 25
The following theorem was assumed as an axiom by Euclid. If Euclid had included
our ruler axiom among his axioms, then, of course, he would not have needed to
assume what we are about to prove.
* T H E O R E M 1.3: Extendibility
If A and B are any two points, then the segment AB can be extended by any positive
distance on either side of segment AB (Figure 1.10).
PROOF
Let e > 0 be the amount of extension wanted, and let’s say we want to extend past
B to a point C so that B is between A and C and BC = e. Let a and b be the real
←−→
numbers fA and fB under the ruler function for the line AB.
Case 1
a < b (Figure 1.10). Then define c = b + e. By part 3 of the ruler axiom, there is a
point C that corresponds to the number c. C is the point we want since:
Case 2
a > b. We leave this as an exercise.
PROOF
We leave this as an exercise.
The midpoint theorem suggests that we think of points as infinitely small. If they
had any positive size, a line segment would be a bit like a necklace (Figure 1.11). If
the number of points on a segment were even, there would not be one exactly in the
middle as required by Theorem 1.4.
DEFINITION
−
→
If A and B are distinct points, the ray from A through B, denoted AB, is the set of all points
←−→
C on line AB such that A is not between B and C. We call A the endpoint of the ray.
The negative phrasing of this definition is sometimes awkward, so the following
theorem is sometimes handy. Its proof is based on one of our previous results. Can
you find the proof?
* T H E O R E M 1.5
−
→
AB consists of segment AB together with all points X where A-B-X.
DEFINITION
→−
− →
Let A B, and C be any three distinct points. AB AC is called the angle BAC and
denoted ∠BAC (Figure 1.9). We may also denote this angle ∠CAB. A is called the
Figure 1.11 A segment AB of six “fat” points would not have a midpoint.
1.3 AXIOMS FOR EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY 27
vertex of the angle. If A B, and C lie on a line (are collinear), with A between B and
←−→
C, we call ∠CAB a straight angle. It is no different from the line BC.
When we think of an angle that is not a straight angle and not 0 , we often think
of it as the space between the rays that border it. Our definition of angle does not try
to capture that idea. We need a separate definition of the interior of an angle, and we
base it on the next axiom.
Separation
A X I O M 3 : Pasch’s Separation Axiom for a Line
Given a line L in the plane, the points in the plane that are not on L form two
non-Empty sets, H1 and H2 , called half-planes, so:
(a) If A and B are points in the same half-plane, then AB lies wholly in that
half-plane.
(b) If A and B are points not in the same half-plane, then AB intersects L.
H1 and H2 are also called sides of L L is called the boundary line of H1 and H2 .
Notice that the half-planes mentioned in Pasch’s axiom do not contain their
boundary line. For this reason they are sometimes referred to as open half-planes.
DEFINITION
Let A B, and C be three noncollinear points, as in Figure 1.12. Let HB be the half-plane
←−→ ←−→
determined by AC that contains B. Let HC be the half-plane determined by AB that
contains C. The inside, or interior, of ∠BAC is defined to be HB ∩ HC .
Pasch’s axiom was only added to the axiom set for Euclidean geometry in the late
nineteenth century, when geometers became aware that, for many geometric figures,
there was no way to rigorously define the inside or outside of the figure, much less
prove theorems about the insides and outsides. For example, if you had asked Euclid
to prove that if a line contains a point on the inside of an angle, then it must cross
at least one of the rays making the angle, he would have been unable to do so. He
would undoubtedly have been unconcerned about this, thinking this theorem to be
too obvious to bother with.
* T H E O R E M 1.6
−
→
If a ray AB has endpoint A on line L, but B does not lie on L, then all points of the
ray, except for A, lie on the same side of L as B.
PROOF
The proof is indirect. Assume there is a point C on the ray so that C and B are on
opposite sides of L. By Pasch’s axiom, BC crosses L at some point. This must be A,
←−→ ←−→
since BC ⊂ AB and, by Theorem 1.1, AB crosses L in just one point, namely, A. Since
A is not B or C, the fact that A is in BC means B-A-C. But this means C is not in
−
→
AB, by the definition of a ray.
Triangles play a starring role in geometry, and now it is time to define them. Let
A B C be three points that are not collinear. In that case, we define the triangle ABC
to be AB ∪ BC ∪ AC. Can you see how to define the interior of a triangle?
Suppose we have a triangle ABC and we extend side AC to D, thereby creating
an exterior angle ∠BCD as in Figure 1.13. Pick any point M on BC that is not B or
C, and then extend AM past M to a point E. Will E be on the inside of the exterior
Figure 1.13
1.3 AXIOMS FOR EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY 29
angle ∠BCD? Our visual intuition says yes. But if we want the highest degree of rigor,
we need a proof. Here it is, but with reasons for some steps left out for you to supply.
* T H E O R E M 1.7
If A B, and C are not collinear and
1. A-C-D
2. B-M-C
3. A-M-E
PROOF
According to our definition of the interior of an angle, we need to show two things:
←−→
(a) that E is on the same side as D of line BC, and
←−→
(b) that E is on the same side as B of line CD.
←−→
(a) A and D are on opposite sides of BC . (Why?) A and E are on opposite
←−→
sides of BC . (Why?) Thus, we have shown both E and D to be on the
←−→
opposite side from A of line BC . Therefore, E and D must be on the
←−→
same side of BC , as we wished to prove.
←−→ ←−→ ←−→ ←−→
(b) By hypothesis, B is not on AC, so B is not on CD since AC and CD are the
←−→
same line. Thus, by the previous theorem, CB lies wholly on the B side of
←−→ ←−→
CD (except for C). But B-M-C means M is on CB , and so M and B lie
←−→ ←−→
on the same side of CD. Likewise, E and M lie on the same side of AC.
←−→
Thus, E and B lie on the same side of CD, as we wished to prove.
DEFINITION
If m∠BAC = m∠PQR, then we say ∠BAC and ∠PQR are congruent angles.
DEFINITION
←−→
If A-B-C, and D is any point not on line AC, then ∠ABD and ∠DBC are called
supplementary (Figure 1.14a).
Now consider two lines crossing at X, making four angles as in Figure 1.14b. Each
angle has two neighboring supplementary angles and one that is “across” from it.
Figure 1.14 (a) Supplementary angles: + = 180 . (b) ∠AXB and ∠A XB are vertical
angles; ∠BXA and ∠B XA are vertical angles.