Thought Experiment Entry
Thought Experiment Entry
CONTENTS
What are thought experiments? Philosophical and empirical theories of thought
Kinds of thought experiments experimental cognition
Uses of thought experiments in philosophical cognitive Controversies and issues regarding the use of thought
science experiments
Thought experiment: to perform a thought experi- programmed computer might manifest under-
ment is to reason about an imaginary scenario with standing, Searle asks his reader to consider
the aim of confirming or disconfirming some whether a person locked in a room with a sheaf of
hypothesis or theory. Chinese characters and a set of instructions enab-
ling her to select certain batches of characters
(`answers') when prompted by certain other
WHAT ARE THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS? batches of characters (`questions') would be pro-
To perform a thought experiment is to reason about perly credited with understanding Chinese. (Searle
an imaginary scenario with the aim of confirming expects his reader to give a negative answer.) Other
or disconfirming some hypothesis or theory. In its examples are presented and discussed below.
original usage, the expression was reserved for Although Ernst Mach is generally credited with
cases intended to evoke intuitions about the phys- having coined the expression Gedankenexperiment in
ical world; more recently, it has also been used to his 1897 essay of the same name, and although
refer to cases intended to evoke intuitions concern- contemporary German, English, and French usage
ing the proper application of nearly any descriptive can be traced to Mach's writings, the expression
or evaluative concept. Gedankenexperiment appears in the Danish Kantian
So, for instance, Galileo's famous refutation of Hans Christian OÈ rsted's 1811 `Prolegomenon to the
the Aristotelian view that heavy bodies fall faster General Theory of Nature', and a term for experi-
than light ones is a paradigmatic example of a ment with thoughts ± mit Gedanken experimentieren ±
scientific thought experiment concerning the phys- can be found in a 1793 entry to German polymath
ical world. Galileo asks his reader to imagine a Georg Christoph Lichtenberg's `Common Place
heavier body strapped to a lighter one, and shows Book' (cf. Lichtenberg, 1793/1983; Mach, 1897;
that the Aristotelian is committed to saying that the Mach, 1905/1976; Schildknecht, 1990, pp. 147ff;
joined object will fall both faster and more slowly Witt-Hansen, 1976).
than the heavier body alone. By contrast, John In any case, use of the method antedated its
Searle's (1980, 1984) case of the Chinese Room is a labeling by several thousand years, having been
classic example of a philosophical thought experi- employed by ancient and medieval philosophers
ment concerning the application of our concepts. In and natural philosophers, and by scientists and phil-
an effort to undermine the thesis that a suitably osophers in the early modern and contemporary
Thought Experiments 389
periods (for representative discussions, see happen in a given imaginary scenario assuming
Rescher, 1991; King, 1991; and other papers col- that natural laws are held constant; the latter in-
lected in Horowitz and Massey, 1991). After the volve asking the reader to decide whether a par-
publication of Mach's 1897 essay, the term itself ticular scenario is logically or metaphysically
seems to have taken roughly four decades to possible, or whether a given concept applies to
become widespread in scientific circles. (Despite such a scenario. Bealer maintains that the term
his extensive reading of Mach, for instance, Ein- `thought experiment' should be reserved for cases
stein appears not to have used the expression in of the former sort, roughly the class generally re-
his own writings. In general, however, it is difficult ferred to as `scientific thought experiments'. Tamar
to trace reliably the term's history, as later editions Szabo Gendler (2000, pp. 25±27) suggests a slightly
of works often interpolate it where it was not ori- different taxonomy, distinguishing between factive
ginally used.) Employment of the expression and conceptual/valuational thought experiments.
`thought experiment' in its philosophical sense Factive thought experiments are those where the
seems to have begun sometime in the 1970s, and it question asked is naturally described as `what
was only in the last decade of the twentieth century would happen?'; conceptual/valuational thought
that philosophical reference works began to in- experiments are those where the question asked
clude entries for the term. (For an extensive bibli- is naturally described as `how should we describe
ography of the philosophical literature on thought or evaluate this outcome?' Thought experiments
experiment, see Gendler, 2000, pp. 229±250.) that are factive tend to be those involving scientific
Given how broadly the term is used, it seems that subject matter; thought experiments that are con-
nearly any imaginary example might reasonably be ceptual/valuational tend to be those involving
termed a `thought experiment'. As a matter of philosophical subject matter.
sociological fact, however, the expression tends to James Robert Brown (1991) provides a taxonomy
be reserved for cases involving a certain degree of of scientific thought experiments that has gained
visualization, complexity, or novelty. So, for in- some currency in certain philosophy of science
stance, although they describe imaginary scenarios circles. Brown distinguishes between destructive
whose consideration may play some role in con- and constructive thought experiments, subdividing
firming or disconfirming some hypothesis or the latter category into mediative, conjectural, and
theory, simple examples in physics books (`a direct. Destructive thought experiments are those
car travelling at 65 miles per hour strikes a con- involving imaginary examples designed to raise
crete wall ¼') are rarely considered material for difficulties for a particular theory; constructive
thought experiments, nor are their equally austere thought experiments are those aimed at establish-
analogs in philosophy, psychology, linguistics, law, ing a positive result. Within the class of con-
and so on. structive thought experiments, mediative thought
experiments are those which facilitate the drawing
of a conclusion from a specific, well-articulated
KINDS OF THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS theory; conjectural thought experiments are those
Although a number of taxonomies for thought ex- where thinking about an imaginary scenario causes
periments have been proposed, none has become us to consider a phenomenon for which we then
canonical. Perhaps the most widely accepted dis- provide some sort of theoretical explanation; direct
tinction is between scientific and philosophical thought experiments are those that directly yield
thought experiments, though these categories are a well-established theory. Thought experiments
rarely made precise: scientific thought experi- that are simultaneously destructive and direct-
ments are simply those concerning scientific constructive Brown calls platonic, since, he claims,
subject matter, philosophical thought experiments they give us a priori knowledge of nature.
those concerning nonscientific subject matter Other taxonomies have also been proposed,
(cf., for instance, Horowitz and Massey, 1991; though like those described above, none has gained
Sorensen, 1992). canonical status. Nicholas Rescher (1991), for in-
A more sharply focused version of the scientific/ stance, distinguishes between thought experiments
nonscientific distinction is made by George Bealer that are explanatory and those that are refutatory,
(1998, pp. 207±208), who distinguishes imaginary offering further subdivisions into six more
cases that are used to evoke physical intuitions precisely articulated methods. Sarah Thomason
from those used to evoke intuitions about the ap- (1991) divides thought experiments in linguistics
plication of nonphysical concepts. The former in- into two categories: those that identify what sort
volve asking the reader to determine what would of evidence might be conclusive in testing a
390 Thought Experiments
particular theory, and those that test linguistic vision. Jackson asks what would happen if Mary
hypotheses by providing introspective data (these were released from her confinement and shown
might be called `experiments-in-thought'). D. A. a red object: would Mary learn anything new?
Anapolitanos (1991) offers a six-celled taxonomy Jackson (1982) expects his reader to agree that the
of thought experiments in mathematics; Richard answer is `yes', and concludes that what Mary has
Gale (1991) distinguishes thought experiments learned when she has learned what it is like to see
that yield clear-cut counterexamples from those red is a nonphysical fact.
that result in undecideable cases; Allen Janis
(1991) distinguishes three ways in which thought
Parfit's Fission Case
experiments in physics might fail; Roy Sorensen
(1992, pp. 197±202) classifies thought experi- In an effort to undermine the view that personal
ments on the basis of whether the corresponding identity is what properly underlies our concern for
actual experiment is gratuitous, unaffordable, or our future continuants, Derek Parfit (1984/1987)
impossible; Pierre Duhem (1914/1954, p. 202) simi- discusses a pair of cases involving brain transplants
larly distinguishes merely unperformed experi- from an individual in whom all cognitively rele-
ments, experiments which could not be performed vant features are realized in duplicate ± once in the
with precision, physically unperformable experi- left half of the brain, and once in the right. In the
ments, and absurd experiments; and SoÈren HaÈggq- first scenario, the left half of the original person's
vist (1996, pp. 136±159) and Kathleen Wilkes brain is transplanted into the body of his decere-
(1988, chap. 1) each present principles for distin- brated identical triplet, resulting in an individual
guishing successful from unsuccessful thought qualitatively identical to the original in all bodily
experiments. and psychological characteristics, while the right
half of the original brain is destroyed. In the second
scenario, both the left and right halves of the brain
USES OF THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS IN
of the original individual are transplanted, each
PHILOSOPHICAL COGNITIVE SCIENCE into the decerebrated body of one of his identical
In the cognitive science literature, the term `thought triplets, resulting in two individuals each qualita-
experiment' is generally used to refer to some tively identical to the original in all bodily and
widely discussed imaginary case designed to psychological characteristics. Parfit suggests that
evoke intuitions about the proper application of a the relation between the original individual and
concept such as `meaning' or `consciousness'. So, his successor in the first case is a relation of per-
for instance, among the cases generally referred to sonal identity, and a fortiori is sufficient to render
as `thought experiments' are Frank Jackson's case his prudential concern for that continuer rational.
of Mary the Color Scientist, Derek Parfit's case of In the second case, the relation between the original
fission, Hilary Putnam's case of Twin Earth, and individual and each of his two continuers is intrin-
John Searle's case of the Chinese Room. For what- sically identical to that in the first case; hence,
ever reason, discussions of zombies and inverted contends Parfit, it is sufficient to render prudent-
spectra are less commonly referred to as `thought ial concern for each of them rational. But a relation
experiments', though slight variations on them, of identity does not hold between the original indi-
such as Ned Block's case of inverted Earth, gener- vidual and both of his two continuers (since iden-
ally are. Each of these cases is described briefly tity is a one±one relation). So, concludes Parfit,
below, followed by a discussion of some of their identity is not what matters in making prudential
common features. concern rational.
one on Earth named Oscar, and his molecule-for- described; (b) an intuition concerning the scenario
molecule Twin-Earth duplicate Twin-Oscar. Put- is presented with the assumption that it will be
nam holds that when Oscar says water he refers endorsed, or some argument is presented for why
to water (that is, H2O), but that when Twin-Oscar a particular evaluation of the scenario is correct;
says water he refers to twin-water (that is, XYZ). and (c) this intuition or evaluation is then taken as
So, concludes Putnam, reference is at least partly a datum in understanding something about cases
determined by physical environment. (See also beyond the scenario. So, for instance, in the case of
Burge, 1979 for a number of parallel cases). (See Twin Earth, the imaginary scenario described
Externalism) posits the existence of the planet on which some-
thing qualitatively identical to water has the chem-
ical structure XYZ; the intuition Putnam expects
Searle's Chinese Room
the scenario to evoke is that speakers of English
See the description in opening section. and speakers of Twin-English refer to something
different by their use of the word water; and the
larger lesson is that `meanings [or at least reference]
Zombies ain't just in the head' (Putnam, 1975, p. 227, italics
In an effort to bring out certain issues related to the omitted). In the case of fission, the imaginary scen-
nature of conscious experience and the plausibility ario posits a pair of cases where the relations
of physicalism, numerous philosophers have dis- between the earlier and later individual(s) are
cussed the case of zombies, beings molecule-for- qualitatively indistinguishable, but differ in their
molecule identical to human beings but who lack identity properties; Parfit's arguments aim to show
all conscious experience (cf. Kirk, 1974; Dennett, that this gives us a case where prudential concern
1991; Chalmers, 1996). On the basis of such cases, for a nonidentical continuer is rational; the larger
some have concluded that consciousness cannot be lesson is that `personal identity is not what matters'
fully explained in physical terms. (Parfit 1984/1987, p. 255, italics omitted).
Challenges to particular thought experiments
may come at any of these three levels: (a0 ) inco-
Inverted Spectrum and Inverted Earth
herence criticisms: the scenario described is in
In an effort to illuminate various issues relating some sense incoherent; (b0 ) misleading intuition/
to the status of qualia, materialism, behaviorism unsound argument criticisms: although the scen-
and consciousness, numerous philosophers have ario described is coherent, the intuition it generates
employed a case first introduced by John Locke is unreliable or the argument establishing the cor-
(1689/1975 at II:XXXII:15). In its simplest form, rect evaluation of the scenario is unsound; or (c0 )
the Inverted Spectrum example hypothesizes an inapplicability criticisms: although the scenario de-
individual whose visual experience on seeing, scribed is coherent and the evaluation of the scen-
say, yellow is qualitatively identical to the visual ario correct, the conclusion drawn on its basis is
experience of a normal person seeing, say, blue. mistaken. So, for example, some have argued (a0 )
Variations on the case abound. For instance, in that fission is biologically or physically or concep-
arguing against certain representationalist and tually impossible; others (b0 ) that though the scen-
functionalist accounts of qualia, Ned Block (1990) ario described is coherent, it does not present us
introduces the example of Inverted Earth, a planet with a case where someone would bear a relation of
whose colors are inverted, so that grass on Inverted rational prudential concern to a nonidentical con-
Earth is red and the sky on Inverted Earth is yellow. tinuer; and others (c0 ) that though the scenario pre-
A person is transported to Inverted Earth, and sents a case where someone would bear a relation
given color-inverting contact lenses that cause of rational prudential concern to a nonidentical
everything on Inverted Earth to appear to her to continuer, this does not show that identity is not
be normally colored (cf. also Shoemaker, 1982; what matters for rational prudential concern in
Chalmers, 1996). (See Functionalism; Materialism; ordinary cases.
Qualia)
PHILOSOPHICAL AND EMPIRICAL
Discussion of Common Features of THEORIES OF THOUGHT
the Above EXPERIMENTAL COGNITION
Appellation notwithstanding, such cases tend to Perhaps the most perplexing question raised by the
share the following features: (a) a scenario is technique of thought experiment is the epistemic
392 Thought Experiments
indeterminate in their application when we con- Burge T (1979) Individualism and the mental. In: French
sider such bizarre cases. Others have offered paral- P et al. (eds) Midwest Studies in Philosophy: Studies in
lel arguments from a Wittgensteinian perspective Metaphysics, pp. 73±122. Minneapolis, MN: University
(e.g. Gale, 1991). of Minnesota Press.
Chalmers D (1996) The Conscious Mind. New York and
In recent years, two other areas of related interest
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
have begun to be explored, both of which raise Dancy J (1985) The role of imaginary cases in ethics.
concerns for the reliability of thought experiment Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 66: 141±153.
as a methodology. As before, the implications of Dennett D (1984) Elbow Room. Cambridge, MA: MIT
these investigations will need to be considered on a Press.
case-by-case basis. Following the work of psycholo- Dennett D (1991) Consciousness Explained. Boston, MA:
gists such as Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tverksy, Little, Brown.
demonstrating that human reasoning is, in a wide DePaul MR and Ramsey W(eds) (1998) Rethinking
range of cases, subject to apparently intractable Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and its Role in
cognitive illusions, a number of philosophers and Philosophical Inquiry. Lanham, MD: Rowman and
psychologists have begun to consider whether in- Littlefield.
Duhem P (1914/1954) The Aim and Structure of Physical
tuition itself is reliable in the ways that thought
Theory, translated by P Wiener. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
experimental reasoning seems to presuppose (see, University Press.
for instance, the papers collected in DePaul and Gale R (1991) On some pernicious thought experiments.
Ramsey, 1998). In a related vein, though for reasons In: Horowitz and Massey (eds) Thought Experiments in
arising from a concern with the nature of modality Science and Philosophy, pp. 297±304. Savage, MD:
and the relation between epistemology and meta- Rowman and Littlefield.
physics, a number of philosophers have begun Gendler TS (2000) Thought Experiment: On the Powers and
to rethink the relation between conceivability and Limits of Imaginary Cases. New York, NY: Garland Press.
possibility (see, for instance, papers collected in Gendler TS and Hawthorne JP (eds) (forthcoming)
Gendler and Hawthorne, forthcoming). If, as some Imagination, Conceivability, and Possibility. Oxford, UK:
suggest, what we can conceive (or fail to conceive) Oxford University Press.
Gooding DC (1992) The cognitive turn, or, why do
is unreliable as a guide to what is genuinely pos-
thought experiments work? In: Giere R (ed.) Cognitive
sible, or if we lack a reliable sense of what we are Models of Science, pp. 45±76. Minneapolis, MN:
capable of conceiving, then reasoning about im- University of Minnesota Press.
aginary scenarios may be an ineffective means of HaÈggqvist S (1996) Thought Experiments in Philosophy.
confirming or disconfirming certain hypotheses Stockholm, Sweden: Almqvist and Wiksell.
or theories. Horowitz T and Massey G (eds) (1991) Thought
Experiments in Science and Philosophy. Savage, MD:
Rowman and Littlefield.
References
Janis AI (1991) Can thought experiments fail? In: Horowitz
Anapolitanos DA (1991) Thought experiments and and Massey (eds) Thought Experiments in Science and
conceivability conditions in mathematics. In: Horowitz Philosophy, pp. 113±118. Savage, MD: Rowman and
and Massey (eds) Thought Experiments in Science and Littlefield.
Philosophy, pp. 87±97. Savage, MD: Rowman and King P (1991) Mediaeval thought-experiments: the
Littlefield. metamethodology of mediaeval science. In: Horowitz
Arthur R (1999) On thought experiments as a priori and Massey (eds), pp. 43±64.
science. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science Kirk R (1974) Zombies vs. materialists. Proceedings of the
13(3): 215±229. Aristotelian Society 48 (supplement): pp. 135±152.
Bealer G (1998) Intuition and the autonomy of Kuhn T (1964/1977) A function for thought experiments.
philosophy. In: DePaul M and Ramsey W (eds) Reprinted in The Essential Tension. Chicago, IL:
Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and its University of Chicago Press.
Role in Philosophical Inquiry. New York: Rowman and Jackson F (1982) Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical
Littlefield. Quarterly 32: 127±136.
Block N (1990) Inverted Earth. Philosophical Perspectives 4: Lichtenberg GC (1983) Schriften und Briefe: SudelbuÈcher,
53±79. Fragmente, Fabeln, Verse (Erster Band) (ed.) FH Mautner.
Bohr N (1949) Discussions with Einstein on Frankfurt, Germany: Insel Verlag.
epistemological problems in atomic physics. In: Locke J (1689/1975) An Essay Concerning Human
Schilpp PA (ed.) Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, Understanding (ed.) PH Nidditch. New York, NY:
pp. 199±242. La Salle, IL: Open Court. Oxford University Press.
Brown JR (1991) The Laboratory of the Mind: Thought Mach E (1897) U È ber Gedankenexperimente. Poskes
Experiments in the Natural Sciences. New York and Zeitschrift fuÈr den physikalischen und chemischen
London: Routledge. Unterricht, January 1897, pp. 1±5.
394 Thought Experiments
Mach E (1905/1976) U È ber Gedankenexperimente. Searle J (1984) Minds, Brains and Science. Cambridge, MA:
Erkenntnis und Irrtum, Leipzig, 1905, pp. 183±199. Harvard University Press.
Reprinted as: On thought experiment. Knowledge and Shoemaker S (1982) The inverted spectrum. Journal of
Error (translation of 1926 edition of Erkenntnis und Philosophy 79(7): 357±381.
Irrtum by TJ McCormack and P Foulkes). Dordrecht, the Sorensen R (1992) Thought Experiments. New York and
Netherlands: Reidel, 1976, pp. 134±147. London: Oxford University Press.
Mach E (1933/1960) The Science of Mechanics, 9th edn, Thomason S (1991) Thought experiments in linguistics.
translated by T McCormack. La Salle, IL: Open Court In: Horowitz and Massey (eds) Thought Experiments in
Publishers. Science and Philosophy, pp. 247±257. Savage, MD:
Miscevic N (1992) Mental models and thought Rowman and Littlefield.
experiments. International Studies in the Philosophy of Wilkes K (1988) Real People: Personal Identity without
Science 6(3): 215±226. Thought Experiments. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
Nersessian N (1993) In the theoretician's laboratory: Witt-Hansen J (1976) H.C. O È rsted, Immanuel Kant, and
thought experiment as mental modeling. Proceedings of the thought experiment. Danish Yearbook of Philosophy
the Philosophy of Science Association, vol. 2, pp. 291±301. 13: 48±65.
Norton J (1991) Thought experiments in Einstein's work.
In: Horowitz and Massey (eds) Thought Experiments in Further Reading
Science and Philosophy, pp. 129±148. Savage, MD:
Rowman and Littlefield. Bunzl M (1996) The logic of thought experiments.
Norton J (1996) Are thought experiments just what you Synthese 106(2): 227±240.
thought? Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26(3): 333±366. Cargile J (1987) Definitions and counterexamples.
Parfit D (1984/1987) Reasons and Persons. Oxford, UK: Philosophy 62: 179±193.
Oxford University Press. Fodor JA (1971) On knowing what we would say. In:
Putnam H (1975) The Meaning of `Meaning'. Reprinted Rosenberg JF and Travis C (eds) Readings in the
in Mind, Language and Reality: Collected Papers Volume 2, Philosophy of Language, pp. 198±212. Englewood Cliffs,
pp. 215±271. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Press. Gentner D and Stevens AL (eds) (1983) Mental Models.
Quine WVO (1972) Review of Identity and Individuation. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Journal of Philosophy 69(16): 488±497. Giere R (ed.) (1992) Cognitive Models of Science.
Rescher N (1991) Thought experiments in pre-Socratic Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
philosophy. In: Horowitz and Massey (eds) Thought Hintikka J (1999) The emperor's new intuitions. Journal of
Experiments in Science and Philosophy, pp. 31±41. Savage, Philosophy 96(3): 127±147.
MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Miller FD and Smith N (eds) (1989) Thought Probes:
Schildknecht C (1990) Philosophische Masken: Literarische Philosophy through Science Fiction Literature. Englewood
Formen der Philosophie bei Platon, Descartes, Wolff und Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Lichtenberg. Stuttgart, Germany: Metzler. Popper K (1959) On the use and misuse of
Searle J (1980) Minds, brains and programs. Behavioral imaginary experiments, especially in quantum
and Brain Sciences 3: pp. 417±424. [Peer commentary, theory. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York:
pp. 425±449; reply by Searle, pp. 450±456. Basic Books.