MC and Jehle Partial Sol Manual PDF
MC and Jehle Partial Sol Manual PDF
Jianfei Shen
Part
Part 1. Consum
Consumer
er Theory
Theory 1
Chapter 1. Solution for Exercise I 3
1. (JR, 1.4) 3
2. (JR, 1.27) 3
3. (JR, 1.56) 4
4. (JR, 1.24) 5
5. (Homogeneity) 6
Chapter 2. Solution for Exercise II 9
1. (JR, 1.36) 9
2. (JR, 2.10) 9
3. (MWG, 2.F.7) 10
4. (JR, 1.62) 11
5. (JR, 2.9) 11
Part
Part 2. Production
Production and Choice under Uncert
Uncertaint
ainty
y 13
Chapter 3. Solution for Exercise III 15
1. (JR, 3.36) 15
2. (JR, 3.39) 16
3. (The Allais Paradox) 17
4. (The Simplex) 18
5. (Independence Axiom) 19
Chapter 4. Solution for Exercise IV 21
1. (MWG, 6.C.16) 21
2. (MWG, 6.C.20) 22
3. (Betweenness Axiom) 23
4. (Quadratic v.N-M Utility Function) 24
i
Part 1
Consumer Theory
CHAPTER 1
1. (JR, 1.4)
L
Proof. Suppose that x,y,z ∈ R + , and x y, y z. By Definition 1.21,
we have
(1.1) x y ⇔ x y ∧ y x;
and
(1.2) y z ⇔ y z ∧ z y.
The transitivity implies that x z. Suppose that z x. Since y z [by equation
(1.2)], the transitivity then implies that y x. But this contradicts (1.1). Thus
z x. Hence
x z.
Suppose x ∼ y, and y ∼ z. By Definition 1.3 2, we have
(1.3) x ∼ y ⇔ x y ∧ y x;
and
(1.4) y ∼ z ⇔ y z ∧ z y.
The transitivity implies that
xz and z x.
Hence
x ∼ z.
2. (JR, 1.27)
Solution. If x 1 < x2 ,
u(x) = max[ax1 , ax2 ] + min[x1 , x2 ] = ax 2 + x1 ;
If x 2 < x1 ,
u(x) = max[ax1 , ax2 ] + min[x1 , x2 ] = ax 1 + x2 .
p1
Case i: a < p2
< a1 . In this case,
w
x1 = x 2 = .
p1 + p2
1Jehle & Reny, 2001, P6
2Jehle & Reny, 2001, P7
3
4 1. SOLUTION FOR EXERCISE I
x2
C
O B x1
p1
Case ii: p2
> a1 . In this case, there is a corner solution
w
x1 = 0, x2 = .
p2
p1
Case iii: p2
< a. In this case, there is a corner solution, too
w
x1 = , x2 = 0.
p1
p1
Case iv: p2
= a1 . In this case, the UMP is
x1 =
w − p2 x2
, x2 ∈
w
,
w
.
p1 p1 + p2 p2
p1
Case v: p2
= a. In this case, the UMP is
x1 =
w − p2 x2
, x2 ∈ 0,
w
.
p1 p1 + p2
3. (JR, 1.56)
Solution. Use the monotone transformation of the given utility function 3:
n
v(x) = ln u(x) = bi ln(xi − ai ).
i=1
3Stone, J.E. (1954): Linear Expenditure Systems and Demand Analysis: An Application to
the Pattern of British Demand. Economic Journal 64: 511–27
4. (JR, 1.24) 5
4. (JR, 1.24)
Solution. A utility function that represents a preference relation is not
unique. For any strictly increasing function : f : R → R , v(x) = f (u(x)) is a new
utility function representing the same preferences as u(·)4.
a: f (x) = u(x) + [u(x)]2 .
∂f (·)
= 1 + 3[u(x)]2 > 0.
∂u(·)
So this is a strictly increasing function, and it represents the same .
b: f (x) = u(x) + [u(x)]2 .
∂f (·)
= 1 + 2u(x).
∂u(·)
∂f (·)
• ≤ 0 if u(x) ≤ − 12 . In this case, f (x) does not represents the
∂u (·)
same ;
(·)
• ∂f
∂u (·)
> 0 if u(x) > − 12 . In this case, f (x) represents the same .
c: f (x) = u(x) + ni=1 xi .
Not necessarily. f represents the same preferences as u if u(x) is a
n
monotonic transformation of i=1 xi . Otherwise, they may not represent
the same preferences. For example, suppose u(x) = x1 . Then
u(1, 0, . . . , 0) > u(0, 3, 0, . . . , 0),
but
f (1, 0, . . . , 0) = 1 + 1 = 2 < 3 = 0 + 3 = f (0, 3, 0, . . . , 0).
4Let x, y ∈ R L . Since u(·) represents , x y iff u (x) ≥ u(y ). Since f (·) is strictly
+
increasing, u (x) ≥ u (y ) iff v (x) ≥ v (y). Hence x y iff v (x) ≥ v (y ). Therefore v (·) represents .
This completes the proof.
6 1. SOLUTION FOR EXERCISE I
5. (Homogeneity)
L L
Proof. a: We want to show that ∀ p ∈ R ++ , y ≥ 0, α ≥ 0, and x ∈ R + , if x
is the Marshallian demand at ( p, y), then x = αx is the Marshallian demand at
( p, αy). We’ll complete this proof with two steps:
Step I: we prove that the consumption bundle x is affordable at ( p, αy).
1. (JR, 1.36)
Solution. a. By definition,
e( p, u) min p · x
L
x∈R+
s.t. u(x) ≥ u
The solution to the EMP is known as the Hicksian demand function : h( p, u). Hence
u(x0 ) ≥ u 0 ,
and so
e( p, u0 ) ≤ p · x0 ,
with the equality sign holds when p = p 0 .
b. It follows immediately from part a that
f ( p) = e( p, u) − p · x0
is maximized at p = p0 :
max f ( p) = 0.
c. If f ( p) is differentiable at p 0 ,
∇ p f p0 = 0.
(2.1)
d. If e( p, u) is differentiable in p, then by equation (2.1) we have
∇ p f = ∇ p e − x0 = 0,
so
h( p, u) = ∇ p e( p, u).
2. (JR, 2.10)
Solution. a.
Bundle
0
x x1 x2
p0 42 48 40∗
Price p1 33∗ 36 39(∗)
p2 52 48∗ 51
9
10 2. SOLUTION FOR EXERCISE II
These consumption bundles are plausible in that the WARP is satisfied. In partic-
ular, we note
p1 x1 = 36 > 33 = p1 x0 ,
p0 x0 = 42 < 48 = p0 x1 ,
so
(2.2) x1 R x0 .
p0 x0 = 42 > 40 = p0 x2 ,
p2 x2 = 50 < 52 = p2 x0 ,
so
(2.3) x0 R x2 .
p2 x2 = 50 > 48 = p2 x1 ,
p1 x1 = 36 < 39 = p1 x2 ,
so
(2.4) x2 R x1 .
b. Now, from (2.2) and (2.3) we have
x1 R x0 , x0 R x2 ;
but from (2.4), something utterly revolting occurs:
x2 R x1 .
So the revealed preference R is intransitivity .
3. (MWG, 2.F.7)
Proof. If the Walrasian demand function x( p, w) satisfies Walras’ law, then
for all p and w:
L
∂x ( p, w)
(2.5) p + xk ( p, w) = 0, ∀ k = 1, . . . , L ,
∂p k
=1
or
(2.6) p · D p x( p, w) + x( p, w) = 0
and
L
∂x ( p, w)
(2.7) p = 1,
∂w
=1
or
(2.8) p · Dw x( p, w) = 1.
If the Walrasian demand function x( p, w) is h.o.d. 0, then for all p and w:
L
∂x ( p, w) ∂ x ( p, w)
(2.9) pk + w = 0, ∀ = 1, . . . , L ,
∂p k ∂w
k=1
or
(2.10) D p x( p, w) p + Dw x( p, w)w = 0.
5. (JR, 2.9) 11
4. (JR, 1.62)
Solution. Since
p · S ( p, w) = 0,
S ( p, w) p = 0
and by symmetric, we have
a = − 8, b = 2, p = 32.
5. (JR, 2.9)
Proof. a. In the case of two goods, equation (2.13) can be written as
p · S ( p, w) = p1 p2
s11 ( p, w) s12 ( p, w)
s21 ( p, w) s22 ( p, w)
(2.15)
= p1 s11 ( p, w) + p2 s21 ( p, w) p1 s12 ( p, w) + p2 s22 ( p, w)
= 0 0 .
From equation (2.15) we have
p1
s21 ( p, w) = − s11 ( p, w),
p2
12 2. SOLUTION FOR EXERCISE II
and
p2
s12 ( p, w) = − s22 ( p, w).
p1
And the equation (2.14) becomes
s ( p, w) s12 ( p, w)
S ( p, w) p = 11
p1
s21 ( p, w) s22 ( p, w) p2
(2.16) =
p1 s11 ( p, w) + p2 s12 ( p, w)
p1 s21 ( p, w) + p2 s22 ( p, w)
=
0
.
0
From equation (2.16) we have
p1
s12 ( p, w) = − s11 ( p, w),
p2
and
p2
s21 ( p, w) = − s22 ( p, w).
p1
Thus
s12 ( p, w) = s 21 ( p, w).
Part 2
1. (JR, 3.36)
Proof. We can get some intuition from the following figure 1.
x2
tx02 B
x02 y1
A
y0
O x01 tx01 x1
Now we give the regular proof. The cost function for all homothetic production
function can be written
(3.1) c(w, y) = h(y)φ(w),
where φ(w) is linear homogeneous. 1
Then using the Shephard’s Lemma 2, we have
∂c(w, y)
xi (w, y) = = h(y)φi (w),
∂w i
∂c(w, y)
xj (w, y) = = h(y)φj (w).
∂w j
Hence
xi (w, y) φi ( w )
(3.2) = ψ(w),
xj (w, y) φj (w)
that is,
∂ (xi (w, y)/xj (w, y))
= 0.
∂y
1Any cost function is linear homogeneous in the factor prices.
2JR, Theorem 3.2, p.129
15
16 3. SOLUTION FOR EXERCISE III
2. (JR, 3.39)
Proof. a: If the production function is CRS, then
n
c(w, y) = wi xi (w, y)
i=1
n
= λf i xi (w, y) [ From the F.O.C. ]
i=1
n
= λ xi (w, y) f i
i=1
= λy [ From the Euler Equation ]
∂c(w, y)
= y [ By the interpretation of λ ]
∂y
or
∂c(w, y) ∂y
(3.3) = .
c(w, y) y
Solve the partial differential equation (3.3), we get
(3.4) c(w, y) = yφ(w),
where φ(w) is a function of factor prices w only.
b: If c(w, y) = yφ(w), then from the F.O.C. of the cost minimization problem
that for ∀ x(w, y) > 0
(3.5) wi = λf i ,
and
∂c(w, y)
(3.6) λ =
.
∂y
Combine equation (3.5) and (3.6), we obtain
wi = φ(w)f i ,
or
wi xi
xi f i = .
φ(w)
Hence, for all x i (w, y)
n n
wi xi
xi f i =
i=1 i=1
φ(w)
n
1
= wi xi
φ(w) i=1
c(w, y)
=
φ(w)
yφ(w)
=
φ(w)
= f (x).
3. (THE ALLAIS PARADOX) 17
p3 p3
g2 g3 g2 g3
g1 p1 g4 1 g1 p1 g4 1
(a) (b)
rf (x) = xi f i .
i=1
18 3. SOLUTION FOR EXERCISE III
g6 =
0.10
◦ 5,
0.01
◦ 0 ;
0.11 0.11
g7 = Get 0 with certainty .
By the Completeness Axiom , we know either g 5 g6 or g 6 g5 .
(1) If g5 g6 : by the IA, we have
0.11g5 + 0.89g5 0.11g6 + 0.89g5 ,
or
g1 g2 ;
and
0.11g5 + 0.89g7 0.11g6 + 0.89g7 ,
or
g4 g3 .
(2) If g6 g5 : we can do the job with the same logic as part (1), and get
g2 g1 ,
and
g3 g4 .
4. (The Simplex)
Solution. The slope: Keeping the level of v.N.M utility constant
p1 u(x1 ) + p2 u(x2 ) + (1 − p1 − p2 )u(x3 ) = Const.,
and varying p 1 and p 2 alone, one has, locally,
dp 2 dp2
u(x1 ) + u(x2 ) + ( −1 − )u(x3 ) = 0,
dp1 dp1
or
dp2 u(x3 ) − u(x1 )
= ≥ 0,
dp1 u(x2 ) − u(x3 )
4In the alternative case of relatively flat indifference curves, the gambles g and g would be
2 3
preferred.
5. (INDEPENDENCE AXIOM) 19
p2
p1 1
Figure 4.1. Expected utility indifference curves in the sim-
plex diagram
5. (Independence Axiom)
Proof. Let us assume without loss of generality that the elements of A have
been indexed so that
a1 a2 · · · an .
Now, let g k , 0 ≤ k ≤ n, be the gamble that yields outcome k with probability
one:
gk = (0 ◦ a1 , 0 ◦ a2 , . . . , 1 ◦ ak , . . . , 0 ◦ an ).
Then
a1 gk an ,
since all of them can be identified with sure outcomes.
Let
g = ( p1 ◦ a1 , . . . , pn ◦ an )
be any gamble in G , then
n
g = pk gk .
k=1
If there is only one k, s.th. pk = 1, that is, pj = 0, ∀ j = n, there is nothing to
prove. So let
N = # {(1, . . . , n) : pk
= 0, 0 ≤ k ≤ n } > 1
20 3. SOLUTION FOR EXERCISE III
a1
pk gk an
k=1
CHAPTER 4
1. (MWG, 6.C.16)
Solution. The maximum amount the person is willing to buy the
gamble:
u(·)
A
u(w)
B
Rb Rb
w−y w w + x w
u(·)
E [u(·)] C
u(w) D
Rs
where C E w−R and C E w are certainty equivalence for (4.1) and (4.2), respectively.
b
thus
Rb = Rs .
2. (MWG, 6.C.20)
Proof.
u(CE ) = 0.5u(x + ε) + 0.5u(x − ε),
where C E is the Certainty Equivalent . Hence
∂C E
(4.5) u (CE ) = 0.5u (x + ε) − 0.5u (x − ε),
∂ε
2
∂ 2 CE
(4.6)
u (CE )
∂C E
+ u (CE ) = 0.5u (x + ε) + 0.5u (x − ε).
∂ε ∂ε 2
Thus
∂CE 2
0.5u (x + ε) + 0.5u (x − ε) − u (CE )
∂ 2 CE
∂ε
lim = lim
ε↓0 ∂ε 2 ε↓0 u (CE )
u (x)
=
u (x)
= − R a (x),
1See MWG (1995) Section 6.C.
3. (BETWEENNESS AXIOM) 23
since
∂C E 0.5u (x + ε) − 0.5u (x − ε)
lim = lim
ε↓0 ∂ε ε↓0 u (CE )
= 0,
and
lim u(CE ) = u(x).
ε↓0
3. (Betweenness Axiom)
Solution. The Betweenness Axiom 2 only requires that indifference sets be
convex , i.e., if an individual is indifferent between two lotteries, then any probability
mixture of these two is equally good: if g ∼ g , then
λg + (1 − λ)g ∼ g, ∀ λ ∈ [0, 1].
Essentially, the betweennss axiom is a substantially weaker version of the contro-
versial independence axiom. 3
The axioms 1-4, 6, and the betweenness axiom means that the indifference
curves are straight lines can be established in the same way as in Chapter 3, exercise
(3). Note that we do not use the independence axiom in that exercise, in fact,
betweenness axiom is suffices.
Note also that these straight indifference curves need not be parallel, because
the betweenness axiom imposes restrictions only on straight indifference curves and
nothing on the relative positions of different indifference curves.
p2
p1 1
Figure 3.1. Betweenness axiom means the indifference curves
are straight lines, but need not be parallel.
2See Dekel, E. (1986) for further discussion.
3See MWG Exercise 6.B.1A .
24 4. SOLUTION FOR EXERCISE IV
The integral on the right-hand side of this equation is a function of .5 If we let
α
6
d.
Then, the individual must be indifferent between g 1 , g 2 , and a compound gamble
Letting µ i and σ i2 denote the mean and variance, respectively, of the distribu-
tions corresponding to the gambles (i = 1, 2, and q ).
6Markowitz (1959) demonstrated that if the ordering of alternatives is to satisfy the v.N-M
axioms of rational behavior, only a quadratic utility function is consistent with an ordinal expected
utility function that depends solely on the mean and variance of the return. Consequently, even
if the return for each alternative has a normal distribution, the mean-variance framework cannot
be used to rank alternatives consistently with the v.N-M axioms unless a quadratic v.N-M utility
function is specified.
7Our proof gives here follows Baron (1977).
26 4. SOLUTION FOR EXERCISE IV
V (µ, σ 2 ) = β
µ2 g2
µq gq
g1
µ1
Note that distribution functions preserve the linear structure of gambles (as do
P.D.F.’s),8 so
µq =
w d qF 1 (w) + (1 − q )F 2 (w)
(4.7)
= q
w dF 1 (w) + (1 − q )
w dF 2 (w)
= qµ 1 + (1 − q )µ2 .
2
σq =
2
w − qµ 1 − (1 − q )µ2 d qF 1 (w) + (1 − q )F 2 (w)
(4.8) =
2
q (w − µ1 ) + (1 − q )(w − µ2 ) d qF 1 (w) + (1 − q )F 2 (w)
= qσ 12 + (1 − q )σ22 + q (1 − q )(µ1 − µ2 )2 .
Solving for q from (4.7) yields
µq − µ2
(4.9) q = .
µ1 − µ2
Substituting (4.9) into (4.8) yields
µ2 µ1 (µ1 − µ2 ) + µ2 σ12 − µ1 σ22
µq −
µ1 − µ2
µ2q + σq2 =
,
µ1 − µ22 + σ12 − σ22
2 µ21 − µ22 + σ12 − σ22
or
µq − α µ2q + σq2 = k,
(4.10)
where
µ1 − µ2
α = ,
µ21 −
µ22 + σ12 − σ22
µ2 µ1 (µ1 − µ2 ) + µ2 σ12 − µ1 σ22
k = .
µ21 − µ22 + σ12 − σ22
8See MWG (1995) p.183.